Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-gbm5v Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-25T07:04:50.215Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Karl Popper's Philosophical Breakthrough

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2022

Abstract

Despite his well-known deductivism, in his early (unpublished) writings, Popper held an inductivist position. Up to 1929 epistemology entered Popper's reflections only as far as the problem was that of the justification of the scientific character of these fields of research. However, in that year, while surveying the history of non-Euclidean geometries, Popper explicitly discussed the cognitive status of geometry without referring to psycho-pedagogical aspects, thus turning from cognitive psychology to the logic and methodology of science. As a consequence of his reflections on the problematic relationship between geometrical-mathematical constructions and physical reality Popper was able to get over a too direct notion of such a relationship, cast doubts on inductive inference and started conceiving in a new (strictly non-inductivist) manner the relationship between theoretical and observational propositions.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

I am most grateful to Joseph Agassi, Nimrod Bar-Am, Malachi H. Hacohen, Troels E. Hansen, John R. Wettersten, and two anonymous referees for their comments on previous drafts of this paper. Special thanks to Roberta Magrini and particularly Ferdinando Vidoni, without whom I would never have been able to write this paper. I dedicate it to John Preston, with friendship.

References

Agassi, Joseph (1961), “The Role of Corroboration in Popper’s Methodology”, The Role of Corroboration in Popper’s Methodology 39:8191. Reprinted in Agassi 1975, 40–50.Google Scholar
Agassi, Joseph (1968), “Science in Flux: Footnotes to Popper”, in Cohen, Robert S. and Wartofsky, Marx W. (eds.), Proceedings of the Boston Colloquium for the Philosophy of Science, 1964–1966. In Memory of Norwood Russell Hanson. Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 293323. Reprinted in Agassi 1975, 9–39.Google Scholar
Agassi, Joseph (1975), Science in Flux. Dordrecht and Boston: D. Reidel.10.1007/978-94-010-1810-4CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Agassi, Joseph (1988), “Sir Karl Popper in Retrospect. The Positive Power of Negative Thinking”, in Agassi, Joseph, The Philosophical Art of Philosophical Polemics. Selected Reviews and Comments. La Salle, IL: Open Court, 479501.Google Scholar
Agassi, Joseph (1993), A Philosopher’s Apprentice: In Karl Popper’s Workshop. Amsterdam and Atlanta: Rodopi.10.1163/9789401206112CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bühler, Karl (1927), Die Krise der Psychologie. Jena: Gustav Fischer.Google Scholar
Euclid (1951), “The Elements”, in Selections Illustrating the History of Greek Mathematics, edited and translated by Ivor Thomas. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 436479.Google Scholar
Gattei, Stefano (2002a), “The Ethical Nature of Karl Popper’s Solution to the Problem of Rationality”, The Ethical Nature of Karl Popper’s Solution to the Problem of Rationality 32:240266.Google Scholar
Gattei, Stefano (2002b), “The Positive Power of Negative Thinking”, The Positive Power of Negative Thinking 18:446452.Google Scholar
Gattei, Stefano (2004), “Rationality Without Foundations”, in Jarvie, Ian C., Miller, David, and Milford, Karl (eds.), Karl Popper: A Centenary Assessment. London: Ashgate, forthcoming.Google Scholar
Hacohen, Malachi H. (1996), “Karl Popper in Exile. The Viennese Progressive Imagination and the Making of The Open Society”, Karl Popper in Exile. The Viennese Progressive Imagination and the Making of The Open Society 26:452492.Google Scholar
Hacohen, Malachi H. (1998), “Karl Popper, the Vienna Circle, and Red Vienna”, Karl Popper, the Vienna Circle, and Red Vienna 59:711734.Google Scholar
Hacohen, Malachi H. (1999), “Dilemmas of Cosmopolitanism: Karl Popper, Jewish Identity, and ‘Central European Culture’”, Dilemmas of Cosmopolitanism: Karl Popper, Jewish Identity, and ‘Central European Culture’ 71:105149.Google Scholar
Hacohen, Malachi H. (2000), Karl Popper— The Formative Years, 1902–1945. Politics and Philosophy in Interwar Vienna, New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hansen, Troels E. (2004), “Which Came First, the Problem of Induction or the Problem of Demarcation?”, in Jarvie, Ian C., Miller, David, and Milford, Karl (eds.), Karl Popper: A Centenary Assessment, London: Ashgate, forthcoming.Google Scholar
