1. Introduction
The business and human rights movement is at a critical juncture. On the one hand, key discursive and agenda points of the past decade have successfully permeated public discourse and policymaking, marking a transition from soft obligations to hard law. A pivotal example is human rights due diligence (HRDD), which was introduced as a soft obligation in the context of the UN Guiding Principles on Business and Human RightsFootnote 1 in 2011 and has now evolved into a legal obligation in several national legislations and in the EU. On the other hand, this ‘mainstreaming’ of the business and human rights agenda elicits the concern that its impact on the lived realities of global production might be negligeable. The relative ease with which corporate actors appear to be adopting HRDD obligations, even voluntarily, raises questions about the framework’s sufficiency or susceptibility to co-optation.Footnote 2 Therefore, as monitoring obligations and mechanisms of accountability become legally binding, the business and human rights movement finds itself at an existential crossroad, where mere calls for hard obligations are no longer sufficient. One possible direction is the push for more compliance and enforcement, coupled with targeted reforms addressing particular shortcomings of the various emerging business and human rights frameworks. While this incremental strategy is consistent with the historical trajectory of the movement, our Symposium seeks to push the boundaries of the discourse further, towards new institutional imaginaries and a yet-to-be-articulated substantive agenda on corporate power.
In our attempt to redefine the parameters of the debate, we draw on the emerging scholarship of Law and Political Economy (LPE), while also building on a broader ‘disciplinary turn’ among international lawyers who are increasingly focusing on questions of political economy.Footnote 3 Much like business and human rights scholarship, LPE scholarship has targeted the social ramifications of private power. LPE provides a lens through which to interrogate the sources of private power – giving shape, in turn, to normative implications that may infuse the business and human rights agenda. A centripetal discursive point of LPE literature has been the constitutive role law plays in the economy: how, in other words, legal rules and legal entitlements are not merely an external regulation of supposedly pre-political, ‘natural’ economic interactions between private actors but rather constitute the very building blocks of the economy. The assertion that law – through both its prohibitions and implicit permissions – constitutes the foundational infrastructure of national and global economies challenges the influential BHR premise of ‘governance gaps’, which points to a disjunction between the factual reality of economic forces and the limited normative reach of legal regimes.Footnote 4 In unpacking the sources of ‘economic forces’, an LPE perspective to business and human rights goes beyond closing ‘governance gaps’ by extending the rule of law through new norms of transparency, monitoring, and accountability. Instead, we argue that an LPE approach calls for the identification and transformation of the legal structures that facilitate the accumulation of private power in the first place, which in turn leads to predictable patterns of human rights violations. In this way, our argument critiques the revamped agenda of ‘embedded liberalism’,Footnote 5 which shapes instruments like HRDD and promotes embedding business within social institutions, public interests, and social purpose. Rather, we argue that corporate power is not an inevitable fact and an insurmountable reality that needs to be leveraged and harnessed (e.g., through HRDD) but largely the product of deliberate institutional arrangements and, thus, susceptible to fundamentally different orderings. Our ambition is that shifting the gaze to the deliberate legal infrastructure of the global economy, rather than its insufficient reach, may contribute to and enrich the institutional imagination within the BHR field and discourse.
However, our argument also seeks to avoid the danger of halting the interrogation of root causes of human rights violations too soon.Footnote 6 While law plays a key role in enabling the kind of socio-economic formations with the propensity to perpetuate human rights violations, it would be naïve to ignore the patterns according to which legal rules themselves unfold. Put differently, the fact that law consistently and predictably enables practices associated with human rights violations can be seen through the lens of a ‘false contingency’:Footnote 7 far from being pure products of contingent legal choice, the regimes that enable human rights violations encompass a kind of necessity resulting from systemic constraints imposed on the legal system. This shifts the attention to the social relations that condition the production of legal text and meaning. The question, then, becomes not only how the institutional environment enables the practices in question but how it reflects their structural necessity for the maintenance of existing social relations of production. Inspired by these two stages of interrogation, the ‘legal-institutional’ and the ‘legal-social’, our article outlines two modes of critique: an ‘internal’ critique that seeks to forge alternative institutional orderings, and an ‘immanent’ critique that emphasizes the role of collective action and social movements in transforming the underlying social relations of production. We conclude our argument by exploring potential intersections between these modes of critique, focusing on the heuristic of ‘non-reformist reforms’ as a pathway to modify relations of power, empowering those subjected to corporate power by enhancing democratic control over the economy.
