Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-t5tsf Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-14T23:21:47.559Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

How to make a risk seem riskier: The ratio bias versus construal level theory

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2023

Carissa Bonner
Affiliation:
School of Psychology, University of New South Wales
Ben R. Newell*
Affiliation:
School of Psychology, University of New South Wales
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Which statement conveys greater risk: “100 people die from cancer every day” or “36,500 people die from cancer every year”? In statistics where both frequencies and temporal information are used to convey risk, two theories predict opposite answers to this question.

Construal level theory predicts that “100 people die from cancer every day” will be judged as more risky, while the ratio bias predicts that the equivalent “36,500 people die from cancer every year” will result in higher risk judgments. An experiment investigated which format produces higher risk ratings, and whether ratings are influenced by increasing the salience of the numerical or temporal part of the statistic. Forty-eight participants were randomly assigned to a numerical, temporal or control salience condition, and rated risk framed as number of deaths per day or per year. The year format was found to result in higher perceived risk, indicating that the ratio bias effect is dominant, but there was no effect of salience.

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
The authors license this article under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution 3.0 License.
Copyright
Copyright © The Authors [2008] This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/3.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.

1 Introduction

The perception of risk is an important area of research not only for understanding cognitive processes, but also for its practical applications in conveying risk information to the public. In the health domain, perceived risk is generally regarded as the first step in models of health behaviour, and a necessary (but not sufficient) condition for behaviour change (see Weinstein (Reference Weinstein1993) and Van der Pligt (Reference Van der Pligt1996) for reviews). Although other factors have been shown to mediate this relationship (e.g., conscientiousness and gender; Hampson, Andrews, Barckley, Lichtenstein & Lee, Reference Hampson, Andrews, Barckley, Lichtenstein and Lee2000), conveying a sense of risk is a major focus of health communication, with the aim of influencing individual judgment and decision making. The present research investigates how risk perception is affected by the framing (cf. Tversky & Kahneman, Reference Tversky and Kahneman1981) of incidence rates, which are often used to convey risk information to the public.

1.1 Temporal construal

Construal Level Theory (CLT) proposes that temporal distance determines how future events are mentally represented (Trope & Liberman, Reference Trope and Liberman2003). Near events are represented at a lower level construal, defined as concrete, specific and detailed. Distant events are represented at a higher level construal, which are more abstract, decontexualised and general. For example, moving house next week is likely to be described in terms of concrete, specific actions such as packing boxes, while next year would be described in more abstract, global terms such as a new phase of life.

Chandron and Menon (Reference Chandron and Menon2004) extended this theory to risk perception, looking at the effects of message cues on judgments of health risk. They framed risks associated with mononucleosis as occurring “every day” or “every year”, and found that the day frame increased risk ratings. According to CLT, the risk is represented at the same construal level as the time frame. Since the day frame is perceived as more concrete and proximal than the year frame, the risk seems more immediate and threatening, resulting in higher perceived risk.

1.2 Ratio bias

The ratio bias is the tendency for people to judge a low probability event as more likely when presented as a large-numbered ratio, such as 20/100, than as a smaller-numbered but equivalent ratio, such as 2/10. This effect is attributed to a tendency to focus on the frequency of the numerator instead of the overall proportion (Kirkpatrick & Epstein, Reference Kirkpatrick and Epstein1992).

The ratio bias has been investigated in the health domain by Yamagishi (Reference Yamigishi1997) and Pinto-Prades, Martinez-Perez and Abellán-Perpiñán (Reference Pinto-Prades, Martinez-Perez and Abellán-Perpiñán2006). Yamagishi (Reference Yamigishi1997) gave participants mortality rates of well-known causes of death, varying both the percentage incidence rate and population frame (deaths per 100 or 10,000 people) within subjects. Results showed that ratings of risk were consistently higher with a frame of 10,000 than a frame of 100, regardless of the actual percentage incidence rate. For example, participants rated cancer as riskier when it was described as killing 1,286 out of 10,000 people than as killing 24.14 out of 100 people. The fact that 12.86% could be considered more risky than 24.14% is a clear demonstration that the ratio bias can strongly influence perception of risk. Similarly, Pinto-Prades et al. (Reference Pinto-Prades, Martinez-Perez and Abellán-Perpiñán2006) investigated the ratio bias in terms of choices between medical treatments with a given probability of death. They found that the frame determined the point at which participants reached indifference between choices: those given a smaller frame (per 100 people) would choose a particular treatment option up to a 37.1% chance of death, while those given a larger frame (per 1000 people), where the absolute number of deaths was higher, would only accept up to a 17.6% chance of death for the same treatment option.

