Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-2brh9 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-27T18:44:37.277Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

How to Reconcile Physicalism and Antireductionism about Biology

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2022

Abstract

Physicalism and antireductionism are the ruling orthodoxy in the philosophy of biology. But these two theses are difficult to reconcile. Merely embracing an epistemic antireductionism will not suffice, as both reductionists and antireductionists accept that given our cognitive interests and limitations, non-molecular explanations may not be improved, corrected or grounded in molecular ones. Moreover, antireductionists themselves view their claim as a metaphysical or ontological one about the existence of facts molecular biology cannot identify, express or explain. However, this is tantamount to a rejection of physicalism and so causes the antireductionist discomfort. In this paper we argue that vindicating physicalism requires a physicalistic account of the principle of natural selection, and we provide such an account. The most important payoff to the account is that it provides for the very sort of autonomy from the physical that antireductionists need without threatening their commitment to physicalism.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

We are grateful to Frederic Bouchard, Marion Hourdequin, Stefan Linquist, Grant Ramsey, C. Kenneth Waters, a referee for comments on previous drafts, and especially to Marc Lange, for his comments. The urgency of the problem dealt with here was made particularly manifest by Lange (2004).

References

Albert, David (2000), Time and Chance. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Bouchard, Frédéric, and Rosenberg, Alex (2003), “Drift, Fitness, and the Foundations of Probability”, in Hüttemann, Andreas (ed.), Indeterminism in Physics and Biology. Paderborn, Germany: Mentis.Google Scholar
Bouchard, Frédéric, and Rosenberg, Alex (2004), “Fitness, Probability and the Principles of Natural Selection”, Fitness, Probability and the Principles of Natural Selection 55:693712.Google Scholar
Brandon, Robert (1978), “Adaptation and Evolutionary Theory”, Adaptation and Evolutionary Theory 9:181206.Google Scholar
Brandon, Robert (1990), Adaptation and Environment. Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davidson, Donald (1967), “Causal Relations”, Causal Relations 64:691703.Google Scholar
Dennett, Daniel C. (1995), Darwin’s Dangerous Idea. New York: Simon and Schuster.Google Scholar
Dobzhansky, Theodosius (1973), “Nothing in Biology Makes Sense Except in the Light of Evolution”, Nothing in Biology Makes Sense Except in the Light of Evolution 35:125129.Google Scholar
Eigen, Manfred, and Schuster, Peter (1977), “The Hypercycle. A Principle of Natural Self-Organization”, The Hypercycle. A Principle of Natural Self-Organization 64:541565.Google ScholarPubMed
Hellman, Geoffrey, and Thompson, Frank Wilson (1975), “Physicalism: Ontology, Determination, and Reduction”, Physicalism: Ontology, Determination, and Reduction 72:551564.Google Scholar
Hellman, Geoffrey, and Thompson, Frank Wilson (1977), “Physicalist Materialism”, Physicalist Materialism 11:309345.Google Scholar
Kauffman, Stuart (1995), At Home in the Universe: The Search for the Laws of Self-Organization and Complexity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kauffman, Stuart (1993), The Origins of Order: Self-Organization and Selection in Evolution. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kim, Jaegwon (1992), “‘Downward Causation’ in Emergentism and Nonreductive Physicalism”, in Beckermann, Ansgar, Flohr, Hans, and Kim, Jaegwon (eds.), Emergence or Reduction? Berlin: de Gruyter, 119138.Google ScholarPubMed
Kim, Jaegwon (1993), Supervenience and Mind: Selected Philosophical Essays. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kim, Jaegwon (1998), Mind in a Physical World. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kitcher, Philip (1984), “1953 and All That: A Tale of Two Sciences”, 1953 and All That: A Tale of Two Sciences 93:335373.Google Scholar
Kitcher, Philip (1993), The Advancement of Science. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kitcher, Philip (1999), “The Hegemony of Molecular Biology”, The Hegemony of Molecular Biology 14:195210.Google Scholar
Lange, Marc (1995), “Are There Natural Laws Concerning Particular Species”, Are There Natural Laws Concerning Particular Species 112:430451.Google Scholar
Lange, Marc (2004),“The Autonomy of Functional Biology: A Reply to Rosenberg”, The Autonomy of Functional Biology: A Reply to Rosenberg 19:93109.Google Scholar
Mayr, Ernst (1982), The Growth of Biological Thought. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Mitchell, Sandra (2000), “Dimensions of Scientific Law”, Dimensions of Scientific Law 67:242265.Google Scholar
Nagel, Ernest (1961), The Structure of Science: Problems in the Logic of Scientific Explanation. New York: Harcourt, Brace & World.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Railton, Peter (1981), “Probability, Explanation, and Information,” Synthese 48:233256.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rebek, Julius (1996), “The Design of Self-Replicating Molecules,” Current Opinion in Structural Biology 4:629635.Google Scholar
Rebek, Julius, Park, Tae Kwo, and Feng, Qing (1992), “Synthetic Replicators and Extrabiotic Chemistry”, Synthetic Replicators and Extrabiotic Chemistry 114:45294532.Google Scholar
Robert, Jason Scott, and Campbell, Richmond (2005), “The Structure of Evolution by Natural Selection”, Biology and Philosophy, forthcoming.Google Scholar
Rosenberg, Alex (1985), The Structure of Biological Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosenberg, Alex (1993), Instrumental Biology or the Disunity of Science. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Rosenberg, Alex (2001a), “How Is Biological Explanation Possible?British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 52:735760.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosenberg, Alex (2001b), “Reductionism in a Historical Science”, Reductionism in a Historical Science 68:135163.Google Scholar
Salmon, Wesley (1989), “Four Decades of Scientific Explanation”, in Salmon, Wesley and Kitcher, Philip (eds.), Scientific Explanation: Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Volume 13. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 3219.Google Scholar
Sober, Elliott (1984), The Nature of Selection: Evolutionary Theory in Philosophical Focus. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Sober, Elliott (1993), The Philosophy of Biology. Boulder, CO: Westview PressGoogle Scholar
Sober, Elliott (1999), The Philosophy of Biology, 2d ed. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.Google Scholar
Sober, Elliott, and Wilson, David S. (1996), Unto Others. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Waters, C. Kenneth (1990), “Why the Antireductionist Consensus Won’t Survive: The Case of Classical Mendelian Genetics”, in Arthur Fine, Mickey Forbes, and Linda Wessels (eds.), PSA 1990, Proceedings of the 1990 Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, Volume 1, 125139.Google Scholar
Waters, C. Kenneth (1994), “Genes Made Molecular”, Genes Made Molecular 61:163185.Google Scholar
Waters, C. Kenneth (2005), “A Pluralist Interpretation of Gene-Centered Biology”, in Kellert, Stephen, Longino, Helen, and Waters, C. Kenneth (eds.), Scientific Pluralism: Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Volume 19. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, forthcoming.Google Scholar
Woodward, James (1997), “Explanation, Invariance and Intervention” in Lindley Darden (ed.), PSA 1996, Proceedings of the 1996 Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, Volume 2.Google Scholar
Wright, Larry (1973), “Functions”, Functions 82:139168.Google Scholar