Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-jn8rn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T03:10:31.888Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Kuhn on Essentialism and the Causal Theory of Reference

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2022

Extract

The causal theory of reference is often taken to provide a solution to the problems, such as incomparability and referential discontinuity, that the meaning-change thesis raised. I show that Kuhn successfully questioned the causal theory and Putnam's idea that reference is determined via the sameness relation of essences that holds between a sample and other members of a kind in all possible worlds. Putnam's single ‘essential’ properties may be necessary but not sufficient to determine membership in a kind category. Kuhn argued that extension is fixed by similarity-dissimilarity relations that are liable to change in taxonomic reorganizations of science.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

This article has been under work for an unusually long time. While not all were, some of the reasons that prolonged the process were beyond my control. I wish to warmly thank all those who have kindly offered their comments on different versions of this paper or otherwise helped to improve the content over the years. I have especially the following persons in my mind: Alexander Bird, John Henry, Ranjan Chaudhuri, James W. McAllister, and a number of anonymous referees.

References

Andersen, Hanne. 2000. “Kuhn's Account of Family Resemblance: A Solution to the Problem of Wide-Open Texture.” Erkenntnis 52:312–37.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Andersen, Hanne. 2001a. On Kuhn. Belmont, CA: Wadsworth.Google Scholar
Andersen, Hanne. 2001b. “Reference and Resemblance.” Philosophy of Science 68 (Proceedings): S50S61.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Andersen, Hanne, Barker, Peter, and Chen, Xiang. 1996. “Kuhn's Mature Philosophy of Science and Cognitive Psychology.” Philosophical Psychology 9:347–63.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Andersen, Hanne, and Nersessian, Nancy. 2000. “Nomic Concepts, Frames and Conceptual Change.” Philosophy of Science 67 (Proceedings): S224S241.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barker, Peter, Chen, Xiang, and Andersen, Hanne. 2003. “Kuhn on Concept and Categorisation.” In Thomas Kuhn, ed. Nickles, Thomas, 212–45. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Barsalou, Lawrence. 1992. “Frames, Concepts, and Conceptual Fields.” In Frames, Fields, and Contrasts, ed. Lehrer, Adrienne and Kittay, Eva Feder, 2175. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.Google Scholar
Bird, Alexander. 2000. Thomas Kuhn. Chesham: Acumen.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bird, Alexander. 2002. “Kuhn's Wrong Turning.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 33:443–63.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bird, Alexander. 2003. “Kuhn, Nominalism, and Empiricism.” Philosophy of Science 70:690719.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bird, Alexander. 2004a. “Kuhn and Twentieth Century Philosophy of Science.” Annals of the Japan Association for Philosophy of Science 12:114.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bird, Alexander. 2004b. “Kuhn on Reference and Essence.” Philosophia Scientiae 8:5992.Google Scholar
Bird, Alexander. 2004c. “Kuhn, Naturalism, and the Positivist Legacy.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 35:337–56.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bird, Alexander. 2005. “Naturalising Kuhn.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 105:109–27.Google Scholar
Chen, Xian, Andersen, H., and Barker, P.. 1998. “Kuhn's Theory of Scientific Revolutions and Cognitive Psychology.” Philosophical Psychology 11:528.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Collins, Allan M., and Quillian, Ross. 1969. “Retrieval Time from Semantic Memory.” Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behaviour 8:240–47.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Devitt, Michael. 1997. Realism and Truth. 2nd ed. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Devitt, Michael. 2005. “Rigid Application.” Philosophical Studies 125:139–65.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Devitt, Michael, and Sterelny, Kim. 1999. Language and Reality: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Language. 2nd ed. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Donellan, Keith. 1983. “Kripke and Putnam on Natural Kind Terms.” In Knowledge and Mind: Philosophical Essays, ed. Ginet, Carl and Shoemaker, Sydney, 84104. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Earman, John. 1993. “Carnap, Kuhn, and the Philosophy of Scientific Methodology.” In World Changes: Thomas Kuhn and the Nature of Science, ed. Horwich, Paul, 937. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
English, Jane. 1978. “Partial Interpretation and Meaning Change.” Journal of Philosophy 75:5776.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Friedman, Michael. 2003. “Kuhn and Logical Empiricism.” In Thomas Kuhn, ed. Nickles, Thomas, 1945. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Fuller, Steven. 2000. Thomas Kuhn: A Philosophical History for Our Times. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Gattei, Stefano. 2008. Thomas Kuhn's Linguistic Turns and the Legacy of Logical Empiricism: Incommensurablity, Rationality and the Search for Truth. Aldershot: Ashgate.Google Scholar
