Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-gvvz8 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-25T07:01:18.797Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Nomological Necessity and the Paradoxes of Confirmation

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  14 March 2022

Brian Skyrms*
Affiliation:
University of Michigan

Abstract

“What might have been is an abstraction Remaining a perpetual possibility Only in the world of speculation.”

T. S. Eliot

Burnt Norton

Some of the concerns which motivate attempts to provide a philosophical reduction of nomological necessity are briefly introduced in I. In II, Hempel's treatment of the paradoxes is contrasted with a position which holds that nomological necessity is a pragmatic dimension of laws of nature, and that this pragmatic dimension is of such a type that it prevents laws of nature from contraposing. Such a position is, however, untenable unless (i) the sense of ‘pragmatics’ at issue is specified, and the possibility of pragmatic differences resulting in differences in confirmation is defended, and (ii) a relevant pragmatic difference between contrapositives is indicated. III attempts to satisfy condition (i) by developing a new sense of pure pragmatics and argues that some remarks by Goodman and Scheffler together with work on the logic of explanation by Dr. Rescher and myself suggest that nomological contrapositives are not pragmatically equivalent (i.e. substitutable salva veritate in the pure pragmatics of an ideal scientific language). If such is the case, condition (ii) is also satisfied.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © 1966 by The Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

[1] Carnap, R., Introduction to Semantics, (Cambridge: Univ. of Harvard Press, 1942), pp. 810.Google Scholar
[2] Carnap, R., Logical Foundations of Probability, 2nd ed. (Chicago: U. of Chicago Press, 1962).Google Scholar
[3] Carnap, R.: Logical Syntax of Language, (Patterson, N. J.: Littlefield, Adams & Co., 1959).Google Scholar
[4] Carnap, R., “Meaning and Synonomy in Natural Languages,” in Meaning and Necessity, 2nd. ed. (Chicago: Univ. of Chicago Press, 1956), p. 233.Google Scholar
[5] Carnap, R., “The Philosopher Replies,” in The Philosophy of Rudolf Carnap, ed. P. A. Schilpp, (La Salle, Ill.: Open Court, 1963).Google Scholar
[6] Chisholm, R., “The Contrary-to-Fact Conditional,” Readings in Philosophical Analysis, ed. Feigl & Sellars, (N.Y.: Appleton-Century Crofts, 1949), pp. 482497.Google Scholar
[7] Goodman, N., Fact Fiction and Forecast, (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard Univ. Press, 1955).Google Scholar
[8] Hempel, C., “A Note on the Paradoxes of Confirmation,” Mind, Vol. LV (1946), pp. 7982.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[9] Hempel, C., “Studies in the Logic of Confirmation,” Mind, Vol. LIV (1945).Google Scholar
[10] Mach, E., The Science of Mechanics (LaSalle, Ill.: Open Court, 1893).Google Scholar
[11] Martin, R., Toward a Systematic Pragmatics, (Amsterdam: N. Holland Publishing Co., 1959).Google Scholar
[12] Morris, C. W., “Foundations of the Theory of Signs,” International Encyclopedia of Unified Science, (Chicago: Univ. of Chicago Press, 1938).Google Scholar
[13] Peirce, C. S., The Collected Papers of C. S. Peirce, V, (Cambridge, Mass.: Belknap Press, 1960).Google Scholar
[14] Reichenbach, H., Nomological Statements and Admissable Operations, (Amsterdam: North Holland Publishing Co., 1954) and Montague, Richard; “Logical Necessity, Ethics and Quantifiers,” Inquiry, Vol. 3 (1960), pp. 259269.Google Scholar
[15] Rescher, Nicholas and Skyrms, Brian, “A Methodological Problem in the Evaluation of Explanations,” University of Pittsburgh Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Vol. III (forthcoming).Google Scholar
[16] Scheffler, I., The Anatomy of Inquiry, (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard Univ. Press, 1963).Google Scholar
[17] Scriven, M., “Explanations, Predictions and Laws,” in Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Vol. III (Minneapolis: U. of Minnesota Press, 1962), pp. 170230.Google Scholar