1.3 Concrete versus abstract processing

What ties the temporal construal and ratio biases together is the difference between concrete and abstract information processing. The more concrete the information is, the easier it is to imagine and associate with affect (Newell, Mitchell, & Hayes, in press; Slovic, Monahan & MacGregor, Reference Slovic, Monahan and MacGregor2000), resulting in higher perceived risk. In temporal information, using a closer temporal frame such as “every day” increases the concreteness and proximity of the threat, and therefore increases perceived risk (Chandron & Menon, Reference Chandron and Menon2004). In numerical information, frequencies are more concrete than probabilities or percentages (e.g., Gigerenzer & Hoffrage, Reference Gigerenzer and Hoffrage1995; Slovic et al., Reference Slovic, Monahan and MacGregor2000). For example, Newell et al. (in press) found that frequency information led to higher ratings of the imaginability of rare events, such as suffering the side effects of a vaccine, than did probability information. In addition, small numbers are perceived as being more concrete than large numbers (Denes-Raj & Epstein, Reference Denes-Raj and Epstein1994), leading to a bias towards the numerator of a numerical ratio.

In statistics where both frequencies and temporal information are used to convey risk, these two biases towards concrete information will be in opposition to each other. Construal level theory predicts that “100 people die from cancer every day” will be perceived as more risky due to the use of closer temporal proximity. In contrast, the ratio bias effect predicts that “36,500 people die from cancer every year” will result in higher risk ratings, because risk will be inferred from the absolute number of deaths without sufficient regard for the temporal frame (day or year). The aim of the experiment was to investigate whether one of these effects is more dominant in health statistics, when the biases are in opposition.

2 Method

2.1 Participants

Forty-eight undergraduate students (35 female and 13 male) from the University of New South Wales participated for course credit, with an average age of 19.27 years (SD = 2.43).

2.2 Design

The experiment was set up as a 3 x (2 x 11) factorial design. The salience factor (emphasising the numerical or temporal information, versus a control condition) was between subjects, with 16 participants randomly assigned to each group. The format factor (every day versus every year) and cause of death (11 causes) were repeated within subjects, with the two formats completed one week apart. That is, each participant filled in a first questionnaire with one format (e.g., year) and then returned one week later (range: 6–9 days) to fill in a second questionnaire with the other format (e.g., day). The order of day and year formats was counterbalanced. A similar repeated measures design was used effectively in Yamagishi’s (Reference Yamigishi1997) study, and ensures that individual interpretations of “risk” and response tendencies are taken into account.

2.3 Materials

Following the method of Yamagishi (Reference Yamigishi1997), eleven major causes of death were used: heart failure, stroke, pneumonia, AIDS, motor vehicle accidents, cancer, homicide, respiratory diseases, renal failure, heart disease, and diabetes. Mortality rates were based on the government report Causes of Death, Australia 2003 (Australian Bureau of Statistics, 2004). The mortality rates were approximately equivalent for day and year formats, but were adjusted slightly to give numbers to the nearest 100 in some cases (this was not systematic, i.e., some rounded down and some rounded up). For example, the diabetes statistics used were 8 per day and 2,900 per year, even though 2,920 is the exact equivalent (i.e., 8 x 365). This approach was taken because the generic term “every year” was used, and the exact number of deaths from a particular cause varies each year.

The information about each cause of death was given in a single sentence followed by a rating scale, with all eleven causes on the same page. The order was arranged so that causes with similar incidence rates were not consecutive. To produce the numerical or temporal salience, the relevant information was placed at the beginning of the sentence in bold underlined font (as shown in Table 1). The effect of the font was enhanced by repetition for the eleven causes of death.

Table 1: Example of salience conditions (cancer deaths per day)

This is similar to the method of Chandron and Menon (Reference Chandron and Menon2004), who also used repetition of “every day” or “every year” at the beginning of sentences. Perceived risk was measured by a 26 point Likert scale, anchored at 0 “no risk at all” and 25 “highest possible risk”. This maintains consistency with the Yamigishi (Reference Yamigishi1997) study, and since it is a less familiar scale it may have decreased the possibility of participants remembering their previous responses when completing the second questionnaire (i.e., when they returned one week later). Participants were asked to rate the risk for the average Australian rather than themselves, in order to reduce the influence of personal experience and increase reliance on the statistics.

