Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-tf8b9 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-01T01:54:31.987Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Socializing Naturalized Philosophy of Science

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 April 2022

Stephen M. Downes*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, University of Utah
*
Send reprint requests to the author, Department of Philosophy, 338 Orson Spencer Hall, The University of Utah, Salt Lake City, UT 84112, USA.

Abstract

I propose an approach to naturalized philosophy of science that takes the social nature of scientific practice seriously. I criticize several prominent naturalistic approaches for adopting “cognitive individualism”, which limits the study of science to an examination of the internal psychological mechanisms of scientists. I argue that this limits the explanatory capacity of these approaches. I then propose a three-level model of the social nature of scientific practice, and use the model to defend the claim that scientific knowledge is socially produced.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Philosophy of Science Association 1993

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

This paper was completed during a post-doctoral fellowship at Northwestern University. Arthur Fine, Steve Fuller, David Hull and an anonymous referee provided helpful comments on earlier drafts.

References

Ackermann, R. J. (1985), Data, Instruments and Theory. Princeton: Princeton University Press.10.1515/9781400854936CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bach, K. and Harnish, R. M. (1982), “Katz as Katz Can”, Journal of Philosophy 79: 168171.10.2307/2026073CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barnes, B. and Bloor, D. (1982), “Relativism, Rationalism and the Sociology of Knowledge”, in Hollis, M. and Lukes, S. (eds.), Rationality and Relativism. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 2147.Google Scholar
Bloor, D. (1976), Knowledge and Social Imagery. London: Routledge Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Brannigan, A. (1981), The Social Basis of Scientific Discoveries. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Campbell, D. (1969), “Ethnocentrism of Disciplines and the Fish Scale Model of Omniscience”, in Sherif, C. and Sherif, M. (eds.), Interdisciplinary Relationships in the Social Sciences. Chicago: Aldine Press, pp. 328348.Google Scholar
Churchland, P. M. (1990), A Neurocomputational Perspective: The Nature of Mind and the Structure of Science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Collins, H. M. (1985), Changing Order. London: Sage.Google Scholar
Downes, S. M. (1992), “The Importance of Models in Theorizing: A Deflationary Semantic Approach”, in Forbes, M. and Hull, D. (eds.), Proceedings of the Philosophy of Science Association, vol. 1. East Lansing: Philosophy of Science Association, pp. 142153.Google Scholar
Fleck, L. (1979), The Genesis and Development of a Scientific Fact. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Forman, P. (1971), “Weimar Culture, Causality, and Quantum Theory, 1917–1927: Adaptation by German Physicists and Mathematicians to a Hostile Intellectual Environment”, in McCormmach, R. (ed.), Historical Studies in the Physical Sciences, vol. 3. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, pp. 1115.Google Scholar
Franklin, A. (1986), The Neglect of Experiment. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9780511624896CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fuller, S. W. (1989), Philosophy of Science and its Discontents. Boulder: Westview Press.Google Scholar
Galison, P. (1987), How Experiments End. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Giere, R. (1988), Explaining Science: A Cognitive Approach. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Glymour, C. (1981), Theory and Evidence. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Gooding, D.; Pinch, T. and Schaffer, S. (eds.), (1990), The Uses of Experiment. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hacking, I. (1983), Representing and Intervening. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9780511814563CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hull, D. (1988a), “A Function for Actual Examples in Philosophy of Science”, in Ruse, M. (ed.), What the Philosophy of Biology Is. Dordrecht: Kluwer, pp. 309321.Google Scholar
Hull, D. (1988b), Science as Process. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kitcher, P. (1990), “The Division of Cognitive Labor”, Journal of Philosophy 87: 522.10.2307/2026796CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Knorr-Cetina, K. (1981), The Manufacture of Knowledge. Oxford: Pergamon Press.Google Scholar
Lakatos, I. (1981), “History of Science and its Rational Reconstructions”, in Hacking, I. (ed.), Scientific Revolutions. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 107127.Google Scholar
Langley, P.; Bradshaw, G. L.; Simon, H. A. and Zytgow, J. M. (1987), Scientific Discovery. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.10.7551/mitpress/6090.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Latour, B. (1987), Science in Action. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Latour, B. and Woolgar, S. (1986), Laboratory Life. 2d ed. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Laudan, L. (1977), Progress and its Problems. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Longino, H. (1990), Science as Social Knowledge. Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mulkay, M. (1976), “Norms and Ideology”, Social Science Information 15: 637656.10.1177/053901847601500406CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pickering, A. (1984), Constructing Quarks: A Sociological History of Particle Physics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. (1975), Mind, Language, and Reality. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rouse, J. (1987), Knowledge and Power. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Shapin, S. and Schaffer, S. (1985), Leviathon and the Air-pump. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Thagard, P. R. (1988), A Computational Philosophy of Science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thagard, P. R. (1989a), “Explanatory Coherence”, Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12: 435502.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thagard, P. R. (1989b), “Scientific Cognition: Hot or Cold?” in S. Fuller, M. DeMey, T. Shinn, and S. Woolgar (eds.), The Cognitive Turn: Sociological and Psychological Perspectives on Science. Dordrecht: Kluwer, pp. 7182.10.1007/978-94-015-7825-7_4CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Fraassen, B. (1980), The Scientific Image. Oxford: Oxford University Press.10.1093/0198244274.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilkes, K. (1988), Real People. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Woolgar, S. (1988), Science: The Very Idea. London: Tavistock.Google Scholar