Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-dk4vv Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-27T09:03:36.982Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Stories of the Soul

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  02 April 2024

Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Extract

Core share and HTML view are not available for this content. However, as you have access to this content, a full PDF is available via the ‘Save PDF’ action button.

When it comes to the crunch, how does one know what other people are thinking, feeling etc? One way — the classical modern-philosophical way — of dealing with this question is to say that one knows what others are thinking etc. from analogy with one’s own case. Another way, however, is to go back to the Aristotelian conception of the soul as form of the body — which rules out radical scepticism about other people’s minds. In comparison with the Platonic story, at any rate, Aristotle’s view seems like plain common sense. On the other hand, the imaginative power of the Platonic story is so immense that liberation from it cannot be easily achieved. It is possible to read Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations as an intervention in this long debate. By resorting to St Augustine’s picture of how (why) an infant acquires language, as he does at the beginning of the Investigations, isn’t Wittgenstein inviting his readers to learn to tell a different story about the soul from the one that is so entrenched in the Christian spiritual tradition?

Scepticism about our knowledge of other people’s minds, feelings, etc., may thus be met by the argument that one infers the existence of such hidden entities from analogy with one’s own case. But this concedes far too much to scepticism. This argument remains under the spell of the myth of the homunculus peeping suspiciously through the eyelet-holes of his face-mask at the surrounding horde of similarly masked creatures, all no doubt engaged in equivalent inferences. One alternative to this radically paranoid-solipsist conception is to return to the relatively ‘physicalist’ approach to be found in Aristotle (and perhaps, by qualified extrapolation, in Thomas Aquinas).

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © 1983 Provincial Council of the English Province of the Order of Preachers

References

1 Cf “On the Road to Solipsism”, New Blackfriars, February 1983.

2 Pythagoras who may well have discovered the Theorem, must have died by the close of the 6th century BC: he taught a doctrine of the transmigration of souls, but is in other ways also the legendary figure with whom Plato has to come to terms.

3 The quotation comes from the Magna Moralia (1213a) but those who doubt it was written by Aristotle himself will find the same idea, in much the same words, in the Nicomachean Ethics. The essay by Richard Sorabji, ‘Body and Soul in Aristotle’, in Philosophy 49 (1974), is very illuminating.

4 The quotation comes from the Malcolm Memoir, p 71.

5 Cf “Eine Einstellung zur Seele”, the Presidential Address by Peter Winch, in Aristotelian Society Proceedings 1980‐81.

6 Last Writings on the Philosophy of Psychology, Volume I p 45.Google Scholar