3 Results

The year format resulted in higher mean risk ratings than the day format, averaged across salience conditions and the eleven causes of death. Table 2 shows the mean risk ratings for each cause, all of which had higher risk ratings for the year format.

Table 2: Incidence rates and mean risk ratings for day and year formats, averaged across salience conditions. Scale anchored at 0 = “no risk at all” and 25 = “highest possible risk.”

A 3 x (2 x 11) repeated measures ANOVA was conducted, with factors of salience (control, numerical, temporal), format (day, year) and cause of death (11 causes). A significant main effect of format was found, such that the year format resulted in higher risk ratings than the day format (F(1,45) = 6.17, p = 0.017). As expected when using different incidence rates, there was also a significant main effect of cause (F(1,10) = 36.00; p = 0.000), indicating that the overall risk ratings varied amongst the different causes of death. The rank order of risk ratings amongst the 11 causes generally followed the rank order of incidence rates, with the exception of motor vehicle accidents and heart failure, which are ranked as relatively more risky than their incidence rates suggest. The reason for this is not immediately obvious, but it could be related to lower ratings for diabetes, pneumonia and respiratory diseases, which may be perceived as less obvious causes of death. There was no significant main effect of salience, and there were no significant interactions.Footnote 1 There was no significant main effect of order (day versus year format first), nor did this factor interact with any other factors.

On an individual level, almost two-thirds of the participants (30 out of 48) gave higher average year ratings than day ratings, with a mean difference of 3.57 (SD = 2.34) on the 26 point risk rating scale. The minority of participants (18 out of 48) who gave higher average day ratings than year ratings had a smaller mean difference of 2.49 (SD = 1.70). The higher ratings were not related to the order in which participants completed the two formats, suggesting that there are effects in both directions amongst the individual participants. This can be illustrated using a P-P plot, based on individual paired t-tests of day versus year ratings (11 causes x 2 formats). By definition of the p-value, if H0 is true, then the set of 48 individual p-values will be uniformly distributed from 0 to 1, with equal numbers and distribution in each direction. The cumulative probability for each observed p-value was calculated such that higher day ratings were equal to p/2 (i.e., small p-values approach 0) and higher year ratings were equal to 1-(p/2) (i.e., small p-values approach 1). Figure 1 shows the expected cumulative probabilities against the observed cumulative probabilities for H0. The graph clearly shows that the distribution of observed p-value probabilities deviates from the expected uniform distribution line, such that both directions have more participants at the extreme ends (i.e., small p-values) than would be expected by chance (particularly in the year higher than day direction, approaching 1 on the expected cumulative probability axis), and that overall there are more participants in the year higher than day direction (those above 0.5 on the expected cumulative probability axis).

Figure 1: P-P plot of the observed cumulative probability of individual p-values against the expected cumulative probability. Under the null hypothesis that risk ratings are equal in the day and year formats, a uniform distribution along the identity line is expected. Points above 0.5 on the expected cumulative probability axis indicate year higher than day, with the smallest p-values approaching 1. Points below 0.5 on the expected cumulative probability axis indicate day higher than year, with the smallest p-values approaching 0.

4 Discussion

The present research set out to investigate how different statistical formats influence risk perception. The aim was to find out which of two opposing effects — ratio bias or temporal construal — is more influential in judgments of risk, and whether this can be affected by a salience manipulation. The key finding was that when the ratio bias and the temporal construal effect are in opposition, the ratio bias appears to dominate. Across all eleven causes of death, risk ratings were higher when a “year” format (which had a large frequency based on a longer time period) was used than when a “day” format (which had a small frequency based on a shorter time period) was used. This was despite the fact that the incidence rates in the two formats were equivalent. Increasing the salience of numerical or temporal information through font and order within each statistic had no effect on the relative influence of the ratio bias and temporal construal.

