No CrossRef data available.
Article contents
Policy and Relationality in Tort Law: Contractualist Foundations
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 08 April 2025
Abstract
This article examines the relationship between relationality and policy in tort law from an evolutionary perspective. While, as part of the regulatory system, tort law must evolve in response to structural and allocative policy concerns, its ability to do so is limited by the relational normative structure through which it operates and claims moral authority. This tension is often obscured in mainstream tort theory. Drawing on contractualist philosophy—which traces the implications of mutual recognition and respect across structural, allocative, and relational normative contexts—the article develops a principled reasoning framework that avoids rigid hierarchies and ad hoc balancing: negative policy reasons not to adopt tort norms take precedence in choices of regulatory regimes, while positive policy reasons must be diluted and integrated with relational reasons to shape the content of tort norms. This normative framework illuminates tort law’s ability to respond to complex normative challenges while retaining its integrity and unique value as a regulatory tool.
- Type
- Research Article
- Information
- Copyright
- © The Author(s), 2025. Published by Cambridge University Press
References
1 See Ross Grantham & Darryn Jensen, The Proper Role of Policy in Private Law Adjudication, 68 U. Toronto L. J. 187, 191–192 (2018).
2 On the distinction between settled doctrine and legal evolution, see Hanoch Dagan, The Real Legacy of American Legal Realism, 38 Oxford J. Legal Stud. 123 (2018).
3 Scott Hershovitz, The Search for a Grand Unified Theory of Tort Law, 130 Harv. L. Rev. 942, 962 (2017).
4 Gregory C. Keating, Reasonableness and Risk: Right and Responsibility in the Law of Tort 19 (2022).
5 On these paths, see Peter Benson, Should White v Jones Represent Canadian Law: A Return to First Principles, in Emerging Issues in Tort Law 141 (Jason Neyers, Erika Chamberlain & Stephen Pitel eds., 2007).
6 MacPherson v. Buick Motor Co., 111 N.E. 1050 (N.Y. 1916); Donoghue v. Stevenson [1932] AC 562.
7 John C.P. Goldberg & Benjamin C. Zipursky, The Moral of Macpherson, 146 U. Pa. L. Rev. 1733, 1816–1817 (1998); Peter Cane, The Anatomy of Tort Law 17–18 (2007).
8 See Jay M. Feinman, The Economic Loss Rule and Private Ordering, 48 Ariz. L. Rev. 813 (2006).
9 See Dan B. Dobbs, Undertakings and Special Relationships in Claims for Negligent Infliction of Emotional Distress, 50 Ariz. L. Rev. 49 (2008).
10 See Claire McIvor, Third Party Liability in Tort 67–81 (2006).
11 On this complex jurisprudential possibility (that I need not address here), see Steven Schaus, A Simple Model of Torts and Moral Wrongs, 97 Notre Dame L. Rev. 1029 (2022).
12 See Scott Hershovitz, Law is a Moral Practice 16–18, 27–28, 167 (2023).
13 John Gardner, Obligations and Outcomes in the Law of Torts, in Relating to Responsibility: Essays in Honour of Tony Honoré 111, 121 (Peter Cane & John Gardner eds., 2001). For an intriguing defense of the opposite “cynical” view, see Dan Priel, Tort Law for Cynics, 77 Mod. L. Rev. 703 (2014).
14 On tort law’s substantive pluralism, see Keating, Reasonableness and Risk, supra note 4, at 3–8, 61–66, 305–308; John C.P. Goldberg & Benjamin C. Zipursky, The Oxford Introductions to U.S. Law: Torts 30–43, 120–130, 221–225 (2010).
15 John C.P. Goldberg & Benjamin C. Zipursky, Rights and Responsibility in the Law of Torts, in Rights and Private Law 251, 258 (Donal Nolan & Andrew Robertson eds., 2012).
16 John Oberdiek, It’s Something Personal: On the Relationality of Duty and Civil Wrongs, in Civil Wrongs and Justice in Private Law 301, 314–321 (Paul B. Miller & John Oberdiek eds., 2020).
