Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-g8jcs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-27T11:07:27.213Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Dynamic, Regressive, or Obstructionist Courts? What Kinds of Hopes for Judicial Review

Review products

Gerald Rosenberg. The Hollow Hope. 3rd ed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2023.

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  10 October 2024

Rosalind Dixon*
Affiliation:
Scientia Professor of Law, Faculty of Law and Justice, University of New South Wales, Sydney, Australia
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

There has long been debate about the capacity of the US Supreme Court to achieve “progressive” social change. Recent decisions of the court also point to a new worry for American progressives: the court may not only have a limited capacity to drive such change. In some cases, it may actively stand in the way of such change or help reverse it. This invites us to rethink when, or under what conditions, courts are likely to be effective in driving change—whether in a positive, dynamic, or else more obstructionist or regressive direction.

Type
Review Essays
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of American Bar Foundation

Introduction

In 2023, in Dobbs v. Jackson Women’s Health Organization, the US Supreme Court reversed nearly forty years of precedent upholding a constitutional right of access to abortion.Footnote 1 The effects of that ruling are also still being felt, and assessed, across the United States today. What, however, does the ruling say about the long-running debate about the role of the US Supreme Court—and courts generally—in driving social change and, specifically, “progressive” social change? On one view, the Dobbs ruling is likely to have a widespread impact on women’s lives and, especially, on the lives of young and poor women living in “red” states. But, on another, long advanced by court skeptics, it is likely to have only quite modest effects. The argument here is that Roe v. Wade itself in 1973 did little to expand actual access to abortion on the ground, and, hence, its overruling is likely to have limited impact on such access.Footnote 2

One of the most prominent advocates of this “constrained court” view is Gerry Rosenberg. In his seminal work, The Hollow Hope, Rosenberg (Reference Rosenberg2023) amassed a rich array of social scientific evidence to argue that a wide range of high-profile court rulings, including Roe v. Wade, had limited impact. And Rosenberg offered a clear challenge to those with a more “dynamic court” view or one that placed greater faith in courts as agents of “progressive” social change: under what specific conditions, he asked, could one expect courts to be willing and able to deliver such change? It is thus fortuitous that, at the same time the US Supreme Court chose to overrule Roe, we have a third edition of the Hollow Hope, offering an assessment by Rosenberg of the significance of this important jurisprudential shift by the Supreme Court in Dobbs. Rosenberg’s preliminary assessment is also, as we could predict, entirely consistent with the constrained court view: Dobbs, he argues, is unlikely materially to change access to abortion in the United States.

There are, however, powerful voices pointing the other way: US and comparative scholarship emphasizes that, even though courts may be constrained actors, they are still powerful ones in a range of cases, including for those seeking to achieve social change. It is also notable that Dobbs itself reflects a perception among American conservatives that the decisions of the US Supreme Court matter in areas such as abortion, including when it comes to practical legal outcomes on the ground. And while this may reflect certain biases and pathologies in American legal thought, it could also be treated as important confirmation of the “dynamic court” view.

Noting the support within the United States and elsewhere for the dynamic court view, however, does not suggest that it will always, or even usually, fit empirical reality. First, the preconditions for this view are not always—or even usually—in existence in many constitutional democracies. Second, when these conditions are absent, courts may not only be constrained in their capacity to advance positive change, but they may also actively limit or obstruct it or even become active instruments of dismantling previous change. The existence of “qualified hope” for social change must therefore also be seen with clear eyes, which remain alert to the possibilities and dangers of an obstructionist and regressive form of judicial review.

Concepts and Definitions

The starting point for Rosenberg’s (Reference Rosenberg2023) analysis of the US Supreme Court is a distinction between two broad ideal types or conceptions of the court’s role: “the dynamic court” view of courts as effective agents of social change and the “constrained court” view, which emphasizes the limits on courts as agents of such change. Another important part of Rosenberg’s analysis is a call for greater attention to the necessary preconditions for each view to hold or to play out in practice. For instance, Rosenberg points to three broad potential constraints on court-led social change: (1) the bounded nature of constitutional rights; (2) limits on the independence of the judiciary from the other branches of government; and (3) limits on the tools that courts have “to develop appropriate policies and implement decisions” (17–28). Conversely, he suggests that the challenges of implementing judicial orders are likely to be overcome when one or more of four conditions are met: (1) when non-court actors offer positive incentives to induce compliance; (2) when non-court actors impose costs to induce compliance; (3) when judicial decisions can be implemented by the market; or (4) where courts can provide “leverage, or a shield, cover, or excuse, for persons crucial to implementation who are willing to act” (41–43).

Rosenberg also places particular emphasis on examining the role of courts as agents of “progressive” social change. Why? Because at least in the United States, constitutional liberals or progressives have traditionally been the leading proponents of the dynamic court view. It is also important to note, however, that the notion of “progressive” legal or constitutional change may vary over time. And it may also be subject to disagreement: the notion of “progress,” for instance, is notoriously contested and open to differing interpretations based on whether one prioritizes economic or environmental concerns. The same could also be said for constitutional developments.

Tracking the usage of Rosenberg (Reference Rosenberg2023) himself, I use the term “progressive” as effectively synonymous with the political commitments of the Democratic party and its supporters, including commitments to equality and freedom, as Democrats understand those ideas—specifically, commitments to same-sex marriage, broad, legal access to abortion, and race-conscious policies aimed at overcoming historical race-based discrimination. In 2024, this could also be viewed (based on a 2023 Pew Research Center survey of areas of concern to Democrats and Republicans) as a commitment to: eradicating gun violence, promoting the affordability of health care, addressing the threat posed by climate change, and tackling systemic racism and drug addiction (Pew Research Center 2023).

The Constrained Court View

The mid-twentieth century in the United States marked a range of apparent victories for progressives before the US Supreme Court, including the decisions of the court in Brown v. Board of Education in 1954 (ordering the desegregation of American public schools); Griswold v. Connecticut in 1965 (recognizing a constitutional right of access to contraception); and Roe v. Wade in 1973 (upholding women’s right of access to abortion).Footnote 3 The 1990s and early 2000s also extended those gains into the domain of LGBTQIA+ rights. In Romer v. Evans in 1996, the court held that gays and lesbians were protected from laws expressing pure animus toward them or, at the very least, laws that excluded them from ordinary access to the political process.Footnote 4 In Lawrence v. Texas in 2003, the court held that the state of Texas could not criminally prohibit consensual intercourse between adult gay men.Footnote 5 And in Obergefell v. Hodges in 2015, the court held that the Constitution guaranteed same-sex couples the right of access to civil marriage on terms of equality with opposite-sex couples.Footnote 6 It is this apparent role as a “dynamic” court—helping drive progressive social change—that has long been the focus of Rosenberg’s work. Indeed, a central focus of the most recent edition of the Hollow Hope is the court’s role in advancing LGBTQIA+ rights, and what this tells us about the capacity of the court in general to drive progressive social change.

In short, Rosenberg (Reference Rosenberg2023, 555–56) tells us that Obergefell is not only an unusually powerful example of where the court did help drive change but also to a far lesser degree than many observers think—that is, that the court’s role in this context was largely to accelerate pre-existing trends and make them truly nation-wide rather than drive change in any more fundamental sense. In addition, Rosenberg argues that court’s role in this context fits the pattern he has long identified as necessary for court-led social change. In the context of LGBTQIA+ rights, Rosenberg argues, there was ample precedent to rely on and a strong and growing degree of public and elite support. Indeed, Obergefell was decided in conditions of growing public and elite support for gay rights so that, effectively, the court in this context “did what it does best with significant social reform; acknowledged majority and elite opinion and brought outliers up to the national standard” (555).

For Rosenberg, the lessons of the Hollow Hope on abortion are similarly clear: Roe v. Wade did not materially increase the rate of legal abortions in the United States nor the distribution of abortions across states. Rosenberg reports a steady rise in the rate of legal abortions starting two to three years before Roe (that is, in the early 1970s), and this trend continued for approximately two decades afterwards. The trend, however, was modest, and legal abortions remained much higher in blue compared to red states, where Roe should have made the biggest difference in unlocking legal access to abortion in the face of resistance from officials (Rosenberg Reference Rosenberg2023, 266). Abortion rates also began to fall only modestly in the early 1990s as opposition to, and restrictions on, abortion grew and after Planned Parenthood v. Casey in 1992 expressly permitted states to impose a wider range of restrictions on pre-viability abortions (261–65, 291–92).Footnote 7

Progressives might still argue that Roe mattered for who was able to access abortions (for example, the access of poor and young women rather than older, wealthier women). As the fourth section of this article notes, there is also a range of scholars who have suggested that Rosenberg constructs too demanding a test for “success” in this context, downplaying the court’s role in continuing the upward trend in abortion access. But on Rosenberg’s account, overturning Roe should not have been expected to lead to material changes in the overall number of legal abortions—or live births—in the United States. Indeed, Rosenberg (Reference Rosenberg2023, 322–23) draws on his constrained court hypothesis to suggest that the effects of Dobbs, like Roe, may in fact ultimately be quite modest. The high degree of public support for access to abortion means that several states have already acted to guarantee rights of access to abortion and funding for poor women (335–38), and large corporations have done the same for employees in terms of funding for inter-state access to abortion (336). And, for Rosenberg, the role of the market in the provision of abortions means that clinics in some blue states have already expanded their operations (329), and a range of providers are helping ensure access to pharmaceutical abortions (338).

As the next section explores, however, there are a range of important challenges to Rosenberg’s account, both within the United States and comparatively, which might cast doubt on this relatively sanguine view of the impact of Dobbs.

The Counter-Evidence: Comparatively and Pre- and Post-Dobbs

The first and second editions of the Hollow Hope attracted a large number of responses and reviews, and while these reviews consistently praised the seriousness and value of Rosenberg’s data and methods (see, for example, Stumpf Reference Stumpf1993; Hall Reference Hall2009), several leading scholars have questioned the strength of his conclusions. Mark Tushnet (Reference Tushnet2010), for example, questions Rosenberg’s time frame and yardstick for judging success. Social change may be uneven, iterative, and long rather than short term in nature and still count as meaningful and important. Malcolm Feeley (Reference Feeley1992) likewise notes that change may still be significant, even if it falls short of its proponents’ hopes or expectations. Kim Lane Scheppele (Reference Scheppele1992) highlights the importance of the amplification of ongoing trends and political counterfactuals. How do we reliably predict what might have occurred but for court intervention? And how should we view the significance of increased access, even if it is simply the continuation—and acceleration—of an ongoing trend? Malcolm Langford (Reference Langford2021) makes a similar point in the context of courts’ role in expanding access to social rights: assessing impact in this context necessarily involves a complex set of counter-factual judgments.

Ronald Kahn (Reference Kahn1993, 461), Susan Lawrence (Reference Lawrence1992, 813), and Peter Schuck (Reference Schuck1993, 1785) separately question the degree to which Rosenberg overlooks the interaction or “dialogue” between the court and the political branches. In assessing court impact and effectiveness, it seems mistaken to look at the impact of the court alone. Instead, we should consider how it influences the behavior of Congress, state legislatures, and executive branch officials, and how their actions then shape the enjoyment of constitutional rights on the ground (Helfer and Voeten Reference Helfer and Voeten2014). Finally, scholars such as Michael McCann (Reference McCann1992, 722) noted the limits to Rosenberg’s attempts to capture the full range of “indirect” effects to court decisions, including their consciousness-raising benefits for individuals and social movements and mobilizing effects for civil society. A striking feature of the third edition of the Hollow Hope is its attempt to capture and assess the scope of indirect effects of this kind. Rosenberg (Reference Rosenberg2023, 30), for example, examines media and public attention to key issues and finds limited support for the McCann view in this context. But this may under-state these effects in a social or non-traditional media context. There is also an important argument that court decisions can have powerful effects in shaping the identity, self-perception, and sense of possibility among previously marginalized groups (Guinier and Torres Reference Guinier and Torres2014) and can serve as a “focal point” for the organization of social movements seeking to find ways to coordinate their efforts and membership (Landau Reference Landau2013; Brierley Reference Brierley2019).

Other recent research further underscores the importance of organizations and social movements in enforcing constitutional norms. Adam Chilton and Mila Versteeg (Reference Chilton and Versteeg2018), for example, find that formal constitutional rights guarantees have a limited effect on a range of outcome variables (in ways that are reminiscent of Rosenberg’s claims about courts but on an even more global scale). But the exception is where there are organizations with a clear incentive to enforce particular rights. And while Chilton and Versteeg focus on organizations that pre-exist constitutional guarantees, other scholars in comparative constitutional studies point to the iterative relationship between constitutions, courts, and social movement formation (Neumayer Reference Neumayer2005; Simmons Reference Simmons2009; Epp Reference Epp2010; Landau Reference Landau2013; Brierley Reference Brierley2019). And effects of this kind are a lot more difficult to measure in aggregate terms or without careful ethnographic study of particular social movements (Langford Reference Langford, Langford, Cousins, Dugard and Madlingozi2014).

Similarly, one of the potential roles of courts is to alter who has access certain rights and entitlements, either geographically or across race, class, or other lines. For instance, one view of the US Supreme Court’s rights-based jurisprudence is that it serves to expand access to rights (such as contraception or abortion) within conservative or “outlier” states (Strauss Reference Strauss2009, 878). Courts may also expand access to rights for economically vulnerable groups, such as the poor or even, in some contexts, the middle class (Brinks and Gauri Reference Brinks and Gauri2014; Landau and Dixon Reference Landau, Dixon and Katharine2019, 120). The same argument applies to young and otherwise socially vulnerable individuals: courts in this context can and do fill gaps, or help counter “blind spots” in the coverage of existing laws and policies, to the benefit of socially marginalized groups (Berry Reference Berry, Martin and Paul2007). And while Rosenberg (Reference Rosenberg2023, 574) and scholars such as Chilton and Versteeg (Reference Chilton and Versteeg2018) seek to grapple with these distributional effects, they do so imperfectly and in ways that may therefore downplay some of the virtues of judicial review from a progressive perspective.

Another consideration is that the effectiveness of court decisions may vary according to how they are framed. In exploring the factors necessary for a dynamic court view to hold, Rosenberg focuses on factors “external” to courts themselves. But there is a growing body of comparative work suggesting that how courts reason, and especially how they craft their remedies, can impact the chances of successful implementation of court decisions (Landau Reference Landau2014; Dixon Reference Dixon2007, Reference Dixon2023; Langford Reference Langford and Katharine2019, 69). For instance, in cases involving attempts by courts to prompt state action, strong remedies, involving concrete deadlines and ongoing monitoring, will often be important (Dixon Reference Dixon2007; Rodriguez-Garavito Reference Rodríguez-Garavito2010). Hence, the failure of weaker, more delayed, or non-coercive forms of judicial intervention to prompt change cannot be viewed as evidence of the general validity of the constrained court view. In many ways, this dovetails with the more US-focused critique of the Hollow Hope, which emphasizes the importance of “dialogue” or interaction among the various branches of government in assessing patterns of constitutional change (see Lawrence Reference Lawrence1992; Kahn Reference Kahn1993; Schuck Reference Schuck1993). But it gives that critique a more specific cast: it suggests that the extent of social change that courts can achieve is linked to how they reason and the skill with which they combine strong and weak forms of review (Dixon Reference Dixon2023).

There is likewise a growing comparative literature suggesting the promise, as well as the limits to, courts as agents of democratic stabilization or preservation. Constitutional courts, for instance, have responded to threats to democracy through a range of bold judicial decisions, including decisions disqualifying presidential candidates and invalidating proposed constitutional amendments. Efforts of this kind were certainly not a “silver bullet” against the risk of democratic decline or abusive constitutional change (Landau Reference Landau2013; Dixon and Landau Reference Dixon and Landau2015, Reference Dixon and Landau2021). If they have enough time in office and popular and elite support, would-be authoritarians can generally side-step almost all legal constraints, including those imposed by courts. Courts, therefore, can at best serve as a form of “speed bump” on, or deterrent against, certain forms of abusive constitutional change, which under the right conditions can alter the longer-term trajectory of constitutional politics in a country (Landau Reference Landau2013; Dixon and Landau Reference Dixon and Landau2015, Reference Dixon and Landau2021; see also Bugaric Reference Bugaric2019; Roznai Reference Roznai2020).

But this kind of role is still of enormous consequence. And, in some countries, it is linked to a broader role for courts in driving progressive, as well as pro-democratic, change. This does not directly contradict Rosenberg’s core hypothesis. Recall Rosenberg’s identification of constraints on court-led social change. These conditions imply that, to achieve change, courts must be able to draw on some existing degree of support in existing constitutional modalities of argument, public or elite support, and tools and support structures for implementation. The existing research in India suggests that often social change is linked to Rosenberg’s preconditions or constraints being satisfied (Rosenberg, Krishnaswamy, and Bail Reference Rosenberg, Krishnaswamy and Bail2019a; Jacobsohn Reference Jacobsohn2022). For instance, in the context of People’s Union for CL v. Union of India in 2001, a decision of the Supreme Court of India ordering the nation-wide roll-out of a lunch program for Indian students, Rishad Chowdhury and I have suggested that the Supreme Court was able to play a meaningful role in promoting the expansion of the program, in part because of broader political and social movement support and supportive legal and political precedents (Dixon and Chowdhury Reference Dixon and Chowdhury2019).Footnote 8 Similar findings have been made in Colombia and South Africa (Dugard and Langford Reference Dugard and Langford2011).

In my own work, I point to similar preconditions as necessary for successful democracy-reinforcing review by courts on a global scale (Dixon Reference Dixon2023). Further, while far from the norm, I suggest that these conditions are present in a meaningful number of constitutional democracies worldwide (170). In part, this helps explain how and why constitutional courts in countries such as Colombia and Brazil have been successful in high-stakes attempts at “democratic hedging” or democratic preservation in the face of risks of authoritarian resurgence or backsliding (Issacharoff Reference Issacharoff2011). Indeed, there is good evidence that courts can both accelerate positive change and slow down undesirable change, where they enjoy broad public support or at least limited opposition and there is a sufficiently supportive political and legal culture. Rosenberg (Reference Rosenberg2023, 287), himself, notes this in the Hollow Hope, and scholars such as Lee Epstein, Jack Knight, and Olga Shvetsova (Reference Epstein, Knight and Shvetsova2001, 128) have advanced a sophisticated account of the “tolerance interval” for judicial review, which highlights the role of elite attitudes in the success of court-led social change. We arguably lack a clear account of the relative importance of popular versus elite attitudes in this context. There are also important questions about the willingness of courts to engage in review of this kind and how this relates both to the necessary degree of judicial independence for democracy-enhancing review (Dixon and Landau Reference Dixon and Landau2021) and legal-cultural understandings of the role of courts (Roux Reference Roux2009).

But the research we do have arguably gives a somewhat different cast to the overall claim made by Rosenberg: instead of pointing to courts as a hollow hope for progressives, it suggests that they are perhaps closer to a source of what Rishad Chowdhury and I labelled a form of “qualified hope” in certain settings (Dixon and Chowdhury Reference Dixon and Chowdhury2019; see also Rosenberg, Krishnaswamy, and Bail Reference Rosenberg, Krishnaswamy and Bail2019a; Jacobsohn Reference Jacobsohn2022). It also points to a range of other potential factors or conditions as relevant (Jacobsohn Reference Jacobsohn2022).

