Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-gxg78 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-25T19:20:39.522Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

There Are No Ahistorical Theories of Function

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2022

Abstract

Theories of function are conventionally divided up into historical and ahistorical ones. Proponents of ahistorical theories often cite the ahistoricity of their accounts as a major virtue. Here, I argue that none of the mainstream “ahistorical” accounts are actually ahistorical. All of them refer, implicitly or explicitly, to history. In Boorse’s goal-contribution account, history is latent in the idea of statistical typicality. In the propensity theory, history is implicit in the idea of a species’ natural habitat. In the causal role theory, history is required for making sense of dysfunction. I elaborate some consequences for the functions debate.

Type
Biological Sciences
Copyright
Copyright © The Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

I am grateful to audience members at PSA 2018, where I presented this material. I also thank Daniel Dennett, Paul Griffiths, and Fabian Hundertmark for useful feedback.

References

Amundson, R., and Lauder, G. V.. 1994. “Function without Purpose: The Uses of Causal Role Function in Evolutionary Biology.” Biology and Philosophy 9:443–69.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bigelow, J., and Pargetter, R.. 1987. “Functions.” Journal of Philosophy 84:181–96.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bock, W. J., and Wahlert, G. von. 1965. “Adaptation and the Form-Function Complex.” Evolution 19:269–99.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boorse, C. 1976. “Wright on Functions.” Philosophical Review 85:7086.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boorse, C.. 1977. “Health as a Theoretical Concept.” Philosophy of Science 44:542–73.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boorse, C.. 2002. “A Rebuttal on Functions.” In Functions: New Essays in the Philosophy of Psychology and Biology, ed. Ariew, A., Cummins, R., and Perlman, M., 63112. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Craver, C. 2001. “Role Functions, Mechanisms, and Hierarchy.” Philosophy of Science 68:5374.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cummins, R. 1975. “Functional Analysis.” Journal of Philosophy 72:741–65.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Garson, J. 2016. A Critical Overview of Biological Functions. Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Garson, J.. 2018. “How to Be a Function Pluralist.” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 69:101–22.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Garson, J.. 2019. What Biological Functions Are and Why They Matter. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Godfrey-Smith, P. 1993. “Functions: Consensus without Unity.” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 74:196208.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Griffiths, P. 2009. “In What Sense Does ‘Nothing Make Sense Except in the Light of Evolution’?Acta Biotheoretica 57:1132.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hardcastle, V. G. 2002. “On the Normativity of Functions.” In Functions: New Essays in the Philosophy of Psychology and Biology, ed. Ariew, A., Cummins, R., and Perlman, M., 144–56. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
McLaughlin, P. 2001. What Functions Explain: Functional Explanation and Self-Reproducing Systems. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Millikan, R. G. 1984. Language, Thought, and Other Biological Categories. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Nanay, B. 2010. “A Modal Theory of Function.” Journal of Philosophy 107:412–31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nanay, B.. 2012. “Function Attribution Depends on the Explanatory Context: A Reply to Neander and Rosenberg’s Reply to Nanay.” Journal of Philosophy 109:623–27.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Neander, K. 1983. “Abnormal Psychobiology.” PhD diss., La Trobe University.Google Scholar
Neander, K.. 1991. “Functions as Selected Effects: The Conceptual Analyst’s Defense.” Philosophy of Science 58:168–84.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Neander, K.. 2017. “Functional Analysis and the Species Design.” Synthese 194:1147–68.10.1007/s11229-015-0940-9CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Neander, K., and Rosenberg, A.. 2012. “Solving the Circularity Problem for Functions.” Journal of Philosophy 109:613–22.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wakefield, J. C. 1992. “The Concept of Mental Disorder: On the Boundary between Biological Facts and Social Values.” American Psychologist 47:373–88.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Walsh, D. M. 1996. “Fitness and Function.” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 47:553–74.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Walsh, D. M., and Ariew, A.. 1996. “A Taxonomy of Functions.” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 26:493514.CrossRefGoogle Scholar