Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-2plfb Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-30T20:43:04.715Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Moving Beyond the Canon of Traditional Constitutional History: Anti-Federalists, the Bill of Rights, and the Promise of Post-Modern Historiography

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 October 2011

Extract

Few aspects of post-structuralist literary criticism have garnered as much attention and provoked as much controversy as the move to challenge the idea of a fixed literary canon of great texts. The implications of deconstructing the canon extend well beyond the study of fiction. All fields of scholarship have a canon of established texts, methodologies, and questions. Critiques of the literary canon resemble the challenge to conventional history posed by the new social history and its efforts to write a history from the bottom up that would supplant traditional historical scholarship. A similar revisionist effort is now only just beginning to emerge in constitutional historiography. Proponents of “a new constitutional history” are seeking to challenge the canon of traditional constitutional history. While this revisionist project has not been cast in post-structuralist terms, the perspective provided by recent critical theory can refine the practice of the new constitutional history.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © the American Society for Legal History, Inc. 1994

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1. Guillory, John, “Canon” in Critical Terms for Literary Study, ed. Lentricchia, Frank and McLaughlin, Thomas (Chicago: University of Chicago, 1990), 1233–49Google Scholar; for other studies of canonization, see Baym, Nina, “Melodramas of Beset Manhood: How Theories of American Fiction Exclude Women Authors,” American Quarterly 33 (1981): 1233–49CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Kuklick, Bruce, “Seven Thinkers and How They Grew: Descartes, Spinoza, Leibniz; Locke, Berkeley, Hume; Kant,” in Philosophy in History: Essays in the Historiography of Philosophy, ed. Rorty, Richard, Schneewind, Jerome, and Skinner, Quentin (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1984), 125–39.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

2. Harris, Alice Kessler, “Social History,” in The New American History, ed. Foner, Eric (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1990), 179.Google Scholar

3. Hall, Kermit, “American Legal History as Science and Applied Politics,” Benchmark 4 (1990): 236.Google Scholar

4. On post-structuralism in general and deconstruction in particular, see Rosenau, Pauline Marie, Post-Modernism and the Social Sciences: Insights, Inroads, and Intrusions (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1992)Google Scholar; Dews, Peter, Logics of Disintegration: Post-Structuralist Thought and the Claims of Critical Theory (London: Verso, 1987)Google Scholar; Culler, Jonathan D., On Deconstruction: Theory and Criticism After Structuralism (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1982)Google Scholar; Norris, Christopher, Deconstruction, Theory and Practice (London: Methuen, 1982)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; idem, The Contest of Faculties: Philosophy and Theory after Deconstruction (London, 1985); Eagleton, Terry, Literary Theory: An Introduction (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1983)Google Scholar; Skinner, Quentin, The Return of Grand Theory in the Human Sciences (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985)Google Scholar; Balkin, J. M., “Deconstructive Practice and Legal Theory,” Yale Law Journal 96 (1987): 743–86.CrossRefGoogle Scholar On the new historicism within literary study and its debt to deconstruction, see Aram Veeser, H., ed., The New Historicism (New York: Routledge, 1989).Google Scholar

5. Stone, Lawrence, “History and Post-Modernism,” Past and Present 131 (1991): 217–18Google Scholar; idem, “History and Post-Modernism,” Past and Present 135 (1992): 189–208; Watts, Steven, “The Idiocy of American Studies: Poststructuralism, Language, and Politics in the Age of Self-Fulfillment,” American Quarterly 43 (1991): 625–60CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Palmer, Bryan D., Descent into Discourse: The Reification of Language and the Writing of Social History (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1990)Google Scholar; Himmelfarb, Gertrude, “Telling it as You Like it: Post-Modernist History and the Flight From Fact,” Times Literary Supplement, Oct. 16, 1992.Google Scholar

6. On contextualism see Collingwood, R. H., The Idea of History (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1946)Google Scholar; Skinner, Quentin, “Meaning and Understanding in the History of Ideas,” History and Theory 8 (1969): 353.CrossRefGoogle Scholar For another discussion of this theory, see Murphy, Murray G., Our Knowledge of the Historical Past (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1973).Google Scholar For a critique of contextualism from the perspective of post-structuralism, see LaCapra, Dominick, History and Criticism (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1985)Google Scholar and idem, Rethinking Intellectual History: Texts, Contexts, and Language (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1983).

