Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-g8jcs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-27T19:55:32.805Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Macroscopic Objects: An Exercise in Duhemian Ontology

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 April 2022

Paul Needham*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy University of Stockholm
*
Send reprint requests to the author, Department of Philosophy, University of Stockholm, S-106-91 Stockholm, Sweden.

Abstract

Aristotelian ideas are presented in a favorable light in Duhem's historical works surveying the history of the notion of chemical combination (1902) and the development of mechanics (1903). The importance Duhem was later to ascribe to Aristotelian ideas as reflected in the weight he attached to medieval science is well known. But the Aristotelian influence on his own mature philosophical perspective, and more particularly on his concern for logical coherence and the development of his ontological views, is not generally acknowledged. There are, however, clear pointers in this direction in these two earlier books on the history of science, which are unashamedly written in such a way as to project the author's own view of what is important in the relevant areas. Thermodynamics was the pinnacle of Duhemian science, and its interpretation requires the reinstatement, in Duhem's view, of Aristotelian conceptions which have been unfashionable since the rise of certain ideas with the scientific revolution of the seventeenth century.

The present paper is not primarily an exposition of these Aristotelian views of Duhem's, but an attempt to pursue the interpretation of a macroscopic, thermodynamical perspective on chemical substances from an elementary viewpoint in the spirit of Duhem (1902), sometimes being more definite than Duhem seems to be, and occasionally taking issue with him on certain points. Some of his leading ideas will determine the general approach, but views and problems will also be taken from modern textbooks in an attempt to lay down the general lines along which an explicit ontology—in Quine's sense—of macroscopic theory might be developed.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © 1996 by the Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

This paper was presented at the First International Conference on Philosophy of Chemistry, held at the London School of Economics, 26–27 March, 1994. I would like to thank the participants for the discussion and Eric Scerri for bringing us together.

References

Boyle, Robert ([1662] 1899), “A Defence of the Doctrine Touching the Spring and Weight of the Air”, New Physico-Mechanical Experiments, London, 1662; reprinted in Barus, Carl (ed.), The Laws of Gases: Memoirs by Robert Boyle and E. H. Amagat. Harper, New York.Google Scholar
Callen, Herbert B. (1985), Thermodynamics and an Introduction to Thermostatistics, 2nd ed. New York: Wiley.Google Scholar
Denbigh, Kenneth (1981), The Principles of Chemical Equilibrium, 4th ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Duhem, Pierre ([1902] 1985), Le mixte et la combinaison chimique: Essai sur l'évolution d'une idée, Paris: C. Nord: reprinted, Paris: Fayard.Google Scholar
Duhem, Pierre ([1903] 1992), L'Evolution de la Mécanique, Paris: A. Joanin; reprinted, Paris: Vrin.Google Scholar
Gibbs, J. Willard ([1906] 1948), The Collected Works of J. Willard Gibbs, Volume I; reprinted New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Goodman, D. C. (1969), “Wollaston and the Atomic Theory of Dalton”, in McCormmach, Russell C. (ed.), Historical Studies in the Physical Sciences. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.Google Scholar
Huntington, Edvard V. (1913), “A set of postulates for abstract geometry, expressed in terms of the simple relation of inclusion”, Mathematische Annalen 73: 522559.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maxwell, James Clerk, (1890), The Collected Scientific Papers of James Clerk Maxwell, Niven, W. D. (ed.), Vol. II. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Needham, Paul (1981), “Temporal Intervals and Temporal Order”, Logique et Analyse 93: 4964.Google Scholar
Needham, Paul (1996), “Fleeting Things and Permanent Stuff”, in Faye, Jan, Scheffler, Uwe and Urchs, Max (eds.), Perspectives on Time, (forthcoming).Google Scholar
Röper, Peter (1983), “Semantics for Mass Terms With Quantifiers”, Nous 17: 251265.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sharvy, Richard (1983), “Aristotle on Mixtures”, Journal of Philosophy 80: 439457.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tarski, Alfred ([1926] 1983). “Foundations of the Geometry of Solids”, in Logic, Semantics and Metamathematics, (ed. and trans. by Woodger, J. H.). Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.Google Scholar