17 On this distinction, see David Miller, National Responsibility and Global Justice 84–86 (2007).
18 John Gardner, The Negligence Standard: Political Not Metaphysical, 80 Mod. L. Rev. 1, 11–12 (2017).
19 On this normative leeway, see generally John Oberdiek, The Wrong in Negligence, 41 Oxford J. Legal Stud. 1174 (2021); Yehuda Adar & Ronen Perry, Negligence Without Harm, 111 Geo. L. J. 187 (2022).
20 H.L.A. Hart, Postscript: Responsibility and Retribution, in Punishment and Responsibility (2nd ed., 2008) 210, 212–214. See also Peter Cane, Role Responsibility, 20 J. Ethics 279 (2016).
21 See Goldberg & Zipursky, The Oxford Introductions, supra note 14, at 78.
23 Dilan A. Esper & Gregory C. Keating, Putting Duty in Its Place, 41 Loy. L. A. L. Rev. 1225, 1232 (2008).
24 Henry E. Smith, Modularity and Morality in the Law of Torts, 4 J. Tort L. (2011).
25 See William Lucy, Philosophy of Private Law 250–254 (2007); Tarunabh Khaitan & Sandy Steel, Areas of Law: Three Questions in Special Jurisprudence, 43 Oxford J. Legal. Stud. 76, 86–90 (2023).
26 Peter Cane, Rights in Private Law, in Rights and Private Law 35, 52–53 (Donal Nolan & Andrew Robertson eds., 2012).
27 H.L.A. Hart, American Jurisprudence Through English Eyes: The Nightmare and the Noble Dream, 11 Ga. L. Rev. 969 (1976).
28 See Jean Thomas, Which Interests Should Tort Protect?, 61 Buff. L. Rev. 1, 2 (2013); Sandy Steel, On the Moral Necessity of Tort Law: The Fairness Argument, 41 Oxford J. Legal Stud. 192, 192 (2021).
29 See, e.g., Guido Calabresi, Toward A Unified Theory of Torts, 1 J. Tort L. 1 (2007).
30 Benjamin C. Zipursky, Pragmatic Conceptualism, 6 Legal Theory 457, 460–467 (2000).
31 John C.P. Goldberg & Benjamin C. Zipursky, Replies to Commentators, 41 L. & Phil. 127, 133 (2022).
32 John C.P. Goldberg & Benjamin C. Zipursky, Recognizing Wrongs 239–240, 279–280 (2020).
33 Jean Thomas, The Elusive Third Way? The Role of Positive Morality in Recognizing Wrongs, 27 Jerusalem Rev. Legal Stud. 74, 80–87 (2023); Timothy Borgerson, The Weakness of Relationality as a Unifying Concept in Tort, 68 Am. J. Juris. 131, 134–140 (2023).
34 Ernest J. Weinrib, The Idea of Private Law 5 (2nd ed., 2012).
35 See id., at 204–214; Jules L. Coleman, Doing Away with Tort Law, 41 Loy. L. A. L. Rev. 1149, 1170 (2008); Arthur Ripstein, Private Wrongs 294 (2016).
36 Ernest J. Weinrib, Reciprocal Freedom: Private Law and Public Right 1–25 (2022).
37 Ripstein, Private Wrongs, supra note 35, at 6–14, 290–295.
38 See Stephen R. Perry, On the Relationship Between Corrective and Distributive Justice, in Oxford Essays in Jurisprudence 237 (Jeremy Horder ed., 2000).
39 Arthur Ripstein, Private Authority and the Role of Rights, 14 Jerusalem Rev. Legal Stud. 64, 82–85 (2016).
40 See Keating, Reasonableness and Risk, supra note 4, at 69–121.
41 See also Stephen R. Perry, Professor Weinrib’s Formalism: The Not-so-empty Sepulchre, 16 Harv. J. L. & Pub. Pol’y 597 (1993).
