Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-dsjbd Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-30T18:53:09.072Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Can Cumulative Selection Explain Adaptation?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2022

Abstract

Two strong arguments have been given in favor of the claim that no selection process can play a role in explaining adaptations. According to the first argument, selection is a negative force; it may explain why the eliminated individuals are eliminated, but it does not explain why the ones that survived (or their offspring) have the traits they have. The second argument points out that the explanandum and the explanans are phenomena at different levels: selection is a population-level phenomenon, whereas adaptation occurs on the individual level. Thus, selection can explain why individuals in a certain population have a certain trait, but it cannot explain why a certain individual has this trait. After pointing out that both arguments ignore the significance of the limitation of environmental resources, I will construe a positive argument for the claim that cumulative selection processes can, indeed, play a role in explaining adaptations.

Type
Natural Selection and Evolution
Copyright
Copyright © The Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

I am grateful for comments from Paul Griffiths, David Papineau, John MacFarlane, James Sage, and Branden Fitelson, as well as for comments on earlier versions of this paper presented at the July 2003 Biannual Conference of the International Society for the History, Philosophy, and Social Studies of Biology, the April 2004 Central Division Meeting of the American Philosophical Association, and the November 2004 Biannual Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association.

References

Bedau, Mark (1991), “Can Biological Teleology Be Naturalized?”, Can Biological Teleology Be Naturalized? 88:647657.Google Scholar
Brandon, Robert N. (1985), “Adaptation Explanations: Are Adaptations for the Good of Replicators or Interactors?”, in Depew, David J. and Weber, Bruce H. (eds.), Evolution at a Crossroads: The New Biology and the New Philosophy of Science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 8196.Google Scholar
Brandon, Robert N. (1996), Concepts and Methods in Evolutionary Biology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Cummins, Robert (1975), “Functional Analysis”, Functional Analysis 72:741765.Google Scholar
Darden, Lindley, and Cain, Joseph A. (1989), “Selection Type Theories”, Selection Type Theories 56:106129.Google Scholar
Dawkins, Richard (1976), The Selfish Gene. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Dennett, Daniel C. (1995), Darwin’s Dangerous Idea. New York: Touchstone.Google Scholar
Dretske, Fred (1988), Explaining Behavior. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Dretske, Fred (2000), Perception, Knowledge, and Belief. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, Jerry A. (1990), A Theory of Content and Other Essays. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Gould, Stephen Jay, and Lewontin, Richard (1979), “The Sprandels of San Marco and the Panglossian Paradigm”, The Sprandels of San Marco and the Panglossian Paradigm B205:581598.Google Scholar
Gould, Stephen Jay, and Vrba, Elisabeth S. (1982), “Exaptation—a Missing Term in the Science of Form”, Exaptation—a Missing Term in the Science of Form 8:415.Google Scholar
Hull, David L. (1981), “Units of Evolution: A Metaphysical Essay”, in Jensen, U. J. and Harré, R. (eds.), The Philosophy of Evolution. Brighton, U.K.: Harvester, 2344.Google Scholar
Hull, David L., Langman, Rodney E., and Glenn, Sigrid S. (2001), “A General Account of Selection: Biology, Immunology, and Behavior”, A General Account of Selection: Biology, Immunology, and Behavior 24:511528. Reprinted in Science and Selection. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 49–96.Google ScholarPubMed
Lennox, James G., and Wilson, Bradley E. (1994), “Natural Selection and the Struggle for Existence”, Natural Selection and the Struggle for Existence 25:6580.Google ScholarPubMed
Lewens, Tim (2001), “Sex and Selection: Reply to Matthen”, Sex and Selection: Reply to Matthen 52:589598.Google Scholar
Lewis, David (1973), Counterfactuals. London: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Lewontin, Richard (1970), “The Units of Selection”, The Units of Selection 1:118.Google Scholar
Lewontin, Richard (1978), “Adaptation”, Adaptation 273:213228.Google Scholar
Matthen, Mohan (1999), “Evolution, Wisconsin Style: Selection and the Explanation of Individual Traits”, Evolution, Wisconsin Style: Selection and the Explanation of Individual Traits 50:143150.Google Scholar
Millikan, Ruth G. (1984), Languages, Thought, and Other Biological Categories. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Millikan, Ruth G. (1990), “Seismograph Readings for ‘Explaining Behavior’”, Seismograph Readings for ‘Explaining Behavior’ 50:819839.Google Scholar
Millikan, Ruth G. (1993), White Queen Psychology and Other Tales for Alice. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Nanay, Bence (2001), “A More Pluralist Typology of Selection Processes”, A More Pluralist Typology of Selection Processes 24:547548.Google Scholar
Nanay, Bence (2002), “The Return of the Replicator: What Is Philosophically Significant in a General Account of Replication and Selection?”, The Return of the Replicator: What Is Philosophically Significant in a General Account of Replication and Selection? 17:109121.Google Scholar
Neander, Karen (1995a), “Pruning the Tree of Life”, Pruning the Tree of Life 46:5980.Google Scholar
Neander, Karen (1995b), “Explaining Complex Adaptations: A Reply to Sober’s ‘Reply to Neander’”, Explaining Complex Adaptations: A Reply to Sober’s ‘Reply to Neander’ 46:583587.Google Scholar
Neander, Karen (1995c), “Misrepresenting and Malfunctioning”, Misrepresenting and Malfunctioning 79:109141.Google Scholar
Neander, Karen (1996a), “Dretke’s Innate Modesty”, Dretke’s Innate Modesty 74:258274.Google Scholar
Neander, Karen (1996b), “Swampman Meets Swampcow”, Swampman Meets Swampcow 11:118129.Google Scholar
Pampineau, David (1987), Reality and Representation. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Pampineau, David (1993), Philosophical Naturalism. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Pust, Joel (2001), “Natural Selection Explanation and Origin Essentialism”, Natural Selection Explanation and Origin Essentialism 31:201220.Google Scholar
Sober, Elliott (1984), The Nature of Selection. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Sober, Elliott (1995), “Natural Selection and Distributive Explanation”, Natural Selection and Distributive Explanation 46:384397.Google Scholar
Vrba, Elisabeth (1984), “What Is Species Selection?”, What Is Species Selection? 33:318328.Google Scholar
Walsh, Dennis M. (1998), “The Scope of Selection: Sober and Neander on What Natural Selection Explains”, The Scope of Selection: Sober and Neander on What Natural Selection Explains 76:250264.Google Scholar
Walsh, Dennis M. (2000), “Chasing Shadows: Natural Selection and Adaptation”, Chasing Shadows: Natural Selection and Adaptation 31:135153.Google Scholar
Williams, G. C. (1966), Adaptation and Natural Selection. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar