Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-8ctnn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-23T23:21:14.406Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Kant on Radical Evil and the Origin of Moral Responsibility

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  04 February 2013

Irene McMullin*
Affiliation:
University of Arkansas

Abstract

The notion of radical evil plays a more important role in Kant's moral theory than is typically recognized. In Religion Within the Limits of Mere Reason, radical evil is both an innate propensity and a morally imputable act – a paradoxical status that has prompted commentators to reject it as inconsistent with the rest of Kant's moral theory. In contrast, I argue that the notion of radical evil accounts for the beginning of moral responsibility in Kant's theory, since the act of attributing radical evil to one's freedom is an inauguration into the autonomous stance.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Kantian Review 2013

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Allison, H. (1990) Kant's Theory of Freedom. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Allison, H. (1996) Idealism and Freedom. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Allison, H. (2001) ‘Ethics, Evil, and Anthropology in Kant: Remarks on Allen Wood's Kant's Ethical Thought. Ethics, 111, 594613.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bernstein, R. A. (2002) Radical Evil: A Philosophical Interrogation. Malden, MA: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Cherkasova, E. (2005) ‘On the Boundary of Intelligibility: Kant's Conception of Radical Evil and the Limits of Ethical Discourse’. Review of Metaphysics, 58, 571584.Google Scholar
Fichte, J. G. (2000) Foundations of Natural Right. Ed. F. Neuhouser, trans. M. Baur. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Frierson, P. (2010) ‘Kantian Moral Pessimism’. In S. Anderson-Gold and P. Muchnik (eds), Kant's Anatomy of Evil (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), pp. 3356.Google Scholar
Guevara, D. (2000) Kant's Theory of Moral Motivation. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.Google Scholar
Hare, J. (1996) The Moral Gap. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Herman, B. (1998) ‘Training to Autonomy: Kant and the Question of Moral Education’. In A. O. Rorty (ed.), Philosophers on Education (New York: Routledge), pp. 255272.Google Scholar
Kant, I. (1996) ‘Religion Within the Boundaries of Mere Reason’. In A. W. Wood (ed.), Religion and Rational Theology (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), pp. 41215, Abbreviated R.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kant, I. (1997a) Critique of Practical Reason. Ed. and trans. Mary Gregor. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Abbreviated CPR.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kant, I. (1997b) Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals. Ed. and trans. Mary Gregor. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Abbreviated G.Google Scholar
Kant, I. (2006) ‘Conjectural Beginning of Human History’. In P. Kleingeld (ed.) and D. L. Colclasure (trans.), Toward Perpetual Peace and Other Writings on Politics, Peace, and History (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press), pp. 2436.Google Scholar
Korsgaard, C. (1996a) Creating the Kingdom of Ends. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Korsgaard, C. (1996b) The Sources of Normativity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Korsgaard, C. (1998) ‘Motivation, Metaphysics, and the Value of the Self: A Reply to Ginsborg, Guyer, and Schneewind’. Ethics, 109, 4966.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Michalson, G. E. Jr. (1990) Fallen Freedom. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morgan, S. (2005) ‘The Missing Formal Proof of Humanity's Radical Evil in Kant's “Religion” ’. Philosophical Review, 114, 63114.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moyar, D. (2003) ‘David Sussman, the Idea of Humanity: Anthropology and Anthroponomy in Kant's Ethics’. Ethics, 114, 196199.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Neiman, S. (2002) Evil in Modern Thought. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
O'Connor, D. (1985) ‘Good and Evil Disposition’. Kant-Studien, 76, 288302.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quinn, P. L. (1990) ‘Does Anxiety Explain Original Sin?’ Noûs, 24 (APA Central Division Meeting), 227244.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reath, A. (1989) ‘Kant's Theory of Moral Sensibility: Respect for the Moral Law and the Influence of Inclination’. Kant-Studien, 80, 284302.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Regan, D. H. (2002) ‘The Value of Rational Nature’. Ethics, 112, 267291.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ricoeur, P. (2007) The Conflict of Interpretations: Essays in Hermeneutics. Ed. Don Ihde. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.Google Scholar
Sullivan, R. J. (1995) ‘The Influence of Kant's Anthropology on his Moral Theory’. Review of Metaphysics, 49, 7794.Google Scholar
Sussman, D. (2001) The Idea of Humanity: Anthropology and Anthroponomy in Kant's Ethics. New York: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sussman, D. (2003) ‘The Authority of Humanity’. Ethics, 113, 350366.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sussman, D. (2005) ‘Perversity of the Heart’. Philosophical Review, 114, 153177.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tengelyi, L. (2004) The Wild Region in Life History. Trans. G. Kállay and L. Tengelyi. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wood, A. (1999) Kant's Ethical Thought. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Yovel, Y. (1998) ‘Kant's Practical Reason as Will: Interest, Recognition, Judgment and Choice’. Review of Metaphysics, 52, 267294.Google Scholar