42 E.g., Ernest Weinrib, Deterrence and Corrective Justice, 50 UCLA L. Rev. 621, 638–640 (2002); John C. P. Goldberg & Benjamin C. Zipursky, Civil Recourse Defended, 88 Ind. L. J. 569, 592–593 (2013).
43 E.g., Jane Stapleton, Comparative Economic Loss: Lessons from Case-Law-Focused ‘Middle-Theory’, 50 UCLA L. Rev. 531 (2002); Nora Freeman Engstrom & Michael D. Green, Tort Theory and Restatements, 14 J. Tort L. 333 (2021).
44 Christopher J. Robinette, Tort Rationales, Pluralism, and Isaiah Berlin, 14 Geo. Mason L. Rev. 329 (2007).
45 On this methodology, see generally Carl Knight, Reflective Equilibrium, in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Edward N. Zalta & Uri Nodelman eds., 2023).
46 E.g. Benjamin Shmueli, Legal Pluralism in Tort Law Theory: Balancing Instrumental Theories and Corrective Justice, 48 U. Mich. J. L. Reform 745 (2015); Cristina Carmody Tilley, Tort Law Inside Out, 126 Yale L. J. 1320, 1388–1392, 1403–1404 (2017).
47 See also Avner Levin, Quantum Physics in Private Law, 14 Can. J. L. & Juris. 249 (2001).
48 See Steven J. Burton, Normative Legal Theories: The Case of Pluralism and Balancing, 98 Iowa L. Rev. 535 (2013); Ronen Perry, Pluralistic Legal Theories, 90 Tul. L. Rev. 647 (2016).
49 See Weinrib, Deterrence and Corrective Justice, supra note 42, at 632.
50 See Keating, Reasonableness and Risk, supra note 4, at 81, 86, 114. See also Gary T. Schwartz, Mixed Theories of Tort Law: Affirming Both Deterrence and Corrective Justice, 75 Tex. L. Rev. 1801 (1997); Guido Calabresi & Spencer Smith, On Tort Law’s Dualisms, 135 Harv. L. Rev. F. 184 (2021).
51 See Hanoch Dagan & Avihay Dorfman, Relational Justice: A Theory of Private Law 4, 22, 32, 54, 62, 170 (2024).
52 John Rawls, Justice as Fairness: A Restatement 40, 182 (Erin Kelly ed., 2001).
53 Id., at 5–6, 15–16.
54 Id., at 10–12, 181–182.
55 Id., at 55–57; John Rawls, Political Liberalism 257–271 (2nd ed., 2005).
56 Kevin A. Kordana & David H. Tabachnick, On Belling the Cat: Rawls and Tort as Corrective Justice, 92 Va. L. Rev. 1279 (2006).
57 Ripstein, Private Wrongs, supra note 35, at 290–295. See also Stephen Perry, Ripstein, Rawls, and Responsibility, 72 Fordham L. Rev. 1845 (2004).
58 See also Miriam Ronzoni, What Makes a Basic Structure Just?, 14 Res Publica 203 (2008); Kok-Chor Tan, Justice, Institutions, and Luck 37–38 (2012).
59 Rawls, Justice as Fairness, supra note 52, at 12.
60 See Samuel Scheffler, Distributive Justice, the Basic Structure and the Place of Private Law, 35 Oxford J. Legal Stud. 213 (2015); Samuel Freeman, Private Law and Rawls’s Principles of Justice, in Liberalism and Distributive Justice 167, 172–179 (2018). On tort law’s political aspects, see also Jenny Steele, How is Tort Law Political?, in Private Law and Practical Reason: Essays on John Gardner’s Private Law Theory 281 (Harry Psarras & Sandy Steel eds., 2023).
61 For an account of social justice as comprehensive and exclusive, see David Blankfein-Tabachnick & Kevin A. Kordana, On Rawlsian Contractualism and the Private Law, 108 Va. L. Rev. 265, 278–286 (2022).