7. Cornell, Saul, “Early American History in a Post-Modern Age,” William and Mary Quarterly 50, no. 2 (April 1993): 329–41.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

8. Kurland, Philip B. and Lerner, Ralph, eds., The Founders' Constitution 5 vols. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1987).Google Scholar

9. A good case in point is Herbert Storing's edited collection of Anti-Federalist writings, The Complete Anti-Federalist 6 vols. (Chicago, 1981). Historians have generally been critical of the criteria Storing used to assemble his collection of documents, on this point see Cornell, Saul A., “The Changing Historical Fortunes of the Anti-Federalists,” Northwestern University Law Review 84 (1989): 56.Google Scholar

10. See, for instance, Farber, Daniel A. and Sherry, Suzanna, A History of the American Constitution (Saint Paul: West Publishing, 1990).Google Scholar

11. Kenyon, Cecelia M., “Men of Little Faith: The Anti-Federalists on the Nature of Representative Government,” William and Mary Quarterly, 3d ser., 12 (1955): 343.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

12. Leonard Levy's views on the origins of the Bill of Rights are developed in Legacy of Suppression: Freedom of Speech and Press in Early America (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1960); Emergence of a Free Press (New York: Oxford University Press, 1985); Essays on the Making of the Constitution, 2d ed. (New York: Oxford University Press, 1987); and Original Intent and the Framers' Constitution (New York: Macmillan, 1988). For another view of the Anti-Federalists, stressing their commitment to states' rights, see Mason, Alpheus Thomas, The States Rights Debate: Antifederalism and the Constitution (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice Hall, 1964).Google Scholar

13. Of course, commentators on the Federalist have also exaggerated the coherence of Publius. For a discussion of this problem, see Mason, Alpheus T., “The Federalist—A Split Personality,” American Historical Review 57 (1952): 625–43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

14. Rutland, Robert, The Birth of the Bill of Rights, 1776–1791 (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1955), 232.Google Scholar

15. Schwartz, Bemard, The Great Rights of Mankind: A History of the American Bill of Rights (New York: Oxford University Press, 1977), 230.Google Scholar

16. On the tropes of historical writing and the notion of meta-narrative, see White, Hayden, Metahistory: The Historical Imagination in Nineteenth-Century Europe (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1973).Google Scholar

17. Butterfield, Herbert, The Whig Interpretation of History (New York: Norton, 1965)Google Scholar; and Fischer, David Hackett, Historians' Fallacies: Toward a Logic of Historical Thought (New York: Harper and Row, 1970), 139.Google Scholar

18. Urofsky, Melvin I., A March of Liberty: A Constitutional History of the United States (New York: Knopf, 1988).Google Scholar

19. On the relevance of the notion of “essentially contested concepts,” see Ball, Terrence and Pocock, J. G. A., eds., Conceptual Change and the Constitution (Lawrence: University Press of Kansas, 1988).Google Scholar For one effort to distinguish between diverse libertarian traditions in America, see Fischer, David Hackett, Albion's Seed: Four British Folkways in America (New York: Oxford University Press, 1989).Google Scholar

20. For useful narrative accounts of this period see Morris, Richard B., The Forging of the Union, 1781–1789 (New York: Harper and Row, 1987)Google Scholar; and Countryman, Edward, The American Revolution (New York: Hill and Wang, 1985).Google Scholar

21. Kramnick, Isaac, “‘The Great National Discussion’: The Discourse of Politics in 1787,” William and Mary Quarterly, 3d ser., 45 (1988): 332CrossRefGoogle Scholar; McDonald, Forrest, Novus Ordo Seclorum: The Intellectual Origins of the Constitution (Lawrence: University Press of Kansas, 1985).Google Scholar

22. Bailyn, Bernard, The Ideological Origins of the American Revolution (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1967)Google Scholar; Pocock, J. G. A., The Machiavellian Moment: Florentine Political Thought and the Atlantic Republican Tradition (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1975)Google Scholar; Wood, Gordon, The Creation of the American Republic, 1776–1787 (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1969).Google Scholar On liberalism, see Appleby, Joyce, Capitalism and the New Social Order: The Republican Vision of the 1790s (New York: New York University Press, 1984)Google Scholar; and Diggins, John, The Lost Soul of American Politics: Virtue, Self-interest, and the Foundations of Liberalism (New York: Basic Books, 1984).Google Scholar

23. On the notion of a republican synthesis, see Shalhope, Robert, “Toward a Republican Synthesis: The Emergence of an Understanding of Republicanism in American Historiography,” William and Mary Quarterly, 3d ser., 29 (1972): 4980CrossRefGoogle Scholar; idem, “Republicanism and Early American Historiography,” William and Mary Quarterly, 3d ser., 39 (1982): 334–56.