The pre- and post-Dobbs experience in the United States could also be read as an important challenge to the constrained court view. One hundred days after Dobbs, the Guttmacher Institute (2022) determined that sixty-six clinics across fifteen US states have ceased to provide abortion care. In addition, medical professionals now perceive the risk of prosecution to be higher in clinics, preferring to only provide care in hospital settings (Human Rights Institute 2023, 6). Certainly, many political progressives and conservatives have publicly rejected Rosenberg’s view and acted in ways that show either a sincere or at least strategic commitment to the dynamic court view. US Vice President Kamala Harris (Reference Harris2023) described the decision of Dobbs as creating “a healthcare crisis in America … [where] women … [will] suffe[r] under the consequences of these laws.” Conversely, following the decision, one prominent conservative lawyer made it clear that he and other conservatives saw Dobbs as saving lives: “A year from now,” he suggested, “there will be infants going from milk to soft foods because Dobbs triggered laws and shuttered clinics on Friday and not Monday … they’ll learn to walk, catch fireflies, fall in love, comb grey hair, because of appointments cancelled last Friday. Not just by good fortune but—for the first time in generations—by legal right” (Girgis Reference Girgis2022).

Indeed, it is clear that, for some time, American conservatives have viewed the court as both dynamic and misdirected and devoted considerable political energy to redirecting the court away from that path. The current composition of the court is a product of the efforts of a well-organized group of conservative lawyers, who for several decades have been intent on ensuring that Republican presidents nominate only committed “originalist” judges, with little sympathy for a dynamic court view. That group—largely organized under the umbrella of the “Federalist Society”—has also substantially increased its power and influence over time (Southworth Reference Southworth2008; Hollis-Brusky Reference Hollis-Brusky2019). From its relatively small beginnings in 1982, the society now has over forty thousand members and a large network of lawyers and judges who owe their appointment to its support (People for the American Way Foundation 2002). It has played an increasing role in the process of judicial nomination and confirmation.

There are several explanations for this, which do not undermine the weight of Rosenberg’s claim. One possibility is that many lawyers and legal scholars are reluctant to accept Rosenberg’s findings because of what it means for the relevance of their own work. Lawyers have certainly been more reluctant than political scientists to accept Rosenberg’s findings (Schultz and Gottlieb Reference Schultz and Gottlieb1996), and some scholars attribute this to personal career concerns (Feeley Reference Feeley1992, 758; Powe Reference Powe1992, 1640). Rosenberg (Reference Rosenberg2023, ch. 13) himself notes the appeal of myths of court power and relevance for lawyers. And Richard Delgado (Reference Delgado2008, 147) notes the degree to which, for both lawyers and non-lawyers, the faith in courts to deliver justice in individual cases may spill over to their attitudes toward its role in broader structural reform.

Another possibility might lie in the siloed nature of law as a discipline (see Samuel Reference Samuel2009). There has long been a divide between American law schools and social science faculties, and while scholars such as Rosenberg have consistently sought to bridge that divide both in their scholarship and teaching (Powe Reference Powe1992, 1639), they have inevitably done so with mixed success. The rise of “originalism” in US law schools has also further discouraged deep engagement with social science as compared to history as a discipline (Sunstein Reference Sunstein2023). Other explanations are more asymmetric—that is, they explain why conservatives, rather than progressives, might continue to hold the dynamic court view in contexts such as abortion. Compared even to when the Hollow Hope was published, Americans are far more polarized in what they read and the media and commentary they consume (Dimock and Wike Reference Dimock and Wike2020). The Hollow Hope was always a book that spoke most directly to political liberals (Feeley Reference Feeley1992, 747), even though it was funded by a conservative foundation (Delgado Reference Delgado1993, 1134). And while conservatives in the past might have been curious to understand what leading liberal intellectuals were thinking, this may be less true today than before.

Another potential explanation could be that American conservatives have gained electorally from a belief among voters that overturning Roe would materially change outcomes on abortion in America or actually save (fetal) life, even though it is likely not true, and many have known that to be the case. Rosenberg certainly documents several instances in which conservatives have gained from the perception of the US Supreme Court as a dynamic court. In the context of LGBTQIA+ rights, for example, the Hollow Hope notes the ways in which Karl Rove and the Republican party establishment deliberately sought to use the specter of same-sex marriage as an issue that could drive conservative voter turnout and support (Rosenberg Reference Rosenberg2023, 484–86). Rosenberg (Reference Rosenberg2023, 313, 331) also notes the salience of abortion in support for Republican presidential elections since 2000 (313, 331) and the widespread view, so aptly expressed by Lucas Powe Jr (Reference Powe2009, 311) in this context that Roe was a “gift that ke[pt] on giving—to Republicans.”

Rosenberg places these developments in the context of the forces that can lead to backlash against the court and, hence, the pressure for even the most dynamic courts to become constrained in their impact (Krislov Reference Krislov1992, 370; Brazelton Reference Brazelton2016, 84). Michael J. Klarman (Reference Klarman1994) has also written powerfully about this same form of backlash and its effects on American constitutional practice (see also Graber Reference Graber2011, 37). But one could equally place this story within a narrative about why conservatives have continued to maintain a myth of a dynamic Supreme Court. Another interpretation of these actions, however, would see them as providing important—albeit indirect—support for the dynamic court view. At the very least, it suggests that a large number of legal and political minds in the United States have accepted the dynamic court view as the correct one. And there is a well-established principle pointing to the epistemic value of the judgments of “many minds” (Posner and Sunstein Reference Posner and Sunstein2006, 161). According to this principle, as the number of independent decision makers increases, so too does the probability that their collective decisions or views will be epistemically reliable (Dixon and Posner Reference Dixon and Posner2011).

Dynamic versus Obstructionist or Regressive Courts

Of course, Dobbs was not the only decision handed down by the US Supreme Court in 2023 that disappointed political progressives. In New York State Rifle Assoc v. Bruen in 2022, the court held that to pass muster under the Second Amendment, states must show that gun control measures are consistent with “historical tradition” surrounding gun regulation.Footnote 9 In doing so, the court rejected the approach of lower courts, allowing states to defend even non-traditional measures as reasonable and, hence, greatly restricted the scope for innovative public safety measures, including New York style restrictions on permits to carry firearms in public. And in Students for Fair Admissions v. President and Fellows of Harvard College in 2023, the court held that any form of race-based classification must survive the most demanding forms of strict scrutiny.Footnote 10

Decisions of this kind were also deeply disappointing to political progressives but in a different way from Dobbs. The US Supreme Court, in these cases, was not simply a limited or constrained vehicle for progressive social change. It could be viewed as playing an active role in obstructing such change (the “obstructionist court” view) or helping reverse it (the “regressive court” view), depending on whether one looks backward or forward in time. Bruen in 2022, for example, further limited the scope for states and localities to adopt gun control measures aimed at protecting public safety.Footnote 11 Hence, it led a range of blue and purple states to pause efforts to expand gun control. But it also cast doubt on a range of existing gun control measures in ways that led at least four red states to pass laws allowing residents to carry concealed weapons without a permit (Edelman Reference Edelman2023).