62 John Rawls, A Theory of Justice 11–12 (rev. ed., 1999).
63 Rawls, Political Liberalism, supra note 55, at 228–229.
64 Rawls, Justice as Fairness, supra note 52, at 50.
65 Keating, Reasonableness and Risk, supra note 4, at 119–120.
66 Freeman, Private Law and Rawls’s Principles of Justice, supra note 60, at 170, 187–189.
67 Rawls, Justice as Fairness, supra note 52, at 59–60, 63.
68 Id., at 11–12.
69 Samuel Scheffler, Egalitarian Liberalism as Moral Pluralism, 79 Proceedings Aristotelian Soc. 229, 233 (2005). See also Samuel Freeman, The Basic Structure of Society as the Primary Subject of Justice, in A Companion to Rawls 88 (Jon Mandle & David A. Reidy eds., 2014).
70 Rawls, Political Liberalism, supra note 55, at 397–399.
71 Rawls, A Theory of Justice, supra note 62, at 34.
72 T.M. Scanlon, What We Owe to Each Other 155–156, 189–191 (1998); Rahul Kumar, Contractualism on the Shoal of Aggregation, in Reasons and Recognition: Essays on the Philosophy of T.M. Scanlon 129, 136–138 (R. Jay Wallace, Rahul Kumar & Samuel Freeman eds., 2011).
73 Rahul Kumar, Defending the Moral Moderate, 28 Phil. & Pub. Aff. 275, 286 (2000). See also R. Jay Wallace, The Moral Nexus 136–143, 195 (2019).
74 Aaron James, The Significance of Distribution, in Reasons and Recognition: Essays on the Philosophy of T.M. Scanlon 276, 278, 283 (R. Jay Wallace, Rahul Kumar & Samuel Freeman eds., 2011).
75 Scanlon, What We Owe to Each Other, supra note 72, at 235.
76 Id., at 195, 202–203.
77 Kumar, Defending the Moral Moderate, supra note 73, at 295–296.
78 Scanlon, What We Owe to Each Other, supra note 72, at 153–154.
79 Kumar, Defending the Moral Moderate, supra note 73, at 304–307.
80 T.M. Scanlon, Forms and Conditions of Responsibility, in The Nature of Moral Responsibility: New Essays 89, 105–107 (Randolph Clarke, Michael McKenna & Angela M. Smith eds., 2015). See also Emmanuel Voyiakis, Private Law and the Value of Choice 62–65, 105–106 (2017).
81 T.M. Scanlon, Contractualism and Justification, in Reason, Justification, and Contractualism: Themes from Scanlon 17, 31–32 (Markus Stepanians & Michael Frauchiger eds., 2021).
82 Kumar, Contractualism on the Shoal of Aggregation, supra note 72, at 142, 146.
83 Aaron James, Contractualism’s (Not So) Slippery Slope, 18 Legal Theory 263, 289 (2012).
84 Andrew Lister, Contractualist Alternatives to the Veil of Ignorance, 31 J. Pol. Phil. 177, 188 (2023).
85 Liam Murphy, Nonlegislative Justification, in Principles and Persons: The Legacy of Derek Parfit 247 (Jeff McMahan, Tim Campbell, James Goodrich & Ketan Ramakrishnan eds., 2021).
86 Keating, Reasonableness and Risk, supra note 4, at 6–8, 59–61, 81, 309.
87 Id., at 8–16, 61–68, 107–109, 117–119, 197–199. See, for example, Keating’s discussion of rights against negligently caused pure economic or emotional harm and against battery: id, at 146, 150–152.
88 Gregory C. Keating, Tort, Rawlsian Fairness and Regime Choice in the Law of Accidents, 72 Fordham L. Rev. 1857 (2004).
89 In some places, Keating also relies on Scanlon: e.g. Keating, supra note 4, at 223–225.
90 John Oberdiek, Structure and Justification in Contractualist Tort Theory, in Philosophical Foundations of the Law of Torts 103, 108–112 (John Oberdiek ed., 2014).
91 Id., at 117.
92 Id., at 120.
93 T.M. Scanlon, Reply to Leif Wenar, 10 J. Moral Phil. 400, 403, 405 (2013).
94 James, The Significance of Distribution, supra note 74, at 287; Leif Wenar, Rights and What We Owe to Each Other, 10 J. Moral. Phil. 375, 393 (2013). See also Barbara H. Fried, Can Contractualism Be Saved, in Facing Up to Scarcity 106, 125–127 (2020).
