Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-vdxz6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-27T21:54:49.612Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Kant and Crusius on Belief and Practical Justification

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 February 2019

Gabriele Gava*
Affiliation:
Goethe University Frankfurt

Abstract

Kant’s account of practical justification for belief has attracted much attention in the literature, especially in recent years. In this context, scholars have generally emphasized the originality of Kant’s thought about belief (Glaube), and Kant indeed offers a definition of belief that is very different from views that were prevalent in eighteenth-century Germany. In this article, however, I argue that it is very likely that Christian August Crusius exerted influence on Kant’s definition of belief and his account of practical justification. In turn, acknowledging this influence has relevant consequences for how we understand the phenomenology of Kantian belief.

Type
Articles
Copyright
© Kantian Review 2019 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Alexander, W. (1996) ‘Pluraque credimus, paucissima scimus: Zur Diskussion über philosophische und hermeneutische Wahrscheinlichkeit in der ersten Hälfte des 18. Jahrhunderts’. Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie, 78, 130165.Google Scholar
Borghero, C. (1983) La certezza e la storia: Cartesianesimo, pirronismo e conoscenza storica. Milan: F. Angeli.Google Scholar
Chignell, A. (2007a) ‘Kant’s Concepts of Justification’. Noûs, 41, 3363.Google Scholar
Chignell, A. (2007b) ‘Belief in Kant’. Philosophical Review, 116, 323360.Google Scholar
Crusius, C. A. (1744) Anweisung vernünftig zu leben. Leipzig.Google Scholar
Crusius, C. A. (1747) Weg zur Gewissheit und Zuverlässigkeit der menschlichen Erkentniss. Leipzig.Google Scholar
Crusius, C. A. (1753) Entwurf der nothwendigen Vernunft-Wahrheiten, 2nd edn. Leipzig.Google Scholar
Danneberg, L. (1994) ‘Probabilitas hermeneutica. Zu einem Aspekt der Interpretations-Methodologie in der ersten Hälfte des 18. Jahrhunderts’. Aufklärung, 8, 2748.Google Scholar
Daston, L. (1988) Classical Probability in the Enlightenment. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Dyck, C. (2018) ‘G. F. Meier and Kant on the Belief in the Immortality of the Soul’. In C. Dyck and F. Wunderlich (eds), Kant and his German Contemporaries (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 7693.Google Scholar
Fonnesu, L. (2011) ‘Kant on Moral Certainty’. In L. Cataldi Madonna and P. Rumore (eds), Kant und die Aufklärung (Hildesheim: Olms), 183204.Google Scholar
Fonnesu, L. (2015) ‘Kant on Private Faith and Public Knowledge’. Rivista di Filosofia, 106, 361390.Google Scholar
Gava, G. (2016) ‘The Fallibilism of Kant’s Architectonic’. In G. Gava and R. Stern (eds), Pragmatism, Kant and Transcendental Philosophy (London: Routledge), 4666.Google Scholar
Gava, G. (forthcoming) ‘Sind die regulativen Ideen ein doktrinaler Glaube? Über die Rechtfertigung des regulativen Gebrauchs der Ideen im Anhang zur transzendentalen Dialektik’. In V. L. Waibel und M. Ruffing (eds), Akten des 12. internationalen Kant-Kongresses (Berlin: De Gruyter).Google Scholar
Gava, G. and Willaschek, M. (forthcoming) ‘The Transcendental Doctrine of Method of the Critique of Pure Reason ’. In S. Baiasu and M. Timmons (eds), The Kantian Mind (London: Routledge).Google Scholar
Gelfert, A. (2010) ‘Kant and the Enlightenment’s Contribution to Social Epistemology’. Episteme, 7, 7999.Google Scholar
Höwing, T. (2016) ‘Kant on Opinion, Belief and Knowledge’. In T. Höwing (ed.), The Highest Good in Kant’s Philosophy (Berlin: De Gruyter), 201222.Google Scholar
Kant, I. (1900-), Kants gesammelte Schriften. Berlin: De Gruyter, Reimer.Google Scholar