The same could be said for decisions, such as Students for Fair Admissions, which increased the obstacles to racial diversity in universities and the electoral process. The court’s decision made it harder for universities to adopt new measures designed at promoting racial diversity in their entering class (making it an “obstructionist” court). But it also forced universities to reverse prior policies advancing progressive aims—for example, the use of race as a “plus” factor in admissions (making the decision “regressive” in nature). Rosenberg (Reference Rosenberg2023, 6–7) explicitly notes the possibility of this kind of obstructionist role for the court by connecting the idea of an “obstructionist” court to previous periods in the court’s history, including the Lochner court era. The US Supreme Court during this period was notorious for its obstructionist stance: in the face of progressive-era attempts to improve American living and working conditions, the court insisted on the primacy of the property and contract rights of businesses under the Due Process Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment. And in the face of congressional attempts to regulate a range of social harms, the court adopted a narrow, formalistic view of Congress’s power under the Commerce Clause, which largely defeated these efforts at reform. Worse still, when the Great Depression struck and President Franklin Delano Roosevelt sought to pass measures designed to promote economic recovery, the court continued to obstruct these efforts through this same mix of Substantive Due Process and Commerce Clause reasoning. It was only in 1937, with the threat of court-packing by Roosevelt and the famous “switch in time that saved nine”—the shift in stance by Justice Owen Roberts—that the court adopted a more flexible, democratically “responsive” approach to progressive economic regulation (Dixon Reference Dixon2023).

In the rest of the world, the court’s Lochner-era obstructionist stance also continued to reverberate for decades to come, causing progressive constitutional drafters across the globe to adopt constitutional language deliberatively designed to avoid the perils of Lochner-style substantive due process reasoning (Choudhry Reference Choudhry2004). For example, in India, the drafters of the 1950 Constitution studiously avoided adopting a right to liberty, lest it be interpreted by the Supreme Court of India in a Lochneresque vein (Choudhry Reference Choudhry2013). Likewise, in Canada, the drafters of the 1982 Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms chose to enshrine a right to freedom and security of the person that was carefully aimed (if ultimately not successfully so) at limiting the scope for substantive due process reasoning (Hogg Reference Hogg1990).Footnote 12

Yet Rosenberg (Reference Rosenberg2023, 7) suggests that patterns of obstruction, at least, are amply addressed by others, and, hence, his prime focus is on the limits of the court as an agent for progressive change (see, for example, Dahl Reference Dahl1957; McCloskey Reference McCloskey1960). This focus, however, is increasingly hard to square with the most recent decisions of the US Supreme Court as well as with developments in many areas of constitutional law that began well before even the second edition of the Hollow Hope was published. For instance, in 1995, in United States v. Lopez, the court asserted new limits to Congress’s power under the Commerce Clause as a basis for striking down attempts to regulate the possession of guns in schools.Footnote 13 And, in 2000, in United States v. Morrison, the court extended this logic to invalidate aspects of the Violence against Women Act.Footnote 14 The court also began to develop new freestanding federalism doctrines in the form of an “anti-commandeering” principle, which the court held limited the capacity of Congress to regulate nuclear wasteFootnote 15 and to enlist local officials in the enforcement of federal gun regulations (in the form of the interim enforcement of background check requirements under the Brady Handgun Violence Prevention Act.Footnote 16

The US Supreme Court also began during this period to cast doubt on key aspects of its earlier equal protection jurisprudence. Most notably, it began to impose increasingly stringent limits on the scope for higher education institutions to adopt race-conscious admissions policies, first by requiring individualized consideration of race as a factor in admissionsFootnote 17 and then by limiting deference to higher educational institutions on the question of how far race-conscious policies were necessary to achieve the goal of educational diversity.Footnote 18 In addition, the court limited the scope for the Department of Justice to impose pre-clearance requirements on the drawing of electoral districts by states with a history of race-based discriminationFootnote 19 while, at the same time, declining to impose constitutional limits on partisan gerrymandering.Footnote 20

One of the key questions raised by Rosenberg in the Hollow Hope involved the conditions necessary for a dynamic court view to hold. But a related, and now seemingly equally pressing, question is about when and how courts will succeed in engaging in obstructionist and regressive forms of judicial review. Does the success of an obstructionist court, for example, depend on Rosenberg’s conditions for court dynamism? That is, does it depend on the barriers that courts erect being accompanied by positive incentives for compliance, and costs for non-compliance, on the part of non-court actors or court decisions acting as “leverage, or a shield, cover, or excuse, for persons crucial to implementation who are willing to act” (Rosenberg Reference Rosenberg2023, 41–43). One might expect that there is at least some degree of cross-over here. After all, as I foreshadow in the introduction, one person’s “progressive” vision could be another’s vision of decline or decay. And there are good reasons to think that blocking change requires political support, even if not the same degree as is required to implement widespread social change.

Does the success of a regressive court depend on similar factors? Perhaps, for instance, it is no coincidence that efforts to overrule the practical effects of Roe v. Wade in Texas have involved legislation that grants private actors the power and incentive to enforce limits on access to abortion.Footnote 21 Private actors may recover a minimum of ten thousand US dollars per performed abortion and are not required to demonstrate individual injury (Woolhandler Reference Woolhandler2023, 655). Another factor may be the degree to which a prior court order was in fact implemented, and, hence, there is the potential for burdens of inertia to affect a judicial attempt to reverse it (compare Dixon Reference Dixon2023).