95 Murphy, Nonlegislative Justification, supra note 85, at 251–253.
96 Wallace, supra note 73, at 49–61; Stephen Darwall, The Second-Person Standpoint: Morality, Respect, and Accountability 24, 35–38, 300–304, 320 (2006).
98 Darwall, The Second-Person Standpoint, supra note 96, at 6–13.
99 Stephen Darwall, Bipolar Obligation, in Morality, Authority, & Law: Essays in Second-Personal Ethics I 20 (2013).
100 Wallace, supra note 73, at 82–86, 157–163, 176–177.
101 Id. at 180.
102 Id. at 184–188.
103 Thomas Nagel, War and Massacre, 1 Phil. & Pub. Aff. 123, 136–138 (1972) (claiming that consequentialism portrays moral agents as “benevolent bureaucrats” who distribute benefits and burdens in society).
104 On this societal side of contractualism, see Wallace, supra note 73, at 67–76.
105 On this form of guidance, see generally Jeremy Waldron, Vagueness and the Guidance of Action, in Philosophical Foundations of Language in the Law 58, 65 (Andrei Marmor & Scott Soames eds., 2011); Avihay Dorfman, Foreseeability as Re-Cognition, 59 Am. J. Juris. 163 (2014).
106 See Anita Bernstein, How to Make a New Tort: Three Paradoxes, 75 Tex. L. Rev. 1539 (1997).
107 See Bernard Williams, Afterword: What Has Philosophy to Learn from Tort Law?, in Philosophical Foundations of Tort Law 487, 492 (David G. Owen ed., 1995); Sandy Steel, Justifying Civil Recourse for Wrongs, 27 Jerusalem Rev. Legal Stud. 1, 8 (2023).
108 Anns v. Merton London Borough Council [1978] AC 728.
109 Caparo Industries plc v. Dickman [1990] 2 AC 605.
110 Robinson v. Chief Constable of West Yorkshire Police [2018] AC 736. See also James Goudkamp & Donal Nolan, Robinson v. Chief Constable of West Yorkshire Police: Taking Duty Back to Basics, 16 J. Tort L. 125 (2023).
111 Cooper v. Hobart [2001] 3 S.C.R. 537, 552.
112 Deloitte & Touche v. Livent Inc (Receiver of) [2017] 2 S.C.R. 855, 883. For criticisms of the two-stage structure and its reliance on policy reasons, see Ernest J. Weinrib, Corrective Justice 60–71 (2012).
113 W. Jonathan Cardi, The Hidden Legacy of Palsgraf, 91 B.U. L. Rev. 1873, 1878, 1890–1892 (2011).
114 Restatement (Third) of Torts: Liab. for Physical & Emotional Harm § 7(b) (Am. Law Inst. 2012).
115 Rowland v. Christian, 443 P.2d 561, 564 (Cal. 1968).
117 See Victor E. Schwartz & Christopher E. Appel, Reshaping the Traditional Limits of Affirmative Duties Under the Third Restatement of Torts, 44 John Marshall L. Rev. 319, 325–326 (2011).
118 Brown v. USA Taekwondo, 483 P.3d 159 (Cal. 2021). See also Gregory C. Keating, Putting “Duty” Back on Track, 16 J. Tort L. 301 (2023).
119 See Peter Cane, Responsibility in Law and Morality 13–14 (2002).
120 Tony Honoré, The Dependence of Morality on Law, 13 Oxford J. Legal Stud. 1 (1993). See also Meir Dan-Cohen, Responsibility and the Boundaries of the Self, 105 Harv. L. Rev. 959 (1992); Henry S. Richardson, Institutionally Divided Moral Responsibility, 16 Soc. Phil. & Pol’y 218 (1999).
