Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-dlnhk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-02T19:32:03.340Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

When Is Scientific Dissent Epistemically Inappropriate?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2022

Abstract

Normatively inappropriate scientific dissent prevents warranted closure of scientific controversies and confuses the public about the state of policy-relevant science, such as anthropogenic climate change. Against recent criticism by de Melo-Martín and Intemann of the viability of any conception of normatively inappropriate dissent, I identify three conditions for normatively inappropriate dissent: its generation process is politically illegitimate, it imposes an unjust distribution of inductive risks, and it adopts evidential thresholds outside an accepted range. I supplement these conditions with an inference-to-the-best-explanation account of knowledge-based consensus and dissent to allow policy makers to reliably identify unreliable scientific dissent.

Type
Social Epistemology and Science Policy
Copyright
Copyright 2021 by the Philosophy of Science Association. All rights reserved.

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

This article was written with the support of the Israel Science Foundation grant 650/18 for the project Skepticism about Testimony (principal investigators: Arnon Keren and Boaz Miller). I thank Kristen Intemann, Inmaculada de Melo-Martín, and David Kovacs for helpful feedback.

References

Biddle, Justin. 2014. “Can Patents Prohibit Research? On The Social Epistemology of Patenting and Licensing in Science.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 45:1423.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Biddle, Justin, and Leuschner, Anna. 2015. “Climate Skepticism and the Manufacture of Doubt: Can Dissent in Science Be Epistemically Detrimental?European Journal for Philosophy of Science 5 (3): 261–78.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Borgerson, Kirstin. 2011. “Amending and Defending Critical Contextual Empiricism.” European Journal for Philosophy of Science 1 (3): 435–49.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brown, Mark B. 2009. Science in Democracy: Expertise, Institutions, and Representation. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brown, Matthew J. 2020. Science and Moral Imagination: A New Ideal for Values in Science. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dang, Haixin. 2019. “Do Collaborators in Science Need to Agree?Philosophy of Science 86 (5): 1029–40.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Delborne, Jason A. 2016. “Suppression and Dissent in Science.” In Handbook of Academic Integrity, ed. Bretag, Tracy, 943–56. Singapore: Springer.Google Scholar
Dellsén, Finnur. 2018. “When Expert Disagreement Supports the Consensus.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 96 (1): 142–56.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
de Melo-Martín, Inmaculada, and Intemann, Kristen. 2018. The Fight against Doubt: How to Bridge the Gap between Scientists and the Public. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Douglas, Heather. 2000. “Inductive Risk and Values in Science.” Philosophy of Science 67 (4): 559–79.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Douglas, Heather. 2009. Science, Policy, and the Value-Free Ideal. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Elliott, Kevin C. 2017. A Tapestry of Values: An Introduction to Values in Science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fernández Pinto, Manuela. 2014. “Philosophy of Science for Globalized Privatization: Uncovering Some Limitations of Critical Contextual Empiricism.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 47:1017.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fernández Pinto, Manuela, and Hicks, Daniel J.. 2019. “Legitimizing Values in Regulatory Science.” Environmental Health Perspectives 127 (3): 035001–1.–8.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hicks, Daniel J., Magnus, P. D., and Wright, Jessey. 2020. “Inductive Risk, Science, and Values: A Reply to MacGillivray.” Risk Analysis 40 (4): 667–73.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Intemann, Kristen, and Melo-Martín, Inmaculada de. 2010. “Social Values and Scientific Evidence: The Case of the HPV Vaccines.” Biology and Philosophy 25 (2): 203–13.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Jasanoff, Sheila. 2012. “The Practices of Objectivity in Regulatory Science.” In Social Knowledge in the Making, ed. Camic, Charles, Gross, Neil, and Lamont, Michèle, 307–38. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Longino, Helen. 2002. The Fate of Knowledge. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Magnus, P. D. 2018. “Science, Values, and the Priority of Evidence.” Logos and Episteme 9 (4): 413–31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miller, Boaz. 2013. “When Is Consensus Knowledge Based? Distinguishing Shared Knowledge from Mere Agreement.” Synthese 190 (7): 1293–316.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miller, Boaz. 2014a. “Catching the WAVE: The Weight-Adjusting Account of Values and Evidence.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 47:6980.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miller, Boaz. 2014b. “Science, Values, and Pragmatic Encroachment on Knowledge.” European Journal for the Philosophy of Science 4 (2): 253–70.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miller, Boaz. 2015. “‘Trust Me—I’m a Public Intellectual’: Margaret Atwood’s and David Suzuki’s Social Epistemologies for Climate Science.” In Speaking Power to Truth: Digital Discourse and the Public Intellectual, ed. Keren, Michael and Hawkins, Richard, 113–28. Athabasca: Athabasca University Press.Google Scholar
Miller, Boaz. 2016. “Scientific Consensus and Expert Testimony in Courts: Lessons from the Bendectin Litigation.” Foundations of Science 21 (1): 1533.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miller, Boaz. 2019. “The Social Epistemology of Consensus and Dissent.” In The Routledge Companion to Social Epistemology, ed. Henderson, David, Graham, Peter, Fricker, Miranda, and Pedersen, Nikolaj, 228–39. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Oreskes, Naomi. 2019. Why Trust Science? Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Oreskes, Naomi, and Conway, Erik M.. 2010. Merchants of Doubt: How a Handful of Scientists Obscured the Truth on Issues from Tobacco Smoke to Global Warming. New York: Bloomsbury.Google Scholar
Rolin Kristina. 2009. “Scientific Knowledge: A Stakeholder Theory.” In The Social Sciences and Democracy, ed. Bouwel, Jeroen van, 6280. New York: Palgrave-Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilholt, Torsten. 2009. “Bias and Values in Scientific Research.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 40:92101.CrossRefGoogle Scholar