And what is the significance in this context of social versus economic or political reliance on prior court decisions? For instance, in Planned Parenthood v. Casey, decided just over thirty years before Dobbs, the court famously suggested that reliance was a crucial factor in upholding the “central finding” in Roe and that the Constitution protects a woman’s right of access to abortion. The reliance in question was also a mix of social, economic, and political in nature. That is, the court held that Roe’s central holding should be upheld in part because “for two decades … people have organized intimate relationships and made choices that define their views of themselves and their places in society, in reliance on the availability of abortion in the event that contraception should fail.” In addition, the court noted that “[t]he ability of women to participate equally in the economic and social life of the Nation has been facilitated by their ability to control their reproductive lives.” But the same factors might also inform the degree of resistance to a regressive court ruling. Decisions on which people have come to rely, for example, may also be more likely to see a popular defense in the name of judicial attempts at repeal or regression: this is certainly one way of reading the widespread protests against Dobbs and attempt to override it both by state legislative change and state court rulings and state-based constitutional amendment (Landau and Dixon Reference Landau and Dixon2022; Murray and Shaw Reference Murray and Shaw2024).

Finally, are there differences in the willingness of certain political actors to push back against what they perceive to be obstructionist or regressive court rulings? Some scholars suggest that Democrats may be more reluctant than Republicans to engage in certain forms of “constitutional hardball” (Fishkin and Pozen Reference Fishkin and Pozen2018). This might also affect their willingness to pass legislation that attempts to evade or limit the effect of (what for progressives are clearly) obstructionist or regressive rulings when conservatives have often been quite willing to do the same for “dynamic” court rulings. Others suggest that it may be easier for courts to enliven intolerance than tolerance and, hence, achieve regressive as opposed to more dynamic, inclusive forms of change. However, the degree of this potential constitutional “asymmetry” remains an open question (Fishkin and Pozen Reference Fishkin and Pozen2018).

Conclusion

We may not live in a time where many Americans are inclined to ponder whether the US Supreme Court can still act as an agent of progressive social change. And for that reason, some readers may be inclined to think that the Hollow Hope is no longer addressed to the most central questions of our time. But there is still a question of whether the Supreme Court might be able to play other roles—both negative and positive—in the protection or erosion of constitutional democracy and the extent to which courts elsewhere can do the same. Focusing on the preconditions for successful judicial review is thus an enduring question that is of interest to constitutional lawyers and scholars worldwide. In that context, the Hollow Hope could be considered an invitation—for us to consider more carefully when and how it is that courts can maintain either a dynamic, obstructionist, or regressive role in social change, and what if anything that tells us about our hopes for constitutional judicial review more generally.

Judicial review is certainly no silver bullet against the dangers of democratic erosion or for delivering on the promise of social change. But nor is it likely as ineffective as skeptics suggest. Indeed, the best comparative evidence seems to be that courts are a source of “qualified hope” for those seeking to curb the excesses and failings of majoritarian politics. But it can cut two ways for democracy. In many countries today, we are arguably witnessing a new display of the power of courts to drive change but not in a direction that is welcomed. Given this, the key question for scholars in the next decade may no longer be whether courts have the power to drive change but, rather, when and how that power can be channeled toward democratic rather than anti-democratic or illiberal ends.

Footnotes

The author thanks Malcolm Langford and colleagues at University of New South Wales Sydney for helpful comments on prior drafts, and Niki Nojoumian and Hayden Clift for outstanding research assistance. Research support was provided by the Australian Research Council (no. FT210100667).

1 Dobbs v. Jackson Women’s Health Organization, 597 U.S. 215 (2022).

2 Roe v. Wade, 410 U.S. 113 (1973).

3 Brown v. Board of Education, 347 U.S. 483 (1954); Griswold v. Connecticut, 381 U.S. 479 (1965); Roe, 410 U.S.

4 Romer v. Evans, 517 U.S. 620 (1996).

5 Lawrence v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558 (2003).

6 Obergefell v. Hodges, 576 U.S. 644 (2015).

7 Planned Parenthood v. Casey, 505 U.S. 833 (1992).

8 People’s Union for CL v. Union of India, Case no. 196, 2001.

9 New York State Rifle Association v. Bruen, Case no. 20-843 (U.S. June 28, 2022).

10 Students for Fair Admissions v. President and Fellows of Harvard College, Case no. 20-1199 (U.S. June 24, 2023).

11 Bruen, Case no. 20-843.

12 Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms, Part 1 of the Constitution Act, 1982, being Schedule B to the Canada Act 1982 (UK), 1982, c. 11; Tremblay v. Daigle, [1989] 2 S.C.R. 530.

13 United States v. Lopez, 514 U.S. 549 (1995).

14 United States v. Morrison, 529 U.S. 598 (2000); Violence against Women Act, September 13, 1994, 108 Stat. 1796.

15 New York v. United States, 505 U.S. 144 (1992).

16 Printz v. United States, 521 U.S. 898 (1997); Brady Handgun Violence Prevention Act, November 30, 1993, 107 Stat. 1536.