In Section 2, we recount how the hegemonic approaches in business and rights have focused on filling ‘governance gaps’ and creating more accountability for corporations’ negative effects on human rights. In Section 3, we critically examine this key, action-underpinning concept of ‘governance gaps’, drawing on its conceptualization in John Ruggie’s influential work. We problematize the ensuing normative agenda of embedded liberalism, using the analytical lenses of LPE scholarship. Our critique aspires to expose the institutional foundations of private power, drawing attention to how attempts to ‘publicize’ private actors and harness private governance operate in conditions of ‘false necessity’ that present corporate power as an inevitable fact, masking the historicity of the arrangements that have made it the reality that it is. In Section 4, we move from the ‘legal-institutional’ to the ‘legal-social’ stage of interrogation and we nuance the argument presented in Section 3 by delving deeper into the imbrication of law within global social relations of production. This also leads to the emergence of the two directions of critique, ‘internal’ and ‘immanent’, as well as to some initial reflections on how these directions of critique may be bridged. The Conclusion briefly summarizes our findings.
2. Business and Human Rights against corporate power: Filling ‘governance gaps’, expanding accountability
The BHR movement emerged as a somewhat belated response to the significant, and crucially, what was perceived as unchecked power of transnational corporations and their capacity to negatively impact human rights.Footnote 8 Pointing to the example of the Atlantic slave trade, Nadia Bernaz emphasizes that while many scholars view modern globalization as the impetus for the movement, corporations have long been responsible for harmful conduct.Footnote 9 Anita Ramasastry points to more contemporary examples such as so-called conflict diamonds, the use of child labour and the level of working conditions in the apparel industry, and the role of technology companies in human rights abuses as triggering often multistakeholder initiatives to reduce the negative impact of companies.Footnote 10 Ultimately, the combined impact of many such situations and responses to individual crises led to the emergence of a more coherent BHR movement, which has focused on addressing ‘governance gaps’ and efforts to create more (legal) accountability for corporations’ negative effects on human rights.Footnote 11
The backdrop of the discourse around ‘governance gaps’ has been the state-centric framework of international human rights lawFootnote 12 established after the Second World War to prevent recurrence of the atrocities perpetrated by states.Footnote 13 This framework does not allow for the direct application of human rights treaties at the international level: businesses can neither be party to international human rights treaties nor be the subject of complaints before international courts and UN human rights treaty monitoring bodies. In other words, international human rights law was developed with a vertical framework, to regulate the relationship between individuals and the state rather than relationships between private actors (e.g. businesses and individuals).
In the confines of this state-centric framework, BHR theory and practice has regularly proceeded from a conceptual division between material facts on the ground – corporate power – and the normative reach of legal regimes.Footnote 14 By way of response, various theories have emerged to extend the rule of (international human rights) law to corporations. In particular, theories of direct and indirect horizontal effect have been proposed that envisage, or allow, human rights law to be applied in cases concerning human rights abuse in which businesses are implicated to different extents.Footnote 15 Direct horizontal effect would comprise the direct applicability of human rights law provisions to businesses (substantive direct horizontal effect) and allow for their enforcement by victims (procedural direct horizontal effect).Footnote 16 Rather than focusing solely on businesses, some theories propose the notions of ‘shared responsibility’ or ‘multi-duty bearer regimes’ to account for the contribution of both states and private actors to human rights abuses.Footnote 17 Justifications for direct horizontal effect vary, with some commentators pointing towards the limitations of the state-centric approach in international human rights lawFootnote 18 and others finding a basis in our understanding of human rights themselves rather than human rights law.Footnote 19 Yet other theories of direct horizontal effect are grounded in the ‘characteristics of corporate activity’ and the relationship between a business and duty-bearers and rights-holders under the current legal framework.Footnote 20
In contrast, indirect horizontal effect theories are often grounded in positive state obligations that require domestic regulatory efforts to ensure that businesses ‘“indirectly” comply with human rights duties by requiring private actors to refrain from interfering with individual rights’.Footnote 21 Other approaches to indirect horizontal effect rely on the recategorization of private actors as public actors in situations where private actors fulfil public functions usually conducted by the state, such as the provision of public services.Footnote 22 Additionally, particularly in the context of national private law, ‘value-driven’ and ‘weak’ indirect horizontal effect as well as ‘background horizontality’ have been discussed, which involve courts interpreting private law in a way that invokes the values protected by human rights.Footnote 23
Pockets of practice applying a degree of indirect horizontal effect exist at the national level,Footnote 24 in the jurisprudence of the European Court of Human Rights,Footnote 25 the Inter-American Court of Human Rights,Footnote 26 and in the individual communications and general comments of UN human rights treaty monitoring bodies.Footnote 27 Various approaches are taken but the most common at the international and regional levels is the application of states’ positive obligations with broad interpretations of law and creative legal bases within the confines of applicable legal frameworks.Footnote 28 At the national level, various approaches are taken. One interesting strand of case law on foreign direct liability within European countries has seen several efforts to hold businesses directly accountable for contributing to human rights abuse through the duty of care.Footnote 29 Such cases are grounded in tort law rather than human rights lawFootnote 30 and the judiciary has been careful not to ‘lift the [corporate] veil without a legislative mandate’.Footnote 31 However, in a significant climate change case against Shell in 2021, a Dutch court relied on the UN Guiding Principles on Business and Human Rights (UNGPs) among other soft-law initiatives to interpret Dutch tort law on the duty of care,Footnote 32 giving human rights a significant role in judicial decision-making.
Beyond the courts, the attempt to fill in the ‘governance gaps’ that emerge from the disjunction between social realities and the normative reach of legal regimes has also influenced policy, with the most recent development being the proliferation of HRDD instruments and the aspiration to internalize human rights compliance within corporate structures. At the EU level, the European Commission’s draft Directive on Corporate and Sustainability Due Diligence (CSDDD) envisages obligations for businesses falling under its scope. This includes various provisions on HRDD, including the adoption of human rights policies and human rights impact assessments. Nationally, several countries have adopted or begun the legislative process for binding national legislation containing mandatory HRDD standards. Despite the varied content and scope of different HRDD legislation, there is undeniably a growing momentum for hard law obligations for businesses regarding human rights at the national level. The impact of such legislation remains largely to be seen, but concerns have been voiced that the instruments focus too much on procedure to the detriment of substance and rely too heavily on a market-based model of accountability.Footnote 33
Despite partial victories and the clear success in mainstreaming the BHR discourse, prevailing approaches centring around the impetus to fill in the governance gaps created by processes of globalization have not provided a ‘silver bullet regulatory solution to corporate unaccountability’Footnote 34 nor fundamentally challenged the underlying roots of corporate power.Footnote 35 A first level of critique draws attention to the sociological dimension of corporate power. For instance, theories and practice of indirect horizontal effect do not account for the authority that multinational businesses can hold over states – particularly those with a keen interest in foreign direct investment.Footnote 36 Additionally, the movement has experienced powerful pushbacks from businesses against efforts to achieve corporate accountability on all levels, with effective resistance to the adoption and content of hard law (e.g. by the extractive industry in Canada and by European businessesFootnote 37) and policies (e.g. by the tobacco industry).Footnote 38 The lobbying power of businesses over corporate responsibility initiatives has extended on all levels,Footnote 39 including their role in global human rights governanceFootnote 40 and influencing the content of laws and policies as well as their enforcement.Footnote 41 Further, although initiatives such as the UNGPs have been a crucial stepping stone to hard law, their impact in practice has been questionable.Footnote 42 Finally, the ‘orthodox view’ and application of international human rights law simultaneously fails to consider the relative power of corporations in comparison with statesFootnote 43 and to sufficiently clarify standards of behaviour expected of businesses vis-à-vis human rights.Footnote 44 Ultimately, despite a now significant global BHR movement, we still witness countless negative human rights impacts implicating businesses.Footnote 45
Yet, a deeper level of critique extends to the very diagnosis of ‘governance gaps’ and the ensuing normative agenda of ‘embedded liberalism’ through corporate accountability and the currently prominent instrument of human rights due diligence. In the following section, we will unpack this direction of critique, drawing from the scholarship of Law and Political Economy.
3. Rethinking ‘governance gaps’: A critique of ‘embedded liberalism’
Emerging in a context of accelerating social crises, LPE scholarship has also recognized the pernicious role of private power.Footnote 46 Rather than an artefact of horizontal, social relations, private power is understood to be a product of law and institutional arrangements, manifesting through legally constituted forms of coercion. Think, for example, of social relations of employment and wage labour, the possibility to use and exclude others from accessing productive resources, or regimes of limited liability associated with incorporation: the private power inherent in these institutionalized interactions is underpinned by legal rules and allocations of legal entitlements that confer state-backed coercive power.Footnote 47 Indeed, legal rules and entitlements, such as property rights or the advantages of the corporate form, confer to their holders the power to restrict socially available choices of other parties.Footnote 48 Contrary to the liberal defence of markets as freedom- and utility-maximizers,Footnote 49 the legal realist insight underpinning LPE stresses the zero-sum nature of rights, where an allocation of an entitlement to one imposes an onus on another.Footnote 50 Seen through this lens, market exchanges, including the selling of labour power, are exposed as voluntary only within the confining and coercive framework set by law and in a landscape defined by a prior distribution of property rights. For example, the owner’s right to exclusively benefit from productive resources, a fundamental aspect of property rights, implies a legal obligation for non-owners to refrain from accessing these resources without the owner’s consent.Footnote 51 As Robert Hale underlines:
unless, then, the non-owner can produce his own food, the law compels him to starve if he has no wages, and compels him to go without wages unless he obeys the behests of some employer. It is the law that coerces him into wage-work under penalty of starvation.Footnote 52
This analysis positions the state and its public power as both the source of such entitlements, and as their ultimate guarantor through its monopoly on the use of force. The centring of public power is manifest in Hale’s further critique of property rights:
Ownership is an indirect method whereby the government coerces some to yield an income to the owners. When the law turns around and curtails the incomes of property owners, it is in substance curtailing the salaries of public officials or pensioners.Footnote 53
The assimilation of property owners to public officials or pensioners is indicative of the institutionalist mindset that sees private property as an artificial construct and product of state power. While this account halts the analysis at the level of state power,Footnote 54 it marks an important step in demystifying private power. By denying property – and by extension private power – a naturalistic foundation, the realist position pre-empts critiques of regulation as an infringement on private autonomy. Instead, it reframes regulation as a re-balancing of the rights, duties, and coercive power of different actors.
Framing the economy, and the private power accumulated therein, as legally constituted can be transposed to the global level.Footnote 55 Critical perspectives on the global economy emphasize that it is predominantly shaped by a complex assemblage of rules and institutions.Footnote 56 This warns against an exclusive focus on the institutions of international economic law as the supposed rules of the global political economy. Instead, the global political economy encompasses national private law, corporate law, conflict of rules regimes, etc.Footnote 57 Centring public power manifesting through legal institutions signifies a shift in perspective concerning the nexus between law and economy: it accentuates the primacy of the former in shaping the latter. For example, while it is acknowledged that changes in the global economy, such as the shift to offshore outsourcing, have profound implications for public governance, it is often forgotten that these changes did not occur in a vacuum but were largely a product of new institutional arrangements – in this case, reforms of trade and market liberalization, intellectual property protection, or labour under-regulation associated with export-led growth.
A portrayal of the global economic order as replete with law challenges the influential BHR premise of governance gaps. John Ruggie has eloquently posed the terms of the debate:
The root cause of the business and human rights predicament today lies in the governance gaps created by globalization – between the scope and impact of economic forces and actors, and the capacity of societies to manage their adverse consequences. These governance gaps provide the permissive environment for wrongful acts by companies of all kinds without adequate sanctioning or reparation. How to narrow and ultimately bridge the gaps in relation to human rights is our fundamental challenge.Footnote 58
A key analytical tool that underpins the ‘governance gaps’ diagnosis and conditions the normative agenda that follows it is the Polanyian notion of embeddedness/disembeddedness. In his early and influential work, International Regimes, Transactions, and Change: Embedded Liberalism in the Postwar Economic Order, Ruggie explicitly draws from Karl Polanyi to outline an agenda of ‘embedded liberalism’. More specifically, he uses the dynamic of Polanyi’s ‘double movement’ to explain the ascendance and subsequent constraint of market rationalities in the global economic order. According to Polanyi, ‘double movement’ denotes the deliberate push for free markets and trade that disembedded the economy from social life and relations, only to be followed by a spontaneous reaction of society seeking to constrain and re-embed the economy through regulation and forms of economic planning.Footnote 59 Ruggie returns multiple times to this ideal of ‘embeddedness’, arguing at a later point in time that ‘markets work optimally only if they are embedded within broader social and legal norms, rules, and institutional practices’.Footnote 60 However, while Ruggie acknowledges Polanyi’s historical contextualization of disembedding the economy as an intentional and deliberate process (per Polanyi, ‘laissez-faire was planned’), he differentiates his analysis by underplaying this element of deliberate design and by focusing, instead, on the social dynamics that shape institutions (i.e., the political ascendance of the middle class).Footnote 61 This creates an explanatory formula that can be replicated in the context of globalization. In other words, for Ruggie, the mobility of global capital and the rise of multinational corporations has led the economy to be disembedded from social life, threatening the global social fabric as societies lack the tools to control such centrifugal dynamics. In this account, market expansion follows its own expansionary logic.
We argue that this portrayal overlooks the institutional preconditions for the social dynamics it describes. Polanyi’s powerful claim that ‘laissez-faire was planned’ requires addressing the public power that made the emergence of such dynamics possible in the first place. Indeed, our analysis challenges the concept of ‘governance gaps’ and highlights the deliberate institutional design that underpins globalization. From our perspective, it is precisely legality – and not the lawlessness that ‘governance gaps’ allude to – that facilitates the forms of exploitation and structural inequality that shape our political economy.Footnote 62 In other words, attributing, for example, instances of unfree labour at the base of supply chains to the disjunction between private corporate power of transnational corporations and local enforcement capacities misses the target by omitting how this private power (‘economic forces’) is generated in the first place. The emergence of such private power is neither a natural given nor historically contingent and accidental.Footnote 63 Rather, it is a historical product of existing legal regimes and institutional constellations and the global social relations of production these enable. As such, instances of unfree labour are not an inadvertent and unfortunate product of governance gaps but rather the symptomatic expression of deliberate institutional arrangements that generate ‘economic forces’ with both the propensity and the relative capacity to maximize exploitation. Unfree labour, then, unfolds as the predictable result of legal and contractually permissible price pressure exerted to suppliers in the global periphery by transnational lead firms structured around shareholder primacy and profit-maximization, which maintain their globally dominant position through regimes of incorporation and limited liability, investment protection, robust intellectual property rights, labour under-regulation, contractually circumscribed modes of conflict resolution, etc.
The diagnosis of disembeddedness leads Ruggie to a normative agenda of ‘embedded liberalism’ to constrain free market rationalities and ‘re-embed’ the economy within social life. In Ruggie’s earlier work on global trade, this meant embedding the liberalism of free trade within a deeper commitment to an interventionist programme of governmental social action.Footnote 64 This privileged the state as an actor of global governance, giving priority to international co-operation. However, fast-forward almost 30 years later, and the vision of embedded liberalism underlaying the UNGPs is very different.Footnote 65 Building on the premise that the market follows its own expansionary logic, Ruggie’s pragmatic conclusion is that the old hierarchical model resting on comprehensive ex ante regulation is impossible – the state cannot do ‘all the heavy lifting’ to meet societal challenges.Footnote 66 Tapping into the reconstructive impetus of transnational law and into theories of reflexivity and polycentric governance, Ruggie sketched the contours of a vision where social change would take place within the internal functioning of social systems – including private actors who function as global institutions.Footnote 67 In such an institutional imaginary, the role of the law cannot be the top-down imposition of substantive rationalities, but rather the enhancement of self-reflective capacities and the promotion of the self-limitation of private actors.Footnote 68 Taking the powerlessness of the state as a given and elevating the importance of the ‘courts of public opinion’Footnote 69 as the overseer of corporate conduct, private governance is tasked with filling the ‘governance gaps’ through soft law, contractual governance of the supply chain, and private enforcement. It is in this context that HRDD becomes a key component of Ruggie’s agenda, as it enables to ‘scale up individual Corporate Social Responsibility initiatives to a more systemic level’.Footnote 70 Once again, this obfuscates the role of the state in generating its self-imposed impotence and in the expansion of corporate power – a power which is taken as a given, a cause and a cure, in the institutional imagination of the UNGPs. This attempt to use international law not to plan and regulate but to ‘publicize’ private actors has led to the recurrent critique of corporate power entrenchment and expansion of corporate regulatory authority contrary to democratic principles.Footnote 71
Problematizing the notion of ‘governance gaps’ also triggers a renewed scrutiny of the normative agendas of corporate accountability and HRDD, integral elements of the later agenda of ‘embedded liberalism’. As critical legal approaches have repeatedly shown, calls for corporate accountability for specific instances of misconduct may inadvertently legitimate ongoing exploitation and violence that is not covered by the scope of the case.Footnote 72 This echoes the critique that a human rights framework focused on individual cases of harm and corporate accountability is structurally unsuited to addressing the systemically pernicious effects of corporate power.Footnote 73Addressing a specific instance of harm ex post does not, as a rule, fundamentally challenge the legal framework that made it possible in the first place.Footnote 74 Instead, the harm, albeit a predictable product of institutional design, is framed as an extraordinary instance of illegality or lawlessness that needs to be mended. This could obscure that the fundamental issue is not, for example, how a company’s subsidiary may have once been negligent in its oil pipeline maintenance resulting in environmental damage, but the broader institutional framework that enables the perpetuation of an extractivist economy with the propensity to commit environmental catastrophes again and again. Keeping with current critical accounts of international law, this shifts the emphasis away from new norms of ‘transparency and accountability’ and towards the various pieces of the legal puzzle that already shape and regulate corporate conduct.Footnote 75
Extending a similar line of critique, HRDD, in its effort to mobilize private governance to prevent human rights violations, does not question the institutional foundations of private power. It takes this power as a given – the formula of ‘publicizing’ private actors builds on the presupposition of its existence. While this critique does not necessarily dismiss the potential of HRDD to reconstruct market relations – this ultimately depends on the context of its design and enforcement – it draws attention to how it operates in conditions of ‘false necessity’ that present corporate power as an inevitable fact, masking the historicity of the arrangements that have made it the reality that it is. It is also a critique that problematizes the expansion of the sphere of corporate authority beyond the realm of democratic legitimacy. Not only are corporations tasked with mitigating self-produced harms on the basis of elaborate, self-produced, human rights due diligence plans and risk assessments that corporate outsiders cannot substantively oversee. They are also meant to develop these beneficial policies with only a minimal requirement of ‘stakeholder’ participation that is often unlikely to materialize in the very places where business-related harm takes place, reinstating neo-colonial dynamics and narratives of paternalism.Footnote 76 This type of unilateralism goes against the demand of the ‘Third World’, as a political and juridical project, to subject the conduct of transnational corporations to an international legal framework.Footnote 77 Instead, HRDD points to a path where the limits to corporate conduct are not decided in a centric fashion through international negotiations among sovereign states, but are instead concretely fleshed out by corporations themselves. Given the profit-maximizing rationality of corporate actors, the public interest represented by human rights obligations is translated and coded in economic terms, which ultimately means that regulatory reach becomes dependent on market incentives and sanctions, thus privileging the populations that have the market power to enforce such incentives or sanctions.Footnote 78 The risk is that HRDD devolves into another version of the ‘moral responsibility’ of the ‘developed West’ towards ‘the global poor’.Footnote 79
The shared underpinning of the critique emerging from the recognition of the constitutive role of law in the economy and the very conditions that lead to human rights violations is that harms are products of deliberate institution-building – and not its absence. At first, this appears to frame law and institutions as the root cause of human rights violations. Yet, the question emerges: are the laws and institutions that condition the reproduction and perpetuation of business-related harms in some way contingently deficient – and, thus, amenable to reform – or are they themselves the expression of the very historical malcontent we task them with addressing – and, thus, the root causes really lie elsewhere?
4. Root causes once again
Recent critical perspectives into emerging HRDD legislation have identified the risk that the latter’s proceduralism may obfuscate root causes of human rights violations, misdirecting remedial energies towards mere symptoms.Footnote 80 For instance, Radu Mares seeks to draw attention to root causes at the top of supply chains (corporate conduct), at the bottom of supply chains (supplier conduct), and horizontally (market competition). Mares suggests that the UNGPs were not remiss in directing attention to root causes, as they framed wrongful corporate involvement through causation, contribution, or linkages.Footnote 81 The example Mares gives, drawing from the UN Interpretive Guide of the corporate responsibility to respect human rights, is that of a ‘buyer company’s purchasing practices that squeeze suppliers leading to corner-cutting and infringements of worker rights’.Footnote 82
At first, this might appear identical to the example of unfree labour and price pressure used in the previous section. Our analysis, however, seeks to take the inquiry about root causes deeper. First, the Interpretive Guide’s example is already rather limited, referring to ‘changing product requirements for suppliers at the eleventh hour without adjusting production deadlines and prices, thus pushing suppliers to breach labour standards in order to deliver’.Footnote 83 Implicitly, this example reproduces the logic of exception, framing human rights violations within GVCs as singular events, rather than ongoing, continuous exploitation emerging in predictable patterns. Yet, more crucially, our analysis asks two questions that Mares stops short from asking. Mares asks, ‘what are the root causes of worker rights infringements in GVCs’ and finds an answer in ‘buyers purchasing practices’. Taking the inquiry one tier deeper requires asking what enables these purchasing practices in the first place. This leads to the institutionalist dimension of our argument, which, as sketched above, highlights how legal rules of national and international law, including rules of permission, shape the institutional environment that enables such purchasing practices. Yet, if the answer to the question ‘what enables such practices’ is ‘law’, this prompts a second tier of inquiry: What makes law consistently and predictably enable such practices? This shifts the attention to the social relations that condition the production of legal text and meaning. Therefore, while our analysis starts by dismissing a simplistic analytical focus on the social that frames law as simply an external regulator (e.g., mere ‘purchasing practices’), it only exposes the institutional underpinnings of the social (i.e., ‘what enables purchasing practices’) to eventually return to a more complicated picture of the social in the inquiry for root causes (i.e., ‘what enables the enabler’). This leads to a legal institutionalist account that takes seriously the imbrication of law within social relations of production. As such, the question becomes not only how the institutional environment enables the practices in question but how it reflects their structural necessity for upholding this very institutional environment and the social relations that define it.
Uncovering the constitutive role of law in the business and human rights predicament can then lead critique in two different directions: that of an ‘internal’ and that of an ‘immanent’ critique. Internal critique takes the first of the two options laid out in the conclusion of the previous section, staying at the first tier of inquiry of ‘what enables such practices’. The constitutive argument lends itself to an understanding of root causes as embedded within legal regimes, with the ultimate ambition to suggest alternative institutional orderings. For instance, attributing unfree labour to regimes of contractual governance, permissible price pressure, intellectual property rights protection, etc., implies that a different institutional setup would be possible and could eliminate the root causes of worker rights infringements. While critique in that vein could assume different degrees of radicality and depth (is the ‘root cause’ a recent policy shift? Is it the constitutionally articulated property rights regime? Is it a complex and intertwined patchwork of different legal rules and regimes?), the fix is located at the level of institutions. This type of critique accommodates a certain degree of voluntarism, whereby assuming control of legal coding could restructure the economy and rebalance power asymmetries in such ways that would fundamentally address human rights violations.Footnote 84
Yet, this type of internal critique remains vulnerable to an objection, forcefully articulated by Susan Marks in her seminal piece on Human Rights and Root Causes: it halts the investigation of root causes too soon.Footnote 85 It evades the second tier of analysis, namely ‘what makes law and institutions consistently and predictably enable such practices’. While the underpinning legal background plays without a doubt a crucial role in creating the conditions for business-related harms, Marks doubts the implicit message of straightforward institutionalist accounts that ‘if only bad procedures, rules and ideas were replaced and good ones adhered to, the miseries with which human rights are concerned would go away’.Footnote 86 As Marks correctly notes, this halt of investigation privileges the state as the primary agent of change. It thus draws the contours of a critique that is insufficiently material, as it excludes social relations of production both from its analytical scope and from its normative arsenal. In other words, by remaining at the level of legal institutions, such internal critique fails to explain patterns, regularities, and consistency in distributive outcomes, which are seen as the products of presumably contingent institutional arrangements. The effect of this analytical position is to concentrate the effort for social transformation at the level of legal coding and institution-building. This could side-line the importance of social movements that aim to directly change social relations and not merely their juridical inscriptions.
Furthermore, for Marks, this type of internal critique poses the risk of misconstruing the cause-and-effect relationship by positioning law as the ultimate causative factor. In a provocative reversal, this would suggest that unfree labour should not be understood merely as an effect or by-product of institutional arrangements. Rather, the existing institutional arrangements are in place precisely to enable the kind of exploitation that may also take the form of unfree labour – unfree labour is, in fact, the cause. This underscores Marks’ critique, for it is one thing to assert that the vulnerabilities of specific communities are caused by legal arrangements, but it is a different thing to suggest that legal arrangements are structurally oriented to reproduce these vulnerabilities.
This analysis lays the groundwork for a critique that confines more narrowly the transformative potential of legal coding. This is a critique which, despite acknowledging the role of the law (rather than its insufficient reach) in defining the business and human rights predicament, it sees law itself as bound by the non-contingent rationalities of global production. Contrary to the prioritization of institutional fixes, this critique reflects a suspicion to instrumental reason and administrative remedies. This is because the instrumentalism evoked by what we named as ‘internal critique’, where law becomes a means to an end, encounters inherent limitations in becoming purposive and, in the process of seeking legal and administrative outputs, ultimately blunts transformative societal energies.