24. Kelly, Alfred H., Harbison, Winfred A., and Belz, Herman, The American Constitution: Its Origins and Development, 6th ed. (New York: Norton, 1983), chap. 5.Google Scholar

25. For an overview of this literature see Hutson, James, “The Birth of the Bill of Rights: The State of Current Scholarship,” Prologue 20 (Fall 1988): 150.Google Scholar Levy's interpretation has been subjected to a number of withering attacks: Fischer, Historians' Fallacies, 132–33; Rabban, David M., “The Ahistorical Historian: Leonard Levy on Freedom of Expression in Early American History,” Stanford Law Review 37 (1985): 795856.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

26. Levy, Emergence of a Free Press, 221.

27. Levy, Original Intent, 169.

28. Ibid., 170.

29. On the inadequacy of the notion of party during this period, see Formisano, Ronald P., “Deferential-Participant Politics: The Early Republic's Political Culture, 1789–1840,” American Political Science Review 68 (1974): 473–87.Google ScholarMain, Jackson Turner, The Antifederalists: Critics of the Constitution, 1781–1788 (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1961)Google Scholar provides ample evidence of the divisions within the ranks of the Anti-Federalists on a variety of issues.

30. Levy, Original Intent, 148.

31. Here the work of legal scholar Reid, John Philip is crucial, especially his Constitutional History of the American Revolution: The Authority of Rights (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1986)Google Scholar and idem, The Concept of Liberty in the Age of the American Revolution (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1988).

32. For a discussion of Levy that shows how his analysis has failed to respond to the challenge posed by Wood's Creation of the American Republic, see Rabban, “The Ahistorical Historian.”

33. Hall, Kermit L. and Ely, James W. Jr, “The South and the American Constitution,” in An Uncertain Tradition: Constitutionalism and the History of the South, ed. Hall, and Ely, (Athens: University of Georgia Press, 1989), 316.Google Scholar

34. Rutland's Birth of the Bill of Rights cites evidence of popular belief but does not explore the distinctive popular vision of these Anti-Federalists.

35. Levy, The Emergence of a Free Press, 266.

36. On this point, see Cornell, Saul, “Aristocracy Assailed: The Ideology of Back-country Anti-Federalism,” Journal of American History 76 (1990): 1148–72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

37. On the idea of political fictions, see Morgan, Edmund S., Inventing the People: The Rise of Popular Sovereignty in England and America (New York: Norton, 1988), 209–39.Google Scholar On the importance of democratic theory to original-intent jurisprudence, see Farber, Daniel, “The Originalism Debate: A Guide for the Perplexed,” Ohio State Law Journal 49 (19881989): 10851106.Google Scholar For additional discussion of original-intent jurisprudence, see the essays in Rakove, Jack, ed., Interpreting the Constitution (Boston: Northeastern University Press, 1990).Google Scholar The theories of Ely, John Hart, Democracy and Distrust: A Theory of Judicial Review (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1980)Google Scholar; Bork, Robert, The Tempting of America: The Political Seduction of the Law (New York: Free Press, 1990)Google Scholar; Ackerman, Bruce A., We the People: Foundations (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1991)Google Scholar all depend on variants of democratic theory to support their models of constitutional interpretation.

38. Caplan, Russell L., “The History and Meaning of the Ninth Amendment,” in The Rights Retained by the People: The History and Meaning of the Ninth Amendment, ed. Barnett, Randy E. (Fairfax: George Mason University Press, 1989), 281.Google Scholar Caplan's work was cited by Robert Bork during his confirmation hearings when he was questioned about the meaning of the Ninth Amendment. On this point, see Mersky, Roy M. and Myron Jacobstein, J., ed., The Supreme Court of the United States: Hearings and Reports on the Successful and Unsuccessful Nominations of Supreme Court Justices by the Senate Judiciary Committee, 1916–1987, vol. 14 (Buffalo: William S. Hein, 1990), 428, 999.Google Scholar

39. For a discussion of this transformation, see Cornell, Saul A., “The Changing Historical Fortunes of the Anti-Federalists,” Northwestern University Law Review 84 (1989): 3973.Google Scholar For two recent examples of the Anti-Federalist intent of the Ninth Amendment, see Massey, Calvin R., “The Anti-Federalist Ninth Amendment and Its Implications for State Constitutional Law,” Wisconsin Law Review (1990): 1229–66Google Scholar; and McAfee, Thomas, “The Original Meaning of the Ninth Amendment,” Columbia Law Review 90 (1990): 12151320.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