121 See Julian Jonker, Contractualist Justification and the Direction of a Duty, 25 Legal Theory 200 (2019).
122 See generally George P. Fletcher, The Fault of Not Knowing, 3 Theoretical Inq. L. 265, 279–282 (2002); Leslie Kendrick, Culpability and Negligence, in Oxford Studies in Private Law Theory: Volume 1 137, 150–157 (Paul B. Miller & John Oberdiek eds., 2020).
123 See also Avihay Dorfman, Can Tort Law Be Moral, 23 Ratio Juris 205, 213–217 (2010).
124 See Robert E. Goodin, Apportioning Responsibilities, 6 L. & Phil. 167 (1987).
125 See Andrea C. Westlund, Answerability Without Blame?, in Social Dimensions of Moral Responsibility 253 (Katrina Hutchinson, Catriona Mackenzie & Marina Oshana eds., 2018).
126 John Gardner, From Personal Life to Private Law 23–24, 46–50 (2018). See also Gregory C. Keating, Duty or Right? A Comment on John Gardner’s From Personal Life to Private Law, 15 Jerusalem Rev. Legal Stud. 152, 163–165 (2017).
127 Christopher Essert, The Value of the Neighbour Relation, in Private Law and Practical Reason: Essays on John Gardner’s Private Law Theory 297 (Harry Psarras & Sandy Steel eds., 2023).
128 Jason M. Solomon, Equal Accountability Through Tort Law, 103 Nw. U. L. Rev. 1765 (2009); Stephen Darwall & Julian Darwall, Civil Recourse as Mutual Accountability, 39 Fla. St. U. L. Rev. 17 (2011). See also Scott Hershovitz, Treating Wrongs as Wrongs: An Expressive Argument for Tort Law, 10 J. Tort L. 405, 407–408, 419–420 (2018).
129 Palsgraf v. Long Island Railroad Co., 162 N.E. 99, 100–101 (N.Y. 1928).
130 Oberdiek, It’s Something Personal, supra note 16; Benjamin C. Zipursky, Substantive Standing, Civil Recourse, and Corrective Justice, 39 Fla. St. U. L. Rev. 299 (2011).
131 Keating, supra note 4, at 53.
132 On this substantive constraint, see also Oberdiek, Structure and Justification, supra note 90, at 120; Andrew Robertson, Constraints on Policy-Based Reasoning in Private Law, in The Goals of Private Law 261, 274–279 (Andrew Robertson & Tang Hang Wu eds., 2009).
133 Michael Selmi, Indirect Discrimination and the Anti-Discrimination Mandate, in Philosophical Foundations of Discrimination Law 250 (Deborah Hellman & Sophia Moreau eds., 2013). I address this issue at greater length in Tom Kohavi, Discrimination Law as Private Law, Alb. L. Rev. (forthcoming, 2025).
134 See John Oberdiek, Wrongs, Remedies, and the Persistence of Reasons: Re-Examining the Continuity Thesis, in Private Law and Practical Reason: Essays on John Gardner’s Private Law Theory 161 (Haris Psarras & Sandy Steel eds., 2023).
135 See Giulio Fornaroli, Neglecting Others and Making it up to Them: The Idea of a Corrective Duty, 29 Legal Theory 289 (2023).
136 See Scott Hershovitz, Harry Potter and the Trouble with Tort Theory, 63 Stan. L. Rev. 67, 145 (2010); Jenny Steele, Regulating Relationships: The Regulatory Potential of Tort Law Revisited, in Taking Law Seriously 211 (James Goudkamp, Mark Lunney & Leighton McDonald eds., 2021).
137 See also Andrew Robertson, Justifying Liabilities and Duties, in Justifying Private Rights 201, 219 (Simone Degeling, Michael Crawford & Nicholas Tiverios eds., 2020).
138 On thresholds, see Larry Alexander, Deontology at the Threshold, 37 San Diego L. Rev. 893 (2000).
139 On lexical priority, see Jeremy Waldron, Rights in Conflict, 99 Ethics 503, 513 (1989).
140 On indirect consequentialism, see Brad Hooker, Rule Consequentialism, in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Edward N. Zalta & Uri Nodelman eds., 2023).