17 Gratz v. Bollinger, 539 U.S. 244 (2003).

18 Fisher v. University of Texas, 579 U.S. 998 (2016).

19 Shelby County v. Holder, 570 U.S. 529 (2013).

20 Gill v. Whitford, 585 U.S. 6 (2018); Rucho v. Common Cause, 139 S. Ct. 2484 (2019).

21 Texas Heartbeat Act, March 11, 2021, S.B. 8, 87th Leg., R.S., ch. 1.

References

Berry, Christopher. 2007. “The Impact of School Finance Judgments on State Fiscal Policy.” In School Money Trials: The Legal Pursuit of Educational Adequacy, edited by Martin, R. West and Paul, E. Peterson, 213–42. Washington, DC: Brookings Institution Press.Google Scholar
Bugaric, Bojan. 2019. “Central Europe’s Descent into Autocracy: A Constitutional Analysis of Authoritarian Populism.” International Journal of Constitutional Law 17, no. 2: 597616. https://doi.org/10.1093/icon/moz032.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brazelton, Shenita. 2016. “A Hollow Hope? Social Change, the U.S. Supreme Court and Affirmative Action.” Journal of Race & Policy 12, no. 2: 8495.Google Scholar
Brierley, A. 2019. “PUCL v. Union of India: Political Mobilization and the Right to Food.” In Rosenberg, Krishnaswamy, and Bail 2019b, 212–40.Google Scholar
Brinks, Daniel M., and Gauri, Varun. 2014. “The Law’s Majestic Equality? The Distributive Impact of Judicializing Social and Economic Rights.” Perspectives on Politics 12, no. 2: 375–93. https://doi.org/10.1017/S1537592714000887.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bugaric, Bojan. 2019. “Could Populism Be Good for Constitutional Democracy?Annual Review of Law and Social Science 15, no. 1: 4158. https://doi.org/10.1146/annurev-lawsocsci-101518-042927.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chilton, Adam, and Versteeg, Mila. 2018. “Courts’ Limited Ability to Protect Constitutional Rights.” University of Chicago Law Review 85, no. 2: 293335.Google Scholar
Choudhry, Sujit. 2004. “The Lochner Era and Comparative Constitutionalism.” International Journal of Constitutional Law 2 no. 1: 155. https://doi.org/10.1093/icon/2.1.1.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Choudhry, Sujit. 2013. “The Commonwealth Constitutional Model or Models?International Journal of Constitutional Law 11, no. 4: 1094–99. https://doi.org/10.1093/icon/mot057.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dahl, Robert A. 1957. “The Concept of Power.” Behavioral Science 2, no. 3: 201–15. https://doi.org/10.1002/bs.3830020303.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Delgado, Richard. 1993. “Rodrigo’s Fourth Chronicle: Neutrality and Stasis in Antidiscrimination Law.” Stanford Law Review 45, no. 4: 1133–60.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Delgado, Richard. 2008. “A Comment in Rosenberg’s New Edition of the Hollow Hope.” North Western University Law Review 103: 147–52.Google Scholar
Dimock, Michael, and Wike, Richard. 2020. “America Is Exceptional in the Nature of Its Political Divide.” Pew Research Centre. Last modified November 2020. https://www.pewresearch.org/short-reads/2020/11/13/america-is-exceptional-in-the-nature-of-its-political-divide/.Google Scholar
Dixon, Rosalind. 2007. “Creating Dialogue about Socioeconomic Rights: Strong-Form versus Weak-Form Judicial Review Revisited.” International Journal of Constitutional Law 5, no. 3: 391418. https://doi.org/10.1093/icon/mom021.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dixon, Rosalind. 2023. Responsive Judicial Review: Democracy and Dysfunction in the Modern Age. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dixon, Rosalind, and Chowdhury, Rishad. 2019. “A Case for Qualified Hope? The Supreme Court of India and the Midday Meal Decision.” In Rosenberg, Krishnaswamy, and Bail 2019b, 243–68.Google Scholar
Dixon, Rosalind, and Landau, David. 2015. “Transnational Constitutionalism and a Limited Doctrine of Unconstitutional Constitutional Amendment.” International Journal of Constitutional Law 13, no. 3: 606–38. https://doi.org/10.1093/icon/mov039.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dixon, Rosalind, and Landau, David. 2021. Abusive Constitutional Borrowing: Legal Globalization and the Subversion of Liberal Democracy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dixon, Rosalind, and Posner, Eric. 2011. “The Limits of Constitutional Convergence.” Chicago Journal of International Law 11, no. 2: 399423.Google Scholar
Dugard, Jackie, and Langford, Malcolm. 2011. “Art or Science? Synthesising Lessons from Public Interest Litigation and the Dangers of Legal Determinism.” South African Journal on Human Rights 27, no. 1: 3964.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Edelman, Adam. 2023. “Carrying a Concealed Loaded Gun without a Permit May Soon Be Legal in Most States.” NBC News, January 14. https://www.nbcnews.com/politics/politics-news/permitless-concealed-carry-may-soon-legal-states-rcna64947.Google Scholar
Epp, Charles R. 2010. Making Rights Real: Activists, Bureaucrats, and the Creation of the Legalistic State. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Epstein, Lee, Knight, Jack, and Shvetsova, Olga. 2001. “The Role of Constitutional Courts in the Establishment and Maintenance of Democratic Systems of Government.” Law & Society Review 35, no. 1: 117–64. https://doi.org/10.2307/3185388.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feeley, Malcolm M. 1992. “Hollow Hopes, Flypaper, and Metaphors.” Law & Social Inquiry 17, no. 4: 745–60. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1747-4469.1992.tb00638.x.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fishkin, Joseph, and Pozen, David E.. 2018. “Asymmetrical Constitutional Hardball.” Columbia Law Review 118, no. 3: 915–82.Google Scholar
Girgis, Sherif. 2022. “Symposium on the Court’s Decision in Dobbs v Jackson Women’s Health Organization,” SCOTUS Blog, June 28. https://www.scotusblog.com/2022/06/dobbss-history-and-the-future-of-abortion-and-privacy-law/.Google Scholar
Graber, Mark. 2011. “Hollow Hopes and Exaggerated Fears: The Canon? Anticanon in Context.” Harvard Law Review Forum 125: 3339.Google Scholar
Guinier, Lani, and Torres, Gerald. 2014. “Changing the Wind: Notes toward a Demosprudence of Law and Social Movements.” Yale Law Journal 123: 27402804.Google Scholar
Hall, Matthew E. K. 2009. “The Hollow Hope: Can Courts Bring About Social Change? 2nd ed., by Gerald Rosenberg: Book Reviews.” Law & Society Review 43: 941–43. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1540-5893.2009.00393_1.x.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harris, Kamala. 2023. “Remarks on the Anniversary of the U.S. Supreme Court Decision in Dobbs v. Jackson Women’s Health Organization.” The White House, June 24. https://www.whitehouse.gov/briefing-room/speeches-remarks/2023/06/24/remarks-by-vice-president-harris-on-the-anniversary-of-the-u-s-supreme-court-decision-in-dobbs-v-jackson-womens-health-organization/.Google Scholar
Helfer, Laurence R., and Voeten, Erik. 2014. “International Courts as Agents of Legal Change: Evidence from LGBT Rights in Europe.” International Organization 68, no. 1: 77110. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0020818313000398.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hogg, Peter. 1990. “Interpreting the Charter of Rights: Generosity and JustificationOsgoode Hall Law Journal 28, no. 4: 817–38.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hollis-Brusky, Amanda. 2019. “Defending Faith: The Politics of the Christian Conservative Legal Movement by Daniel Bennett (Review).” Great Plains Research 29, no. 1: 4445. https://doi.org/10.1353/gpr.2019.0009.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Human Rights Institute. 2023. “Human Rights Crisis: Abortion in United States after Dobbs.” Last modified April 2023. https://www.hrw.org/sites/default/files/media_2023/04/Human%20Rights%20Crisis%20-%20Abortion%20in%20the%20United%20States%20After%20Dobbs.pdf.Google Scholar
Issacharoff, Samuel. 2011. “Constitutional Courts and Democratic Hedging.” Georgetown Law Journal 99, no. 4: 9611012.Google Scholar
Jacobsohn, Gary J. 2022. “Dynamic and Constrained: Using the Judiciary to Pursue Social Justice in India.” Law & Social Inquiry 47, no. 1: 375–80. https://doi.org/10.1017/lsi.2021.48.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kahn, Ronald. 1993. “The Supreme Court, Constitutional Theory, and Social Change.” Journal of Legal Education 43, no. 3: 454–67.Google Scholar
Klarman, Michael J. 1994. “How Brown Changed Race Relations: The Backlash Thesis.” Journal of American History 81, no. 1: 81118. https://doi.org/10.2307/2080994.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Krislov, Samuel. 1992. “Book Review: The Hollow Hope: Can Courts Bring About Social Change? Gerald N. Rosenberg.” Constitutional Commentary 9: 367–70.Google Scholar
Landau, David. 2013. “Abusive Constitutionalism. University of California Davis Law Review 47, no. 1: 189260.Google Scholar
Landau, David. 2014. “Aggressive Weak Form Remedies.” Constitutional Court Review 5, no. 1: 244–64.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Landau, David, and Dixon, Rosalind. 2019. “Constitutional Non-Transformation?: Socioeconomic Rights beyond the Poor.” In The Future of Economic and Social Rights, edited by Katharine, G. Young, 110–34. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. http://doi.org/10.1017/9781108284653.005.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Landau, David, and Dixon, Rosalind. 2022. “Dobbs, Democracy, and Dysfunction.” Wisconsin Law Review 2023, no. 5: 15691614. https://doi.org/10.59015/wlr/ifpl8019.Google Scholar
Langford, Malcolm 2014. “Housing Rights Litigation: Grootboom and Beyond.” In Socio-Economic Rights in South Africa: Symbols or Substance?, edited by Langford, Malcolm, Cousins, Ben, Dugard, Jackie , and Madlingozi, Tshepo, 187225. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Langford, Malcolm. 2019. “Judicial Politics and Social Rights.” In The Future of Economic and Social Rights, edited by Katharine, G. Young, 66109. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108284653.005.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Langford, Malcolm. 2021. “The Impact of Public Interest Litigation: The Case of Socio-Economic Rights.” Australian Journal of Human Rights 27, no. 3: 505–31. https://doi.org/10.1080/1323238X.2022.2030039.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lawrence, Susan E. 1992. “The Hollow Hope: Can Courts Bring About Social Change? By Gerald N. Rosenberg. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1991.” American Political Science Review 86, no. 3: 812–13. https://doi.org/10.2307/1964174.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCann, Michael W. 1992. “Reform Litigation on Trial.” Law & Social Inquiry 17, no. 4: 715–43. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1747-4469.1992.tb00637.x.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCloskey, Robert Green. 1960. The American Supreme Court. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Murray, Melissa, and Shaw, Katherine. 2024. “Dobbs and Democracy.” Harvard Law Review 137, no. 3: 728807.Google Scholar
Neumayer, Eric. 2005. “Do International Human Rights Treaties Improve Respect for Human Rights?Journal of Conflict Resolution 49, no. 6: 925–53.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Posner, Eric A., and Sunstein, Cass R.. 2006. “The Law of Other States.” Stanford Law Review 59: 131–80.Google Scholar
People for the American Way Foundation. 2002. “The Federalist Society: From Obscurity to Power.” https://www.pfaw.org/report/the-federalist-society-from-obscurity-to-power/.Google Scholar
Pew Research Centre. 2023. “Inflation, Health Costs, Partisan Cooperation Among the Nation’s Top Problems” https://www.pewresearch.org/politics/2023/06/21/inflation-health-costs-partisan-cooperation-among-the-nations-top-problems/.Google Scholar
Powe, L. A. 1992. “The Supreme Court, Social Change, and Legal Scholarship.” Stanford Law Review 44, no. 6: 1615–41. https://doi.org/10.2307/1229029.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Powe, L. A. 2009. The Supreme Court and the American Elite, 1789–2008. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rodríguez-Garavito, César. 2010. “Beyond the Courtroom: The Impact of Judicial Activism on Socioeconomic Rights in Latin America.” Texas Law Review 89: 1669–198.Google Scholar
Rosenberg, Gerald. 2023. The Hollow Hope. 3rd ed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosenberg, Gerald N., Krishnaswamy, Sudhir, and Bail, Shishir. 2019a. “A Qualified Hope.” In Rosenberg, Krishnaswamy, and Bail 2019b, i.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosenberg, Gerald N., Krishnaswamy, Sudhir, and Bail, Shishir. 2019b. A Qualified Hope: The Indian Supreme Court and Progressive Social Change. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Roux, Theunis. 2009. “Principle and Pragmatism on the Constitutional Court of South Africa.” International Journal of Constitutional Law 7, no. 1: 106–38.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Roznai, Yaniv. 2020. “Legislated Rights, Democratic Erosion, and the Rise of Executive Power: Comments on Legislated Rights—Securing Human Rights through Legislation.” Jerusalem Review of Legal Studies 21, no. 1: 129–44. https://doi.org/10.1093/jrls/jlaa001.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Samuel, Geoffry. 2009. “Interdisciplinarity and the Authority Paradigm: Should Law Be Taken Seriously by Scientists and Social Scientists?Journal of Law and Society 36, no. 4: 431–59.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scheppele, Kim Lane. 1992. “Gerald N. Rosenberg ‘The Hollow Hope: Can Courts Bring About Social Change?’ (Book Review).” Contemporary Sociology 21, no. 4: 465–66.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schuck, Peter H. 1993. “ The Hollow Hope: Can Courts Bring About Social Change?Yale Law Journal 102, no. 7: 1763–86.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schultz, David, and Gottlieb, Stephen E.. 1996. “Legal Functionalism and Social Change: A Reassessment of Rosenberg’s The Hollow Hope: Can Courts Bring About Social Change.” Journal of Law and Politics 12, no. 1: 6392.Google Scholar
Simmons, Beth A. 2009. Mobilizing for Human Rights: International Law in Domestic Politics (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2009).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Southworth, Ann. 2008. Lawyers of the Right: Professionalizing the Conservative Coalition. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Strauss, David A. 2009. “The Modernizing Mission of Judicial Review.” University of Chicago Law Review 76, no. 2: 859908.Google Scholar
Stumpf, Harry P. 1993. “ The Hollow Hope: Can Courts Bring About Social Change? Gerald N. Rosenberg.” Journal of Politics 55, no. 1: 256–58. https://doi.org/10.2307/2132247.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sunstein, Cass R. 2023. “Welfare Now.” Duke Law Journal 72, no. 8: 1643–72.Google Scholar
Tushnet, Mark. 2010. “How Courts Implement Social Policy.” Tulsa Law Review 45, no. 4: 855–62.Google Scholar
Woolhandler, Ann. 2023. “State Separation of Powers and the Federal Courts.” William & Mary Bill of Rights Journal 31, no. 3: 633–65.Google Scholar