40. On this dimension of the state bills of rights, see Hutson, James H., “The Bill of Rights and the American Revolutionary Experience,” in A Culture of Rights: The Bill of Rights in Philosophy, Politics, and Law — 1791 and 1991, ed. Lacey, Michael J. and Haakonssen, Knud (Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press, 1991), 94.Google Scholar

41. “Sydney,” [Abraham Yates?] ed., The Complete Anti-Federalist, ed. Storing, Herbert J., 7 vols. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press), 6:109–10.Google Scholar On New York politics in this period, see Countryman, Edward, A People in Revolution: The American Revolution and Political Society in New York, 1760–1790 (Baltimore, 1981).Google Scholar For a discussion of the character of New York Anti-Federalism, see Cornell, Saul, “Politics of the Middling Sort: The Bourgeois Radicalism of Abraham Yates, Melancton Smith, and the New York Anti-Federalists,” in New York in the Age of the Constitution, 1775–1800, ed. Pencak, William and Gilje, Paul (Rutherford, N.J.: Associated University Presses, 1992), 151–75.Google Scholar

42. Melancton Smith, “Amendments Proposed to the New Constitution of Government,” draft manuscript, Melancton Smith Papers, New York State Library, Albany, New York. For a general discussion of natural rights theory during this period, see Knud Haakonssen, “From Natural Law to the Rights of Man: A European Perspective on American Debates,” in A Culture of Rights, 19–61 and Sherry, Suzanna, “The Founders' Unwritten ConstitutionUniversity of Chicago Law Review 54 (1987): 1127–77.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

43. “Brutus,” in Storing, Complete Anti-Federalist 2:396.

44. “Brutus,” ibid. 2:315–16. On Brutus, see Jeffrey, William Jr, “The Letters of ‘Brutus’ — A Neglected Element in the Ratification Campaign,” University of Cincinnati Law Review 40 (1971): 643–63Google Scholar; and Diamond, Anne Stuart, “The Anti-Federalist ‘Brutus,’The Political Science Reviewer 6 (1976): 249–81.Google Scholar

45. “Brutus,” in Storing, Complete Anti-Federalist 2:315–16.

46. For a study that uses Brutus in this fashion, see McDowell, Gary, “Were the Anti-Federalists Right: Judicial Activism and the Problem of Consolidated Government,” Publius 12 (1982): 99108.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

47. On Storing's place in recent scholarship on Anti-Federalism, see Cornell, “The Changing Historical Fortunes of the Anti-Federalists,” 56.

48. Storing, Complete Anti-Federalist 1:72.

49. Ibid. 1:65

50. An excellent introduction to Straussian scholarship is Strauss, Leo and Cropsey, Joseph, eds., History of Political Philosophy, 3d ed. (Chicago, 1987).CrossRefGoogle Scholar A critical assessment of the Straussian paradigm can be found in Wood, Gordon S., “The Fundamentalists and the Constitution,” New York Review of Books 35 (1988).Google Scholar

51. Storing, Complete Anti-Federalist 1:83.

52. Lutz, Donald S., “The Relative Influence of European Writers on Late Eighteenth-Century American Political Thought,” American Political Science Review 78 (1984): 189–97.CrossRefGoogle Scholar In many cases Anti-Federalist ideas about Locke or Brutus were obtained from the popular press and did not necessarily reflect a direct knowledge of classical texts either in the original or in translation.

53. For discussions about the difference between modern and ancient approaches to the meaning of virtue, see Lance Banning, “Second Thoughts on Virtue and Revolutionary Thinking,” in Conceptual Change and the Constitution, 194–212, and Yarbrough, Jean, “Republicanism Reconsidered: Some Thoughts on the Foundation and Preservation of the American Republic,” Review of Politics 41 (1979): 6195.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

54. Storing, Complete Anti-Federalist 1:83. Forrest McDonald is one of the few critics to note this contradiction in Storing's work: Novus Ordo Seclorum, 285. For another effort to view the Anti-Federalists as liberals, see Sinopoli, Richard C., The Foundations of American Citizenship: Liberalism, the Constitution and Civic Virtue (New York, Oxford, 1992).Google Scholar

55. After acknowledging the heterogeneity of the Anti-Federalists, Storing proceeds with the task of seeking their underlying unity. Complete Anti-Federalist 1:6.

