Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-tf8b9 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-02T21:27:58.929Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Discussion: Salmon on Explanatory Relevance

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 April 2022

Christopher Read Hitchcock*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy Rice University

Abstract

One of the motivations for Salmon's (1984) causal theory of explanation was the explanatory irrelevance exhibited by many arguments conforming to Hempel's covering-law models of explanation. However, the nexus of causal processes and interactions characterized by Salmon is not rich enough to supply the necessary conception of explanatory relevance. Salmon's (1994) revised theory, which is briefly criticized on independent grounds, fares no better. There is some possibility that the two-tiered structure of explanation described by Salmon (1984) may be pressed into service, but more work would have to be done. Ironically, Salmon's difficulties are similar to those suffered by his seventeenth-century predecessors.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Philosophy of Science Association 1995

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

I am grateful to Wes Salmon and Jim Woodward for their many discussions with me on this topic.

Send reprint requests to the author, Department of Philosophy, Rice University, MS 14, Houston, TX 77005-1892, USA.

References

Dijksterhuis, E. J. (1961), The Mechanization of the World Picture. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Dowe, P. (1992), “Wesley Salmon's Process Causality and the Conserved Quantity Theory”, Philosophy of Science 59: 195216.10.1086/289662CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dray, W. (1957), Laws and Explanation in History. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Eells, E. (1991), Probabilistic Causality. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9780511570667CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Glymour, C. (1982), “Causal Inference and Causal Explanation”, in McLaughlin, R. (ed.), What? Where? When? Why? Dordrecht: Reidel, pp. 179191.10.1007/978-94-009-7731-0_8CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hempel, C. G. (1965), “Aspects of Scientific Explanation”, in Aspects of Scientific Explanation and Other Essays in the Philosophy of Science. New York: Free Press, pp. 331496.Google Scholar
Hempel, C. G. and Oppenheim, P. (1948), “Studies in the Logic of Explanation”, Philosophy of Science 15: 135175. (Reprinted with added postscript in Aspects of Scientific Explanation and Other Essays in the Philosophy of Science.)10.1086/286983CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hitchcock, C. R. (1993), “A Generalized Probabilistic Theory of Causal Relevance”, Synthese 97: 335364.10.1007/BF01064073CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hitchcock, C. R. (1995), “The Mishap at Reichenbach Fall: Singular vs. General Causation”, Philosophical Studies 78, June (in press).10.1007/BF00990114CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kitcher, P. (1989), “Explanatory Unification and the Causal Structure of the World”, in Kitcher and Salmon (1989), pp. 410505.Google Scholar
Kitcher, P. and Salmon, W. C. (eds.) (1989), Scientific Explanation. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Kyburg, H. (1965), “Discussion: Salmon's Paper”, Philosophy of Science 32: 147151.10.1086/288034CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, D. K. (1986), “Causation” and “Postscripts to ‘Causation’ ”, in Philosophical Papers, Volume II. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 159213.Google Scholar
Salmon, W. C. (1965), “The Status of Prior Probabilities in Statistical Explanation”, Philosophy of Science 32: 137146.10.1086/288033CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Salmon, W. C. (1971), “Statistical Explanation”, in Salmon et al., Statistical Explanation and Statistical Relevance. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press, pp. 2987.10.2307/j.ctt6wrd9p.6CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Salmon, W. C. (1984), Scientific Explanation and the Causal Structure of the World. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Salmon, W. C. (1994), “Causality without Counterfactuals”, Philosophy of Science 61: 297312.10.1086/289801CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Skyrms, B. (1984), “EPR: Lessons for Metaphysics”, in French, P., Uehling, T., and Wettstein, H. (eds.), Midwest Studies in Philosophy IX: Causation and Causal Theories. Minneapolis, University of Minnesota Press, pp. 245255.Google Scholar
Woodward, J. (1979), “Scientific Explanation”, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 30: 4167.10.1093/bjps/30.1.41CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Woodward, J. (1984), “A Theory of Singular Causal Explanation”, Erkenntnis 21: 231262.10.1007/BF00169275CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Woodward, J. (1989), “The Causal Mechanical Model of Explanation”, in Kitcher and Salmon (1989), pp. 357383.Google Scholar