Hacking, Ian. 1993. “Working in a New World: The Taxonomic Solution.” In World Changes: Thomas Kuhn and the Nature of Science, ed. Horwich, Paul, 275311. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Haukioja, Jussi. 2006. “Proto-Rigidity.” Synthese 150:155–69.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hoyningen-Huene, Paul. 1993. Reconstructing Scientific Revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Hoyningen-Huene, Paul, and Oberheim, Eric. 2009. “Reference, Ontological Replacement and Neo-Kantianism: A Reply to Sankey.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 40:203–9.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hoyningen-Huene, Paul, Oberheim, Eric, and Andersen, Hanne. 1996. “On Incommensurability.” Review of The Incommensurability Thesis, by Howard Sankey. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 27:131–41.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Irzik, Gürol, and Grünberg, Teo. 1995. “Carnap and Kuhn: Arch Enemies or Close Allies?British Journal for Philosophy of Science 46:285307.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jackson, Frank. 1998. “Reference and Description Revisited.” Noûs 32 (12): 201–18.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Johnston, Mark. 1997. “Manifest Kinds.” Journal of Philosophy 94:564–83.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kripke, Saul A. 1980. Naming and Necessity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas. 1957. The Copernican Revolution: Planetary Astronomy in the Development of Western Thought. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas. 1970. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. 2nd ed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas. 1977. The Essential Tension: Selected Studies in Scientific Tradition and Change. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas. 1990. “Dubbing and Redubbing: The Vulnerability of Rigid Designation.” In Scientific Theories, ed. Savage, C. Wade, 298319. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science 14. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas. 1993. “Afterwords.” In World Changes: Thomas Kuhn and the Nature of Science, ed. Horwich, Paul, 311–42. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas. 2000. The Road since Structure, ed. Conant, James and Haugeland, John. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Kuukkanen, Jouni-Matti. 2009. “Closing the Door to Cloud-Cuckoo Land: A Reply to Šešelja and Straßer.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 40:328–31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lakoff, George. 1987. Women, Fire, and Dangerous Things. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laporte, Joseph. 2000. “Rigidity and Kind.” Philosophical Studies 97:293316.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laporte, Joseph. 2007. “Rigid Designators.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. Zalta, Edward N.. Stanford, CA: Stanford University, http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2007/entries/rigid-designators/.Google Scholar
Macbeth, Danielle. 1995. “Names, Natural Kind Terms, and Rigid Designation.” Philosophical Studies 79:259–81.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Minsky, Marvin. 1980. “A Framework for Representing Knowledge.” In Frame Conceptions and Text Understanding, ed. Metzing, Dieter, 126. Berlin: de Gruyter.Google Scholar
Putnam, Hilary. 1975. Philosophical Papers II: Mind, Language, and Reality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Read, Rupert, and Sharrock, Wes. 2002. “Thomas Kuhn's Misunderstood Relation to Kripke-Putnam Essentialism.” Journal for General Philosophy of Science 33:151–58.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reisch, George A. 1991. “Did Kuhn Kill Logical Empiricism?Philosophy of Science 58:264–77.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Salmon, Nathan U. 1982. Reference and Essence. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Salmon, Nathan U.. 2005. “Are General Terms Rigid?Linguistics and Philosophy 28:117–34.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sankey, Howard. 1994. The Incommensurability Thesis. Aldershot: Avebury.Google Scholar
Sankey, Howard. 1997. “Incommensurability: The Current State of Play.” Theoria 12:424–45.Google Scholar
Sankey, Howard. 2000. “The Language of Science: Meaning Variance and Theory Comparison.” Language Science 22:117–36.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sankey, Howard. 2009. “Scientific Realism and the Semantic Incommensurability Thesis.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 40:196202.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scheffler, Israel. 1967. Science and Subjectivity. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill.Google Scholar
Schwartz, Stephen P. 2002. “Kinds, General Terms, and Rigidity: A Reply to Laporte.” Philosophical Studies 109:265–77.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sharrock, Wes, and Read, Rupert. 2002. Kuhn: Philosopher of Scientific Revolution. Cambridge: Polity.Google Scholar
Smith, Edward E., and Medin, Douglas L.. 1981. Categories and Concepts. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Soames, Scott. 2002. Beyond Rigidity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stanford, P. Kyle, and Kitcher, Philip. 2000. “Refining the Causal Theory of Reference for Natural Kind Terms.” Philosophical Studies 97:99129.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sterelny, K. 1983. “Natural Kind Terms.” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 64:110–25.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stevenson, Rosemary J. 1993. Language, Thought and Representation. Chichester: Wiley.Google Scholar
Suppe, Frederick. 1977. “Afterword.” In The Structure of Scientific Theories, ed. Suppe, Frederick, 617731. Chicago: University of Illinois Press.Google Scholar
Thagard, Paul. 1984. “Frames, Knowledge, and Inference.” Synthese 61:233–59.CrossRefGoogle Scholar