Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-8bhkd Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-02T21:52:49.289Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Society and God: Culture and Creed From a Philosophical Standpoint by William Charlton, James Clarke & Co, 2020, pp. 195, £65.00, hbk

Review products

Society and God: Culture and Creed From a Philosophical Standpoint by William Charlton, James Clarke & Co, 2020, pp. 195, £65.00, hbk

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2024

Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Type
Reviews
Copyright
Copyright © 2021 Provincial Council of the English Province of the Order of Preachers

William Charlton is never afraid to bring tough philosophical argument to bear on big questions, not least those of religion. He does this with a rare combination of creative independence and respect for traditional Christian faith, integrating his expertise in metaphysics with that in politics and ethics. His masterly knowledge of the ancient world and his first-hand experience of living on a Polynesian island often enable him to observe our easy assumptions with fresh eyes. His style is not that of an apologist arguing to precise, dogmatic conclusions. Rather, he offers a view on how Christian ideas might best be rationally defended.

One of these assumptions is that we know what we mean by ‘religion’. Charlton argues powerfully that this is a far from neutral concept, and that ‘we apply the label to … whatever in societies other than our own most resembles Christianity’. He offers a working definition of the word as it is currently used: ‘a sub-society for life, not essentially confined to one nation or race, existing within a larger society, … which [has] practices and beliefs at variance with those present in the larger society’ (p. 43).

We are religious, then, insofar as we are social. Indeed, Charlton argues, we are human insofar as we are social. He makes short work of atomistic individualism in the manner of J.S. Mill, and develops a tri-partite view of human beings, familiar from his previous writings, as combining egoistic, social, and altruistic elements. Our social nature means that we have a range of emotions and attitudes towards our society and its culture as such, not only towards individuals within it. As social beings, we make the practical judgement (expressed in our practical decisions) that the customs of our society are, on the whole, right. This is neither a weakness nor a source of pride: it is an essential part of what it is to be human.

Christianity is a society not only with customs, but with beliefs. (Again, Charlton lets us take nothing for granted: ‘belief’, he argues, is a concept inherited from Greek philosophy, and many non-European languages do not have a word for it.) These include the existence of the Trinitarian Creator, and life after death. Building on Aristotle, Charlton argues that to say God is Creator is not to give a causal explanation of how the created order began, but rather to make a claim about its purpose: ‘God is responsible for the natural order as we are responsible for our actions,’ (p. 67). Whether or not we are capable of accepting that belief is in large part a question of the kind of people we become, as with all judgement of others’ intentions.

Christians believe they are saved through Jesus Christ. The soteriology Charlton offers involves a double rejection of atomism. We are saved as social beings, by incorporation into the body of Christ, like the branches of a vine. We are also saved as part of a single story: incarnation, crucifixion, ascension, eucharist, and so on are a continuous, and continuing, whole, as we grow into the life of Christ by sharing the sacramental life of the Church. Regretting the lack of contemporary Christian exploration of the afterlife, Charlton continues this theme with philosophically disciplined imagination: the purified faithful, he suggests, might grow into sharing God's very creativity, extending their own love and sympathy in so doing.

Learning to live with Christ's life begins on this earth, and Christians form a sub-society not least because of their ethical beliefs and practices. Charlton makes some shrewd points about the slippery language used in debates about euthanasia and abortion (‘right to life’, ‘person’), and concludes that Christians may have to choose between acting against their principles and abandoning medical roles. The sub-society is ‘at variance with’ the larger society.

Is it in any case a good thing to have sub-societies? Charlton's answer may seem surprising for a member of a Church which is and has often been a persecuted minority. He argues that multi-culturalism is incompatible with state education, for education is nothing if not ‘the transmission of the customs of a society and the concepts associated with them from one generation to the next’ (p. 159). A genuine plurality of cultures, and therefore of systems of education, would imperil social cohesion, while children from a sub-culture educated by the state are pulled in two socially.

Is the only way forward, then, ‘liberal’ indoctrination for all our children? Charlton's unexpected and brilliant finale is to describe all those elements of worth in our own culture that are valued even by liberals - education, arts, history, public celebrations, sport, and so on - and show that liberalism only possesses these insofar as they are inherited from Christianity, while physicalism, psychological egoism and competition for honours are far from attractive compared to their Christian alternatives. Future generations, he concludes, might, to the surprise of the liberals, ‘prefer Christianity to secular liberalism not only as being more cheerful and providing more inspiring ideals, but as being more rational and even more liberal’ (p. 177).

A philosophically imaginative book inevitably raises questions. It was unclear to me, for example, whether the suggestion that ‘the bodies of the risen are the risen bodies of Christ himself’ (p. 120) denies the personal individuality of our risen bodies. The chapter on natural law focused on rather familiar points about the debate about Humanae Vitae and the theories of Grisez and Finnis and missed the opportunity to apply the implications of Charlton's own understanding of human nature to personal ethical questions more widely. On multi-culturalism, it would have been fruitful to explore the possibility that ethical systems can be partly shared and partly divergent (an implication of some versions, at least, of natural law theory), which might give more room for circumscribed subsidiarity within cultures and educational systems. Finally, Charlton's social reading of salvation might benefit from closer engagement with sympathetic readings by New Testament scholars such as N.T. Wright.