Miller, David W. (1994), Critical Rationalism. A Restatement and Defence. Chicago-La Salle, IL: Open Court.Google Scholar
Newton-Smith, William H. (1981), The Rationality of Science. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Notturno, Mark A. (2000), Science and the Open Society. The Future of Karl Popper’s Philosophy. Budapest: Central European University Press.Google Scholar
Popper, Karl R. (1927), “Gewohnheit” und “Gesetzerlebnis” in der Erziehung. Eine pädagogisch- strukturpsychologische Monographie. Hausarbeit. Vienna: Pädagogisches Institut der Stadt Wien; in The Karl Popper Archives (12.11).Google Scholar
Popper, Karl R. (1928), Zur Methodenfrage der Denkpsychologie. Ph.D. Dissertation. Vienna: Universität Wien; in The Karl Popper Archives (17.1).Google Scholar
Popper, Karl R. (1929), Axiome, Definitionen und Postulate der Geometrie; in The Karl Popper Archives (4.6).Google Scholar
Popper, Karl R. ([1935] 1959), Logik der Forschung. Zur Erkenntnistheorie der modernen Naturwissenschaft. Vienna: Julius Springer. English edition, translated by Karl Popper, Julius Freed, and Lan Freed, The Logic of Scientific Discovery. London: Hutchinson & Co.Google Scholar
Popper, Karl R. ([1945] 1966), The Open Society and Its Enemies, vol. I: The Spell of Plato, vol. II: The High Tide of Prophecy: Hegel, Marx, and the Aftermath. 5th ed. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Popper, Karl R. (1946), “Why are the Calculuses of Logic and Arithmetic Applicable to Reality?”, in Logic and Reality, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume 20. London: Harrison & Sons, 40–60. Reprinted as “Why are the Calculi of Logic and Arithmetic Applicable to Reality?”, in Popper 1963a, 201214.Google Scholar
Popper, Karl R. (1957), “Philosophy of Science: A Personal Report”, in Mace, Cecil A. (ed.), British Philosophy in the Mid-Century. A Cambridge Symposium. London: George Allen & Unwin, 155–191. Reprinted as “Science: Conjectures and Refutations”, in Popper 1963a, 3365.Google Scholar
Popper, Karl R. (1963a), Conjectures and Refutations: The Growth of Scientific Knowledge. 5th ed., 1989. London: Routledge &Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Popper, Karl R. (1963b), “Truth, Rationality, and the Growth of Scientific Knowledge”, in Popper 1963a, 215250.Google Scholar
Popper, Karl R. (1974a), “Autobiography of Karl Popper”, in Schilpp, Paul A. (ed.), The Philosophy of Karl Popper, La Salle, Illinois: Open Court, 1–181. Revised and reprinted as Karl R. Popper, Unended Quest. An Intellectual Autobiography. London: Fontana/Collins, 1976.Google Scholar
Popper, Karl R. (1974b), “Replies to My Critics”, in Schilpp, Paul A. (ed.), The Philosophy of Karl Popper. La Salle, Illinois: Open Court, 9611197.Google Scholar
Popper, Karl R. ([1979] 1994), Die beiden Grundprobleme der Erkenntnistheorie, edited by Troels E. Hansen. 2d ed. Tübingen: J. C. B. Mohr (Paul Siebeck).Google Scholar
Russell, Bertrand (1897), An Essay on the Foundations of Geometry. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Schlick, Moritz ([1918] 1925), Allgemeine Erkenntnislehre, Berlin: Naturwissenschaftliche Monographien und Lehrbücher. 2d ed., Berlin: Julius Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
ter Hark, Michel (1993), “Problems of Psychologism: Popper as the Heir to Otto Selz”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 48 24:585609.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
ter Hark, Michel (2002), “Between Autobiography and Reality: Popper’s Inductive Years”, Between Autobiography and Reality: Popper’s Inductive Years 33:79103.Google Scholar
Watkins, John W. N. (1984), Science and Scepticism. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wettersten, John R. (1985), “The Road through Würzburg, Vienna and Gottingen. Review of Karl R. Popper, Die beiden Grundprobleme der Erkenntnistheorie”, The Road through Würzburg, Vienna and Gottingen. Review of Karl R. Popper, Die beiden Grundprobleme der Erkenntnistheorie 15:487506.Google Scholar
Wettersten, John R. (1988), “Külpe, Bühler, Popper”, in Eschbach, Achim (ed.), Karl Bühler’s Theory of Language. Amsterdam and Philadelphia: John Benjamins Publishing Co., 327347.Google Scholar
Wettersten, John R. (1992), The Roots of Critical Rationalism. Amsterdam and Atlanta: Rodopi.CrossRefGoogle Scholar