141 Oberdiek, Structure and Justification, supra note 90, at 105.
142 On the distinction between general and special norms, see H.L.A. Hart, Are There any Natural Rights?, 64 Phil. Rev. 175, 183–188 (1955).
143 See Dorfman, Foreseeability as Re-Cognition, supra note 105, at 189–193.
144 Thing v. La Chusa, 771 P.2d 814, 826–827 (Cal. 1989).
145 See, e.g., Russell Fraker, Reformulating Outrage: A Critical Analysis of the Problematic Tort of IIED, 61 Vand. L. Rev. 983 (2019).
146 For a flexible approach to this issue, see Mark A. Geistfeld, Social Value as a Policy Based Limitation of the Ordinary Duty to Exercise Reasonable Care, 44 Wake Forest L. Rev. 899 (2009).
147 See Tom Kohavi, Moral Pluralism and Constitutional Horizontality, 37 Can. J. L. & Jur. 475, 485–487 (2024).
148 Stelios Tofaris & Sandy Steel, Negligence Liability for Omissions and the Police, 75 Camb. L. J. 128 (2016).
149 Hines v. Garrett, 108 S.E. 690 (Va. 1921).
150 Kline v. 1500 Massachusetts Ave. Apartment Corp., 439 F.2d 477, 484 (D.C. Cir. 1970).
151 See Nathan F. McGuire, When Does a University Have a Duty to Protect Students from Campus Harms? The Fall of the Bystander Era and the Rise of a Special-Relationship Theory of Duty, 55 Suffolk U. L. Rev. 405, 406–422 (2022); Betsy J. Grey, Preventing Student Suicide: Nguyen v. Massachusetts Institute of Technology, 16 J. Tort L. 107 (2023).
152 Kohavi, Discrimination Law as Private Law, supra note 133.
153 Staub v. Proctor Hospital, 562 U.S. 411, 417 (2011).
154 Rawls, A Theory of Justice, supra note 62, at 93–101, 293–301.
155 Lee v Ashers Baking Company Ltd [2018] UKSC 49.
156 Bull v. Hall [2013] UKSC 73.
157 See Daniel J. Solove & Neil M. Richards, Prosser’s Privacy Law: A Mixed Legacy, 98 Cal. L. Rev. 1887 (2010).
158 Keating, supra note 4, at 223–225, 268–282.
159 See generally Peter Chau, Tort Law and Contractualism, 43 L. & Phil. 393, 401–407 (2024).
160 Robertson, Constraints on Policy-Based Reasoning in Private Law, supra note 132, at 263–264.
161 See Kohavi, Moral Pluralism and Constitutional Horizontality, supra note 147.
162 New York Times v. Sullivan 376 U.S. 254 (1964).
163 See John Oberdiek, Imposing Risk 137–150 (2017).
164 See Christopher J. Robinette, Harmonizing Wrongs and Compensation, 80 Md. L. Rev. 343 (2021).
165 W. Bradley Wendel, In the Duty Wars, I’m Switzerland, 18 Brook. J. Corp. Fin. & Com. L. 35, 58 (2023).
166 See John C.P. Goldberg & Benjamin C. Zipursky, Tort Law and Moral Luck, 92 Cornell L. Rev. 1123, 1134–1137 (2007).
167 Boomer v. Atlantic Cement Co., 257 N.E.2d 870 (N.Y. 1970).
168 See Richard W. Wright, Private Nuisance Law: A Window on Substantive Justice, in Rights and Private Law 491, 503–505, 515–523 (Donal Nolan & Andrew Robertson eds., 2012).
169 Thomas Nagel, Pluralism and Coherence, in The Legacy of Isaiah Berlin 105, 109–110 (Mark Lilla, Ronald Dworkin & Robert Silvers eds., 2001).
170 For concerns in this regard, see Robert Stevens, Torts and Rights 308–314 (2007); Peter Jaffey, Policy and Principle and the Character of Private Law, 11 Juris. 387 (2020).