Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-gbm5v Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T09:43:15.713Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Problem of Evil

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 February 2024

Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Extract

Core share and HTML view are not available for this content. However, as you have access to this content, a full PDF is available via the ‘Save PDF’ action button.

We are often told that there is something called ‘the problem of evil’. What is this supposed to be? And how should we respond to it?

It is usually understood as a problem for classical theism (sometimes just called theism), supporters of which are commonly called theists. According to classical theism, God is all-knowing, all-powerful, and allgood. In the world around us, however, we discover a great deal of pain and suffering. We also find a great deal of moral evil—morally culpable actions (or refusals to act) which diminish both those who are morally bad and those around them. The problem of evil is commonly seen as the problem of how the existence of God can be reconciled with the pain, suffering, and moral evil which we know to be facts of life. And it has often been said that they cannot be. Thus it has been urged that the problem of evil constitutes grounds for disbelief in God.

The argument here has taken two forms. First, it has been said that evil is evidence against there being a God—that evil shows the existence of God to be unlikely. Second, it has been held that evil is proof that there could not be a God. The idea here is that theists are caught in a contradiction. They cannot say both that there is evil and that God exists. Since they can hardly deny that there is evil, it follows that God does not exist.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © 1992 Provincial Council of the English Province of the Order of Preachers

References

1 McClosky, H.J., 'God and Evil', Philosophical Quarterly 10 (1960), p.97.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

2 Eddy, Mary Baker, Science and Health with Key to the Scriptures (Boston, 1971), p.257Google Scholar.

3 The Existence of God (Oxford, 1979, revised edition, 1991), pp.210Google Scholar f.

4 The Existence of God, pp.210 ff. For development of this position by Swinbume see also ‘Knowledge from Experience, and the Problem of Evil’ in Abraham, William J. and Holtzer, Steven W. (ed.), The Rationality of Religious Belief (Oxford, 1987)Google Scholar.

5 Evil and the God of Love (2nd edn., London, 1977), pp.372Google Scholar ff.

6 See The City of God, Book II.

7 The Problem of Pain (London, 1940), pp. 122Google Scholar f.

8 God, Freedom and Evil (London, 1975), p.58Google Scholar. In speaking of non‐human agency as he does, Plantinga is not asking us to believe that there are non‐human agents responsible for evil. He is asking us to note a possible explanation for certain kinds of evil. As Plantinga puts it, he is concerned to offer a ‘defence’ rather than a ‘theodicy’. See God, Freedom and Evil, p.28.

9 Logic Matters (Oxford, 1972), p.305Google Scholar.

10 Job 9:22–23; Luke 13:2–3; John 9:3.

11 The Concept of Prayer, p.93.

12 The Brothers Karamazov, trans. Constance Garnett (London, 1950), vol. 1, part II, book V, chap. IV, p.250.

13 A similar line is pressed by Kenneth Surin in Theology and the Problem of Evil (Oxford, 1986), pp.80 ffGoogle Scholar.

14 'A Lecture on Ethics', The Philosophical Review 74 (1965)Google Scholar.

15 See Brown, Stuart C. (ed.), Reason and Religion (Ithaca and London, 1977), p.115Google Scholar.

16 McCabe, Herbert O.P., God Matters (London, 1987), p.31Google Scholar. Cf. Aquinas, Summa Theologiae, Ia,22,2.

17 Rowe, William L., ‘The Problem of Evil and Some Varieties of Atheism’, American Philosophical Quarterly 16 (1979)Google Scholar, reprinted in Adams, Marilyn McCord and Adams, Robert Merrihew (ed.), The Problem of Evil (Oxford, 1990)Google Scholar.

18 Cf. Wykstra, Stephen J., ‘The Humean Obstacle to Evidential Arguments from Suffering: On Avoiding the Evils of “Appearance”’, International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 16 (1979)Google Scholar, reprinted in Adams and Adams (ed.), op. cit.

19 . Mackie, J.L., ‘Evil and Omnipotence’, Mind 64 (1955)Google Scholar, reprinted in Adams and Adams (ed.), op.cit., p.33.

20 The Presumption of Atheism, p.88.

21 The Future (Oxford, 1989), p.229Google Scholar.

22 Summa Contra Gentiles III, 67.

23 Herbert McCabe O.P., God Matters, p. 14.

24 McCabe, op.cit, p.15. For the same view, see Ross, James F., ‘Creation II’, in Freddoso, Alfred J. (ed.), The Existence and Nature of God (Notre Dame and London, 1983)Google Scholar, and Grisez, Germain, Beyond the New Theism (Notre Dame and London, 1975)Google Scholar, Chapter 18.

25 God Matters, p 36

26 Williams, C.J.F., ‘Knowing Good and Evil’, Philosophy 66 (1991), p.238CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

27 Cf. Richard Swinburne, The Coherence of Theism, chap.11.

28 Cf. Eichrodt, Walter, Theology of the old Testament, Vol.1 (London, 1961), p.240Google Scholar.