Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-hc48f Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-25T07:08:49.940Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Are Higher Mechanistic Levels Causally Autonomous?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2022

Abstract

This article provides a detailed analysis and explores the prospects of the arguments for higher-level causal autonomy available for the proponents of the mechanistic framework. Three different arguments (context based, organization based, and constraint based) are distinguished. After clarifying previously raised worries with regard to the first two arguments, the article focuses on the newest version of the third argument that has recently been revived by William Bechtel. By using Bechtel’s own case study, it is shown that not even reference to constraints can establish the causal autonomy of higher mechanistic levels.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

We would like to thank Lise Marie Andersen, Markus Eronen, Lena Kästner, and Beate Krickel for their insightful comments on earlier versions of this article. Funding for this research was provided by the Research Foundation—Flanders (postdoctoral fellowship 1.2.B39.14N to Peter Fazekas).

References

Bechtel, William. 2007. “Reducing Psychology While Maintaining Its Autonomy Via Mechanistic Explanation.” In The Matter of the Mind: Philosophical Essays on Psychology, Neuroscience and Reduction, ed. Schouten, Maurice and Looren de Jong, Huib, 172–98. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Bechtel, William. 2008. Mental Mechanisms: Philosophical Perspectives on Cognitive Neuroscience. New York: Psychology.Google Scholar
Bechtel, William. 2009. “Looking Down, Around, and Up: Mechanistic Explanation in Psychology.” Philosophical Psychology 22:543–64.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bechtel, William. 2017a. “Explicating Top-Down Causation Using Networks and Dynamics.” Philosophy of Science 84:253–74.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bechtel, William. 2017b. “Top-Down Causation in Biology and Neuroscience: Control Hierarchies.” In Philosophical and Scientific Perspectives on Downward Causation, ed. Paoletti, Michele Paolini and Orilia, Francesco. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Bechtel, William, and Abrahamsen, Adele. 2005. “Explanation: A Mechanist Alternative.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science C 36:421–41.Google Scholar
Bechtel, William, and Abrahamsen, Adele. 2008. “From Reduction Back to Higher Levels.” In Proceedings of the 30th Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society, ed. Love, B. C., McRae, K., and Sloutsky, V. M., 559–64. Austin, TX: Cognitive Science Society.Google Scholar
Craver, Carl. 2007. Explaining the Brain: Mechanisms and the Mosaic Unity of Neuroscience. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Craver, Carl, and Bechtel, William. 2007. “Top-Down Causation without Top-Down Causes.” Biology and Philosophy 22:547–63.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Craver, Carl, and Darden, Lindley. 2013. In Search of Mechanisms: Discoveries across the Life Sciences. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eronen, Markus. 2015. “Levels of Organization: A Deflationary Account.” Biology and Philosophy 30:3958.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fazekas, Peter, and Kertész, Gergely. 2011. “Causation at Different Levels: Tracking the Commitments of Mechanistic Explanation.” Biology and Philosophy 26:365–83.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Glennan, Stuart. 1996. “Mechanisms and the Nature of Causation.” Erkenntnis 44:4971.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Glennan, Stuart. 2010. “Mechanisms, Causes, and the Layered Model of the World.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 81:362–81.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Glennan, Stuart. 2017. The New Mechanical Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Glennan, Stuart, and Illari, Phyllis. 2018. The Routledge Handbook of Mechanisms and Mechanical Philosophy. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Hendry, Robin F. 2010. “Ontological Reduction and Molecular Structure.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science B 41 (2): 183–91..Google Scholar
Illari, Phyllis, and Williamson, Jon. 2012. “What Is a Mechanism? Thinking about Mechanisms across the Sciences.” European Journal for Philosophy of Science 2:119–35.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kaiser, Marie I., and Krickel, Beate. 2017. “The Metaphysics of Constitutive Mechanistic Phenomena.” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 68 (3): 745–79..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kim, Jaegwon. 1998. Mind in a Physical World. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Krickel, Beate. 2019. The Mechanical World: The Metaphysical Commitments of the New Mechanistic Approach. New York: Springer.Google Scholar
Machamer, Peter, Darden, Lindley, and Craver, Carl. 2000. “Thinking about Mechanisms.” Philosophy of Science 67:125.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Paoletti, Michele Paolini, and Orilia, Francesco. 2017. Philosophical and Scientific Perspectives on Downward Causation. London: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosenberg, Alex. 2018. “Making Mechanism Interesting.” Synthese 195 (1): 1133..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosenwasser, Alan M., and Turek, Fred W.. 2017. “Physiology of the Mammalian Circadian System.” In Principles and Practice of Sleep Medicine, ed. Kryger, Meir. H., Roth, Thomas, and Dement, William C., 351–61. Philadelphia: Elsevier Health Sciences.Google Scholar
Shoemaker, Sydney. 2007. Physical Realization. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Soom, Patrice. 2012. “Mechanisms, Determination and the Metaphysics of Neuroscience.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science C 43:655–64.Google Scholar