As such, the second type of critique shifts from the ‘legal-institutional’ to the ‘legal social’, focusing on the importance of collective action and social movements in directly challenging (global) social relations of production. This critique is ‘immanent critique’ in that it derives its critical standards rooted from the historical process, rather than through an idealist ‘is/ought’ dipole.Footnote 87 It is a critique that emphasizes the contradiction between social formations and their legitimating ideology – searching, within this ideology, for the seeds of emancipatory practice. Immanent critique within the realm of business and human rights builds upon the observation that the remedial institutions addressing business-related harms (such as HRDD, grievance mechanisms, litigation, regulation, etc.) fall short of fulfilling their inherent promises of human rights and justice in global production. However, contrary to internal critique, the ambitious is not to sketch out legal fixes or institutional blueprints but to defend an openness to societal energies.Footnote 88 This means that immanent critique does not aspire to address specific harms on the basis of given understandings of ‘harms’ and ‘remedy’ but to trace pathways for new social formations that seek to democratize global production. Immanent critique recentres social movements and the lived dimension of participating in global production. In its identification of a contradiction between categories of thought (e.g., human rights) and modes of social being (e.g., exploitation in global production), immanent critique remains agnostic to concrete, palpable normative ends.Footnote 89
While there is a tension between the modes of ‘internal’ and ‘immanent’ critique, it remains possible to conceive of a tenuous bridge between them. This depends on the resurfacing of a materialist element within internal critique, and of a political/juridical element within immanent critique. On the one hand, as the internal critique remains committed to social, political, and institutional imaginaries that would actualize the underlaying promises of the business and human rights agenda, it shares a degree of agnosticism about the institutional means that might achieve this. This means what fundamentally matters is not the form through which business-related human rights harms are addressed (i.e., the state, polycentric modes of governance, bottom-up social movements) but rather the material ends that are pursued through these forms – in other words, how each of these frames affects social relations of production: who is materially empowered and disempowered, who wins and who loses. On the other hand, immanent critique privileges societal energies that may unbalance and restructure social relations of production. Yet, social relations of production should not be understood as merely economic but rather as necessarily taking the form of particular juridical and political relations – ‘modes of domination and coercion, forms of property and social organization’ – which are not merely an external reflection but constituents of these production relations.Footnote 90 This means that political struggle – including struggle about juridical inscriptions – plays a decisive role in the shaping of social relations of production.
However, the different modes of critique still mean privileging different forms of intervention and political participation: While internal critique is ultimately reliant on the state and public power more broadly, immanent critique focuses on social movements and bottom-up grassroots movements. While it is beyond the purposes of this article to elaborate on this extensively, one way to think dialectically about the relationship between top-down and bottom-up politics is the heuristic of ‘non-reformist reforms’. Increasingly employed by activists to ‘conjure up the possibility of advancing reforms that aim not to ameliorate the status quo but call it into question and facilitate transformational change’,Footnote 91 ‘non-reformist reforms’ point to processes of mobilization. Rather than delivering on static, demarcated outputs, ‘non-reformist reforms’ seek to modify decision-making structures and relations of power. Non-reformist reforms in the field of business and human rights would then extend beyond minimizing risks of abuse for vulnerable communities or providing remedies for victims. Instead, for example, they would concentrate on material ends related to community empowerment, enabling economic democracy, and subjecting profit-oriented production under the kind of social control that would fundamentally address root causes.
5. Conclusion
Our article aimed to uncover the institutional underpinnings of private power, illustrating how efforts to ‘publicize’ private actors and leverage the regulatory potential of private governance rest on the implicit naturalization of that power. This critique cautions against strategies to merely ‘extend the rule of law’ or ‘fill governance gaps’, urging instead a focus on how existing legal frameworks themselves generate and sustain human rights harms. At the same time, we challenged the view of legal regimes as merely contingent and open to any form of reform, redirecting attention to how social relations of production shape and constrain legal institutions. Finally, we demonstrated how these two levels of analysis and differing perspectives on the role of law in structuring the economy give rise to two distinct directions of critique – the ‘internal’ and the ‘immanent’ – and explored how these critiques can be reconciled through the concept of ‘non-reformist reforms’.