Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-mkpzs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-25T12:59:47.114Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Kant and the Need for Orientational and Contextual Thinking: Applying Reflective Judgement to Aesthetics and to the Comprehension of Human Life

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  17 August 2020

Rudolf A. Makkreel*
Affiliation:
Emory University

Abstract

This essay explores the relation between worldly orientation and rational comprehension in Kant. Both require subjective grounds of differentiation that were eventually developed into a contextualizing principle for reflective judgement. This kind of judgement can proceed either inductively to find new universals or by analogy to symbolically link different objective spheres. I will argue that the basic orientational function of reflective judgement is to modally differentiate the formal horizonal contexts of field, territory, domain and habitat laid out in the Introduction to the Critique of the Power of Judgement. Assessing which context takes priority will be important in making aesthetic judgements and for applying practical reason to comprehend human affairs.

Type
Articles
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2020. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of Kantian Review

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Ameriks, Karl (2016) ‘Ginsborg, Nature, and Normativity’. British Journal of Aesthetics, 56(4), 389–95.Google Scholar
Benhabib, Seyla (2004) The Rights of Others: Aliens, Residents, and Citizens. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cazeaux, Clive (2004) ‘Kant and Metaphor in Contemporary Aesthetics’. Kantian Review, 8(1), 137.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Derrida, Jacques (1987) The Truth in Painting. Trans. Geoff Bennington and Ian McLeod. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dilthey, Wilhelm (1989) Introduction to the Human Sciences: Selected Works, vol. 1, ed. and trans. Rudolf A. Makkreel and Frithjof Rodi. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Dilthey, Wilhelm (2002) The Formation of the Historical World in the Human Sciences: Selected Works, vol. 3, ed. and trans. Rudolf A. Makkreel and Frithjof Rodi. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Flikschuh, Katrin (2000) Kant and Modern Political Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ginsborg, Hannah (2006) ‘Thinking the Particular as Contained under the Universal’. In Kukla, Rebecca (ed.), Aesthetics and Cognition in Kant’s Critical Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 3560.Google Scholar
Huseyinzadegan, Dilek (2019) Kant’s Nonideal Theory of Politics. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kant, I. (1900–) Gesammelte Schriften. Ed. Prussian Royal (later German, then Berlin-Brandenburg) Academy of the Sciences. Berlin: George Reimer (later Walter de Gruyter).Google Scholar
Kant, I. (1970) Kant: Political Writings. Ed. Hans Reiss, trans. H. B. Nisbet. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kant, I. (1992) Lectures on Logic. Ed. and trans. J. M. Young. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kant, I. (1996a) Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics. Trans. Paul Carus in Beryl Logan (ed.), Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics in Focus. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Kant, I. (1996b) The Metaphysics of Morals. Ed. and trans. M. Gregor. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kant, I. (1998) Religion within the Boundaries of Mere Reason and Other Writings. Ed. and trans. A. Wood and G. di Giovanni. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kant, I. (1999) Critique of Pure Reason. Ed. and trans. P. Guyer and A. Wood. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kant, I. (2000) Critique of the Power of Judgment. Ed. P. Guyer, trans. P. Guyer and E. Matthews. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kleingeld, Pauline (2012) Kant and Cosmopolitanism: The Philosophical Ideal of World Citizenship. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Langer, Susanne K. (1942) Philosophy in a New Key: A Study in the Symbolism of Reason, Rite and Art. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Langer, Susanne K. (1953) Feeling and Form: A Theory of Art Developed from Philosophy in a New Key. New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons.Google Scholar
Longuenesse, Béatrice (1998) Kant and the Capacity to Judge. Trans. Charles T. Wolfe. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Makkreel, Rudolf (1990) Imagination and Interpretation in Kant: The Hermeneutical Import of the Critique of Judgment. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Makkreel, Rudolf (2015) Orientation and Judgment in Hermeneutics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Makkreel, Rudolf (2018) ‘Kant on Cognition, Comprehension, and Knowledge’. In Violetta Waibel and Margit Ruffing (eds), Natur und Freiheit:. Akten des XII. Kant-Kongresses 2015 (Berlin: Walter de Gruyter), 1297–1304.Google Scholar
O’Neill, Onora (2018) From Principles to Practice: Normativity and Judgement in Ethics and Politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar