Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-jn8rn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-25T13:45:49.209Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Global Human Rights, Peace and Cultural Difference: Huntington and the Political Philosophy of International Relations

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  25 March 2011

Wolfgang Kersting
Affiliation:
Kiel University

Summary

In 1989, the age of power political realism ended. The conditions were set to replace the prevailing Hobbesian model of peace by deterrence with the considerably more challenging Kantian model of peace by right. If, however, Huntington's paradigm of fighting civilizations were right, we would have to forget Kant and remember Hobbes. Sober rationality, healthy distrust, striving for power accumulation and all the other instruments from the realist's toolbox of political prudence are very well suited to facilitate political self-assertion in an age of violently clashing cultures. However, this helplessness is not well grounded. Considering that from the very beginning liberalism is a theory of religious and ethical pluralism and well-experienced in dealing with problems of multiculturalism, it is at least possible to argue for a weak liberal universalism which provides normative foundations for a global order of peacefully living together. Of course, conceptual and moral modesty is crucial. If the human rights doctrine wants to defend its universal claim in the face of cultural diversity (which is defined as culturally different interpretations of a good, true and perfect human life), it has to restrict itself to the conditions of esse: the pre-cultural and sheer natural conditions of human being and human coexistence. However, the formulation of the conditions of bene esse (which enable human flourishing, let persons thrive and furnish human living with sense and significance) has to be left to culture and its authorities and belief systems which buttress a cultural constitution of meaning, both theologically and metaphysically. Traditional natural rights theory knew that both have to go together, and that the esse-enabling duties necessarily enjoy priority. No cultural conception of thriving life and existential significance can be accepted which contradicts the fundamental imperatives and conditions of pure human existence and coexistence.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Kantian Review 2002

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Notes

1 Fukuyama, Francis, ‘The end of history?’, The National Interest, 16 (1989).Google Scholar

2 Fukuyama, Francis, The End of History and the Last Man (New York: Free Press, 1993), p. xii.Google Scholar

3 Kojève, Alexandre, Introduction à la lecture de Hegel, 2nd edn (Paris: Gallimard, 1968)Google Scholar; on Kojève's conception of history see Auffret, Dominique, Alexandre Kojève: La Philosophie, l'État, la fin de l'Histoire (Paris, 1990).Google Scholar

4 , Fukuyama, ‘End of history?’, p. 18.Google Scholar

5 Gehlen, Arnold, Einblicke (Frankfurt/M.: Klostermann, 1975), p. 126.Google Scholar

6 Huntington, Samuel P., ‘The clash of civilizations?’, Foreign Affairs, 72 (1993), 2249; cf.CrossRefGoogle ScholarHuntington, Samuel P. et al., The Clash of Civilizations? The Debate (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1996)Google Scholar; Huntington, Samuel, Clash of Civilizations: Remaking of World Order (New York, 1996)Google Scholar.

7 And even Fukuyama had to accept being subsumed under the formula of his opponent, although only abroad: his book Trust: The Social Virtues and the Creation of Prosperity, published in 1995, was distributed in Germany under the title The Conflict of Cultures: Who Wins the Struggle for the Economic Future?

8 Cf. Küng, Hans, Projekt Weltethos (Munich: Piper, 1990)Google Scholar; Küng, Hans and Kuschel, Karl-Josef (eds), Erklärung zum Weltethos (Munich: Yale University Press, 1993)Google Scholar.

9 Ackerman, Bruce A., The Future of Liberal Revolution (New Haven and London, 1993).Google Scholar

10 Kersting, Wolfgang, ‘Philosophische Friedenstheorie und internationale Friedensordnung‘, in Recht, Gerechtigkeit und demokratische Tugend (Frankfurt/M.: Suhrkamp, 1997), 316–52.Google Scholar

11 Cf. Huntington, Samuel P., ‘The coming clash of civilizations, or, the West against the Rest’, New York Times (6 June 1993).Google Scholar

12 , Huntington, Clash of Civilizations: Remaking, p. 92.Google Scholar

14 Ibid., p. 318.

15 Cf. ibid., p. 42.

16 Lapid, Yosef and Kratochwil, Friedrich (eds), The Return of Culture and Identity in IR Theory (London: L. Rienner, 1996).Google Scholar

17 Jepperson, R. J. and Swidler, A., ‘What properties of culture should we measure?’, Poetics, 22 (1994), 359–71, 359.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

18 Cf. Waldron, Jeremy (ed.), Nonsense upon Stilts: Bentham, Burke and Marx on the Rights of Man (London: Methuen, 1987), p. 145.Google Scholar