McCormick, M. (2015) Believing Against the Evidence: Agency and the Ethics of Belief. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Marušić, B. (2015) Evidence and Agency: Norms of Belief for Promising and Resolving. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Meier, G. F. (1752) Auszug auf der Vernunftlehre. Halle.Google Scholar
Pasternack, L. (2010) ‘Kant’s Doctrinal Belief in God’. In O. Thorndike (ed.), Rethinking Kant, vol. 3 (Newcastle upon Tyne: Cambridge Scholars Publishing), 200218.Google Scholar
Pasternack, L. (2011) ‘The Development and Scope of Kantian Belief: The Highest Good, the Practical Postulates and the Fact of Reason’. Kant-Studien, 102, 290315.Google Scholar
Pasternack, L. (2014) ‘Kant on Opinion: Assent, Hypothesis, and the Norms of General Applied Logic’. Kant-Studien, 105, 4182.Google Scholar
Perinetti, D. (2014) ‘Ways to Certainty’. In A. Garrett (ed.), The Routledge Companion to Eighteenth Century Philosophy (London: Routledge), 265293.Google Scholar
Pickering, M. (2016) ‘Kant’s Theoretical Reasons for Belief in Things in Themselves’. Kant-Studien , 107, 589616.Google Scholar
Reimarus, H. S. (1766) Vernunftlehre, als eine Anweisung zum richtigen Gebrauche der Vernunft in der Erkenntniß der Wahrheit, 3rd edn. Hamburg.Google Scholar
Rumore, P. (2018) ‘Kant and Crusius on the Role of Immortality in Morality’. In C. Dyck and F. Wunderlich (eds), Kant and his German Contemporaries (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 213231.Google Scholar
Schmucker, J. (1961) Die Ursprünge der Ethik Kants in seinen vorkritischen Schriften und Reflektionen. Meisenheim am Glan: Anton Hein.Google Scholar
Scholz, O. R. (2009) ‘Von Rom, den Antipoden und von Wundern: Das Zeugnis anderer in Logiken der Neuzeit’. In C. Spoerhase, D. Werle and M. Wild (eds), Unsicheres Wissen: Skeptizismus und Wahrscheinlichkeit 1550–1850 (Berlin: de Gruyter), 245268.Google Scholar
Schwaiger, C. (1999) Kategorische und andere Imperative: Zur Entwicklung von Kants praktischer Philosophie bis 1785. Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt: Frommann-Holzboog.Google Scholar
Shapiro, B. (1983) Probability and Certainty in Seventeenth-Century England: A Study of the Relationships between Natural Science, Religion, History, Law, and Literature. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Shapiro, B. (2003) A Culture of Fact: England, 1550–1720. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Spoerhase, C. (2009) ‘Die “mittelstrasse” zwischen Skeptizismus und Dogmatismus: Konzeptionen hermeneutischer Wahrscheinlichkeit um 1750’. In C. Spoerhase, D. Werle and M. Wild (eds), Unsicheres Wissen: Skeptizismus und Wahrscheinlichkeit 1550–1850 (Berlin: de Gruyter), 269300.Google Scholar
Stern, R. (2004) ‘Does “Ought” Imply “Can”? And did Kant Think it Does?Utilitas, 16, 4261.Google Scholar
Stern, R. (2016) ‘Round Kant or through Him? On James’s Arguments for Freedom, and their Relation to Kant’s’. In G. Gava and R. Stern (eds), Pragmatism, Kant and Transcendental Philosophy (London: Routledge), 152176.Google Scholar
Stevenson, L. (2003) ‘Opinion, Belief or Faith, and Knowledge’. Kantian Review, 7, 72100.Google Scholar
Tonelli, G. (1964) ‘Vorwort’. In C. A. Crusius, Die philosophischen Hauptwerke, vol. 1, ed. G. Tonelli (Hildesheim: Olms).Google Scholar
Walch, J. G. (1740) Philosophisches Lexikon, 2nd edn. Leipzig.Google Scholar
Warda, A. (1922) Immanuel Kants Bücher. Berlin: Martin Breslauer.Google Scholar
Willaschek, M. (2016) ‘Kant and Peirce on Belief’. In G. Gava and R. Stern (eds), Pragmatism, Kant and Transcendental Philosophy (London: Routledge), 133151.Google Scholar
Wolff, C. (1713) Vernünftige Gedanken von den Kräften des menschlichen Verstandes und ihrem richtigen Gebrauche in Erkenntnis der Wahrheit. Halle. (Reprinted in C. Wolff, Gesammelte Werke, ed. J. Ecole, H. W. Arndt, R. Theis, W. Schneiders and S. Carboncini-Gavanelli (Hildesheim: Olms, 1962–), Abt. 1, vol. 1.)Google Scholar