56. Hutson, “The Birth of the Bill of Rights,” 150. On the debate over the test acts in Pennsylvania, see Arnold, Douglas M., A Republican Revolution: Ideology and Politics in Pennsylvania, 1776–1790 (New York: Garland, 1989), 103–19.Google Scholar

57. Ermarth, Michael, “Mindful Matters: The Empire's New Codes and the Plight of Modern European Intellectual History,” Journal of Modern History 57 (1985): 506–27CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Toews, John E., “Intellectual History After the Linguistic Turn: The Autonomy of Meaning and the Irreducibility of Experience,” American Historical Review 92 (1987): 879907CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Hollinger, David, In the American Province: Studies in the History and Historiography of Ideas (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1985).Google Scholar Artisan republicanism is treated by Wilentz, Sean in Chants Democratic: New York City and the Rise of the American Working Class, 1788–1850 (New York: Oxford University Press, 1984).Google Scholar Gendered meanings of republicanism are treated in Kerber, Linda, Women of the Republic: Intellect and Ideology in Revolutionary America (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1980).Google Scholar

58. Hall, Kermit, “American Legal History as Science and Applied Politics,” Benchmark 4 (1990): 236.Google Scholar

59. Forbath, William E., Hartog, Hendrik, and Minow, Martha, “Legal Histories from Below,” Wisconsin Law Review (1985): 764.Google Scholar

60. For an excellent discussion of materialist approaches to ideology, see Eagleton, Terry, Ideology: An Introduction (London: Verso, 1991).Google Scholar The classic Progressive interpretation of the Constitutional struggle is Beard, Charles, An Economic Interpretation of the Constitution (New York: Macmillan, 1913)Google Scholar; the most influential neo-progressive account is Jackson Turner Main, The Anti-Federalists. For a neo-Marxist account, see Nash, Gary B., “Also There at the Creation: Going beyond Gordon S. Wood,” William and Mary Quarterly, 3d ser., 44 (1987): 602–11.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

61. Geertz, Clifford, The Interpretation of Cultures (New York: Basic, 1973).Google Scholar The ideological school's debt to Geertz was more readily apparent in the methodological statements that followed their earlier monographic historical contributions. See, in particular, Bailyn, Bernard, “The Central Themes of the Revolution,” in Essays on the American Revolution, ed. Kurtz, Stephen G. and Hutson, James (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1973), 1012, 23Google Scholar; Wood, Gordon S., “Intellectual History and the Social Sciences,” in New Directions in American Intellectual History, ed. Higham, John and Conkin, Paul K. (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1979), 2741Google Scholar; and idem, “Ideology and Origins of Liberal America,” William and Mary Quarterly, 3d ser., 44 (1987): 628–40. Geertz's framework was developed in the context of detailed ethnographic field work that helped him establish the boundary of the ideological community he analyzed. Historical scholarship invoking Geertz has assumed that America was a single ideological community. This has introduced a strong homogenizing tendency in works inspired by Geertz. For a critique of Geertz, see Walters, Ronald G., “Signs of the Times: Clifford Geertz and the Historians,” Social Research 47 (1980): 537–56.Google Scholar

62. For a more detailed discussion of the variety of discursive communities within the ranks of the Anti-Federalists, see Cornell, Saul A., “The Political Thought and Culture of the Anti-Federalists,” (Ph.D. diss., University of Pennsylvania, 1989).Google Scholar

63. “Cincinnatus,” [Arthur Lee?], in Storing, The Complete Anti-Federalist 6:14.

64. Cornell, “Aristocracy Assailed.”

65. Kenyon, Cecelia, The Anti-Federalists (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1966), lxviii.Google Scholar See also Hofstadter, Richard, Anti-Intellectualism in American Life (New York: Knopf, 1962), 151.Google Scholar

66. “A Watchman,” in Storing, The Complete Anti-Federalist 4:232.

67. Cornell, “Aristocracy Assailed.” For a similar effort to recover popular legal thought, see Hartog, Hendrik, “Pigs and Positivism,” Wisconsin Law Review (1985): 899935.Google Scholar

68. Jensen, Merrill et al., eds., The Documentary History of the Ratification of the Constitution (Madison, Wis.: State Historical Society, 1976–), 2:675.Google Scholar

69. Ibid. 2:685.

70. Koch, Adrienne, ed., Notes of Debates in the Federal Convention of 1787 Reported by James Madison (Athens, Ohio: Ohio University Press, 1966), 488.Google Scholar

71. On the culture of constitutionalism, see Hartog, , “The Constitution of Aspiration and ‘The Rights that Belong to Us All,’Journal of American History 74 (1987): 1013–34.CrossRefGoogle Scholar