The present experiment replicates and extends the findings of Yamagishi (Reference Yamigishi1997) by demonstrating that a temporal frame (e.g., day or year) is neglected in a similar way to a numerical frame (e.g., per 100 or 10,000) when rating the risk of causes of death. However, our failure to find an overall effect of temporal construal is inconsistent with the findings of Chandron and Menon (Reference Chandron and Menon2004). The different pattern of results may be due to the way in which temporal construal is manipulated. In their study, Chandron and Menon presented participants with risk descriptions of the form “Every year a significant number of people die from…”; this contrasts with the numerical information we provided (e.g., “Every year 100 people die from …”). It is possible that the effect of temporal construal demonstrated by Chandron and Menon (Reference Chandron and Menon2004) was due to the ambiguous nature of the phrase “a significant number of people.” In their discussion the authors acknowledge this possibility, suggesting that the temporal information may have been used as an indication of what “a significant number” meant. The numerical figures included in the present study overshadowed the effect of temporal construal for the majority of participants.

Although the term “ratio bias” usually refers to a numerical ratio, the effect found in the present experiment can be explained in the same way, using the heuristic of anchoring and adjustment (Tversky & Kahnemann, Reference Tversky and Kahneman1974).Footnote 2 According to this account, the number of deaths is used as a cue to ratings of risk, with insufficient adjustment for the frame (day or year). In this case, the statistic was framed in a temporal form, but the same principle can be applied to any statistic where a frequency is given in context — successful operations per hospital, faulty goods per order, robberies per suburb, etc. Any frame may be neglected in a similar way to the more typical numerical denominator, leading to greater perceived risk whenever a larger frame (and therefore higher frequency) is used.

The finding that the ratio bias persists even when placed in opposition to the effect of temporal frame adds to existing evidence of its strong influence on judgment and decision making. The ratio bias has been shown to cause non-optimal decisions in both forced choice tasks (Denes-Raj & Epstein, Reference Denes-Raj and Epstein1994) and more realistic scenarios, such as choosing which job to apply for (Alonso & Fernandez-Berrocal, Reference Alonso and Fernandez-Berrocal2003). Monetary incentives to make better choices may reduce the number of non-optimal choices within subjects, but even this does not prevent the effect of the ratio bias (Dale, Rudski, Schwarz & Smith, Reference Dale, Rudski, Schwarz and Smith2007).

From the individual results, the finding that some participants show the opposite effect (i.e., risk ratings higher in the day format) could be related to individual differences in numeracy (Reyna & Brainerd, Reference Reyna and Brainerd2008). When a mixed numerical/temporal ratio is provided, the less numerate participants may focus more on the non-numerical information (day or year) as a cue to risk ratings, leading to a bias towards the closer temporal proximity of the day format. Again, this could be attributed to anchoring and adjustment (Tversky & Kahnemann, Reference Tversky and Kahneman1974), where there is a focus on one part of the statistic with insufficient adjustment for the accompanying information.

The ratio bias has practical implications for risk communication. A simple incidence rate may be the first awareness some people have of a particular risk, so increasing risk perception by using the most effective format could be the difference needed for them to take further action. Although a sense of risk may not itself be sufficient to modify behaviour, it is considered in most health models to be a necessary precondition (Weinstein, Reference Weinstein1993; Van der Pligt, Reference Van der Pligt1996), so anything that increases perceived risk, such as using a larger frame to describe incidence rates, will also increase the chance of reaching positive behavioural outcomes. Although this perspective assumes that increasing risk perception is desirable, it should be acknowledged that such an effect may not always be accurate or beneficial (such as overweighting the risk of side effects from a vaccine, when avoiding the vaccine is actually more risky). In addition, using mixed statistics where the frequency and its frame are in different forms (such as numerical/temporal) may lead to reduced accuracy in risk perception as a result of individual biases towards one form over the other.

Further research on the use of different statistical formats, including non-numerical frames, would enable a better understanding of its effect on risk perception.

Footnotes

*

This research was supported by a Discovery Grant (DP 0558181) from the Australian Research Council awarded to the second author. The authors would like to thank Tim Rakow for extremely helpful and insightful comments on an earlier draft of this manuscript. Correspondence should be addressed to Ben Newell, School of Psychology, University of New South Wales, NSW 2052, Australia.

1 Although the difference between day and year ratings appears to be more pronounced amongst the causes with lower incidence rates, there is no significant interaction between cause of death and day versus year format.

2 See Denes-Raj and Epstein (Reference Denes-Raj and Epstein1994) for an alternative explanation of the ratio bias, based on cognitive-experiential self theory: CEST.

