Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-8ctnn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-23T17:26:40.922Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Two Charges of Intellectualism against Kant

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  04 June 2013

Arthur Melnick*
Affiliation:
University of Illinois Email: [email protected]

Abstract

The contemporary discussion of non-conceptual content inaugurated by Gareth Evans and John McDowell has generated a range of differing views as to Kant's position on the issues raised. I argue that for Kant perception is prior to thought and that it is as being prior that perception connects us to reality in outer intuition. I then argue that for Kant thought relates to perception by being the rule for perceptual procedures. This accounts for thought's extending in scope beyond what we actually perceive to all that is manifest in space and time. As against Merleau-Ponty this Kantian understanding of thought beyond perception does not distort the nature of reality which remains essentially that which can be engaged.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Kantian Review 2013 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Allais, Lucy (2009) ‘Kant, Non-conceptual Content and the Representation of Space’. Journal of the History of Philosophy, 47(3), 383413.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carnap, Rudolf (1964) Logical Syntax of Language, trans. Amethe Smeaton. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Eilan, Naomi (1995) ‘Consciousness and the Self’. In José Luis Bermúdez, Naomi Eilan, and Anthony Marcel (eds), The Body and the Self (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press), pp. 337358.Google Scholar
Frankfurt, H (1970) Demons, Dreamers, and Madmen: The Defense of Reason in Descartes’ Meditations. Indianapolis, IN: Bobbs-Merrill.Google Scholar
Ginsborg, Hannah (2008) ‘Was Kant a Nonconceptualist?’ Philosophical Studies, 137(1), 6577.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goodman, Nelson (1977) The Structure of Appearance. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hanna, Robert (2005) ‘Kant and Non-conceptual Content’. European Journal of Philosophy, 13(2), 247290.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heidegger, Martin (1962) Being and Time, trans. John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson. New York: Harper & Row.Google Scholar
Heidegger, Martin (1990) Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics, trans. Richard Taft. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
Husserl, Edmund (1977) Cartesian Meditations, trans. Dorion Cairns. The Hague: Nijhoff.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kant, Immanuel (2003) Critique of Pure Reason, trans. Norman Kemp Smith. Boston and Bedford: St Martin's.Google Scholar
Kripke, Saul (1980) Naming and Necessity. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
McDowell, John (1994) Mind and World. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Melnick, Arthur (2004) Themes in Kant's Metaphysics and Ethics. Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press.Google Scholar
Merleau-Ponty, Maurice (1958) Phenomenology of Perception, trans. Colin Smith London and New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Putnam, Hilary (1981) Reason Truth and History. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quine, W. V. O. (1969) Word and Object. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Scheler, Max (1961) Man's Place in Nature, trans. Hans Meyerhoff. Boston: Beacon Press.Google Scholar
Smith, A. D. (2003) The Problem of Perception. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Westphal, Kenneth (1997) ‘Affinity, Idealism, and Naturalism: The Stability of Cinnabar and the Possibility of Appearance’. Kant-Studien, 88(2), 139189.CrossRefGoogle Scholar