References

Alonso, A., & Fernandez-Berrocal, P. (2003). Irrational decisions: attending to numbers rather than ratios. Personality and Individual Differences, 35, 15371547.10.1016/S0191-8869(02)00368-9CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Australian Bureau of Statistics (2003). Causes of death, Australia 2003. http://www.abs.gov.auGoogle Scholar
Chandron, S. & Menon, G. (2004). When a day means more than a year: effects of temporal framing on judgments of health risk. Journal of Consumer Research, 31, 375389.10.1086/422116CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dale, D., Rudski, J., Schwarz, A. & Smith, E. (2007). Innumeracy and incentives: A ratio bias experiment. Judgment and Decision Making, 2, 243250.10.1017/S1930297500000577CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Denes-Raj, V. & Epstein, S. (1994). Conflict between intuitive and rational processing: When people behave against their better judgment. Journal of Personality & Social Psychology, 66, 819829.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gigerenzer, G. & Hoffrage, U. (1995). How to improve Bayesian reasoning without instruction: Frequency formats. Psychological Review, 102, 684704.10.1037/0033-295X.102.4.684CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hampson, S. E., Andrews, J. A., Barckley, M., Lichtenstein, E. & Lee, M. E. (2000). Conscientiousness, perceived risk, and risk-reduction behaviors: A preliminary study. Health Psychology, 19, 496500.10.1037/0278-6133.19.5.496CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kirkpatrick, L., & Epstein, S. (1992). Cognitive-Experiential Self-Theory and subjective probability: Further evidence for two conceptual systems. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 63, 534544.10.1037/0022-3514.63.4.534CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Newell, B. R., Mitchell, C. J. & Hayes, B. K. (in press). Getting scarred and winning lotteries: Effects of exemplar cuing and statistical format on imagining low probability events. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making.Google Scholar
Pinto-Prades, J. L., Martinez-Perez, J. E. & Abellán-Perpiñán, J. M. (2006). The influence of the ratio bias phenomenon on the elicitation of health states utilities. Judgment and Decision Making, 1, 118133.10.1017/S1930297500002333CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reyna, V. F. & Brainerd, C. J. (2008). Numeracy, ratio bias, and denominator neglect in judgments of risk and probability. Learning and Individual Differences, 18, 89107.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Slovic, P., Monahan, J. & MacGregor, D. G. (2000). Violence risk assessment and risk communication: The effects of using actual cases, providing instruction, and employing the probability versus frequency formats. Law and Human Behavior, 24, 271296.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Trope, Y. & Liberman, N. (2003). Temporal construal. Psychological Review, 110, 403421.10.1037/0033-295X.110.3.403CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Tversky, A. & Kahneman, D. (1974). Judgment under uncertainty: Heuristics and biases. Science, 185, 11241131.10.1126/science.185.4157.1124CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Tversky, A. & Kahneman, D. (1981). The framing of decisions and the psychology of choice. Science, 211, 453458.10.1126/science.7455683CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Van der Pligt, J. (1996). Risk protection and self protective behaviour. European Psychologist, 1, 3443.10.1027/1016-9040.1.1.34CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weinstein, N. D. (1993). Testing four competing theories of health-protective behavior. Health Psychology, 12, 324333.10.1037/0278-6133.12.4.324CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Yamigishi, K. (1997). When a 12.86% mortality is more dangerous than 24.14%: Implications for risk communication. Applied Cognitive Psychology, 11, 495506.10.1002/(SICI)1099-0720(199712)11:6<495::AID-ACP481>3.0.CO;2-J3.0.CO;2-J>CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Figure 0

Table 1: Example of salience conditions (cancer deaths per day)

Figure 1

Table 2: Incidence rates and mean risk ratings for day and year formats, averaged across salience conditions. Scale anchored at 0 = “no risk at all” and 25 = “highest possible risk.”

Figure 2

Figure 1: P-P plot of the observed cumulative probability of individual p-values against the expected cumulative probability. Under the null hypothesis that risk ratings are equal in the day and year formats, a uniform distribution along the identity line is expected. Points above 0.5 on the expected cumulative probability axis indicate year higher than day, with the smallest p-values approaching 1. Points below 0.5 on the expected cumulative probability axis indicate day higher than year, with the smallest p-values approaching 0.