Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-r5fsc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-30T14:55:29.606Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Exploiting moral wiggle room: Illusory preference for fairness? A comment

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2023

Tara Larson
Affiliation:
University of Texas at Dallas
C. Monica Capra*
Affiliation:
Emory University
*
*Address: C. Monica Capra, Department of Economics, Emory University, 1602 Fishburne Dr., Atlanta, GA 30322. Email: [email protected].
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

We designed an experiment to test the robustness of Dana, Weber, and Kuang’s (DWK), 2007 results. DWK observed that, when participants were given a “costless” way — the click of a button — to ignore the consequences of their actions on others’ payoffs, they chose to remain ignorant and fair behavior diminished. By implementing a double-blind experiment together with a design that controls for alternative explanations for the observed behavior, we confirmed DWK’s findings.

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
The authors license this article under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution 3.0 License.
Copyright
Copyright © The Authors [2009] This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/3.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.

1 Introduction

Previous works have indicated that, although individuals often act altruistically (e.g., Reference BeckerBecker 1974; Reference AndreoniAndreoni 1989, 1990) they also engage in strategic ignorance and thus avoid situations where altruism might be expected or required of them (Reference Bolton, Katok and ZwickBolton, Katok, & Zwick, 1998; Reference KonowKonow, 2000; Carrillo & Marriotti 2000; Reference Dana, Cain and DawesDana, Cain & Dawes, 2006). In a recent paper, Reference Dana, Weber and KuangDana, Weber & Kuang (2007) — henceforth DWK — presented results of an experiment where participants were given a choice of either remaining uninformed about the effects of their actions on someone else’s earnings, or clicking a button on the computer screen to learn about how their decisions could affect another participant’s earnings. Despite this “costless” mechanism, half of the participants in their experiment chose strategic ignorance and, subsequently, selfish actions. In contrast, when participants’ did not have a choice to remain ignorant, behavior was mostly altruistic.

Based on these data, DWK argue that the generosity observed in many experiments may not be due to a preference for a fair outcome, but may be a result of “…people feeling compelled to give due to situational factors, while not really valuing the corresponding outcome” (p. 77). Indeed, DWK observed that, when the one-to-one mapping between actions and outcomes was relaxed, fair behavior diminished. Given the potential significance of these findings in reshaping the discussion of the motives for fair and altruistic behavior and the role that situational factors may play in influencing them, here we check the robustness of DWK’s results to an alternative experimental design.

In DWK’s experiment, subjects were asked to click on a button on the screen to make the consequences of their actions transparent. In addition to a preference for strategic ignorance, there are alternative reasons for why subjects in their experiments may have chosen not to click the button (remain ignorant) and behaved selfishly. First, subjects may have perceived the click of a button as costly, not costless. An extra click requires an additional effort (the click). Secondly, the click may have been avoided because it generated a delay in consumption. In DWK’s experiment, a participant who chooses to reveal the other’s payoffs is forced to wait to learn about the other’s earnings before being able to consume her own payoff. Finally, and more importantly, it is possible that omission bias (i.e., the tendency to judge harmful actions as worse, or less moral than equally harmful inactions — see Reference Ritov and BaronRitov & Baron, 1995) may have caused the curious results. Indeed, one can reasonably expect more generosity in an experimental design where transparency is the default choice and its avoidance the “click” option.

In this paper, by altering the way we ask participants to reveal or not reveal information about others’ earnings, we control for decision costs, consumption delay, and (with some caveats) omission bias. Indeed, in our experiment, to reveal or not reveal information about the other’s payoffs required the same amount of effort and time, and both options required an action or commission. Footnote 1 We also implement a double-blind experiment to generate the most reliable environment to test participant’s decisions. Interestingly, overall, our results confirm the results of Data, Weber & Kuang. We find that individuals engage in strategic ignorance and, when the consequences of their actions are not fully transparent, fair choices diminish.

2 Experimental design

2.1 Subjects and earnings

A total of 54 college students were recruited for a thirty-minute experiment. They were recruited from various departments at Emory University through public announcements and e-mails. There were a total six sessions; at the beginning of each session, each subject was seated in an isolated booth and was assigned a role of either the dictator (Player X) or the receiver (Player Y) by drawing slips of paper from an envelope. The dictator determined his own payoffs and the payoffs that the second player received. In addition to the earnings determined by the dictators, all participants received a $5.00 show-up fee. The average earnings in the experiment (including the show-up fee) were about $10.

2.2 Transparent treatment (baseline)

Our baseline treatment was similar to DWK’s, but we did not use computer terminals and our experiment was double-blind. We implemented a double-blind decision to eliminate potential experimenter induced biases. Participants were given a payoff identical to the table shown below. At the beginning of our baseline sessions, the dictators made their choice of either Action A or B privately and anonymously. In our experiments, subjects made their decisions by opening one of two folders labeled A or B that contained envelopes with payments for both players. They were then asked to get their payment from the envelope and leave B’s payment inside the envelope. Subsequently, subjects dropped the envelopes containing B’s payments inside a box, which we later recovered and distributed among Y players. At no time did we know who, among the X players, had chosen A or B (see instructions for this experiment in Appendix A).

In the baseline treatment, the earnings for both dictators and receivers were common knowledge, thus the consequences of the dictators’ actions were transparent. Notice that B resulted in both players making $5, but A rendered one additional dollar to Player X at the expense of Y, who would get only $1. We refer to this game as the conflicting interest game (CIG). After making a choice, the dictators left the experiment with their payment, which was paid to them anonymously and in cash. Receivers were then randomly matched with a dictator’s decision and also paid anonymously in cash before they left.

2.3 Non-transparent treatment

The non-transparent treatments were also run double-blind and without computers, otherwise, they closely followed the experimental design of DWK (see Appendix B). Below are the payoff tables of two Dictator Games. The upper payoff table contains payoffs where Player X’s best interest is in conflict with Player Y’s. Again, we call this game conflicting interest game (CIG) — notice that this game is identical to that found above. The lower payoff table, on the other hand, shows payoffs where Player X’s best interest is in line with Player Y’s. We call this the similar interest game (SIG); indeed, both the dictator and the receiver earn the most when Action A is chosen.

In our non-transparent treatments, subjects did not know which game they were playing before making their choices, but they were informed that a coin flip, before the session began, had determined which game they would play. Note that, as shown below, in both games Player X’s payoffs were the same, but Player Y’s payoffs depended on which one of the games was being played.

Before deciding on an action (A or B), the dictator had to determine whether or not he wanted to know which of these games was being played. Each dictator was faced with two folders labeled REVEAL PLAYER Y’S PAYOFFS and DO NOT REVEAL PLAYER Y’S PAYOFFS. Dictators were instructed to open the folder corresponding to their choice to either reveal or not reveal which game was being played. If the dictator chose to reveal the game, he opened the REVEAL folder, where he saw the appropriate game (determined before the session began by a random draw), then he chose either Action A or Action B. If a dictator chose to not reveal which of the two games was being played (remaining strategically ignorant), he opened the DO NOT REVEAL folder, where he saw the game matrix as shown below. This table does not tell which game is being played, as the receiver’s payoffs are blocked with a question mark. The dictators then chose either action A or action B.

Payoff table when the “not reveal” option was chosen

To keep it double-blind, the choice of an action was implemented by allowing subjects to select a labeled envelope that contained an amount of money equal to the sum of X and Y’s payoffs for that game. For example, if the conflicting interest game was being played, inside the folder, there were two envelopes labeled A and B with $7 and $10, respectively. Subjects would take the money from one of the envelopes, keep her payment, place B’s payment in a blank envelope, and move to a private area, where the blank envelope was dropped inside a box. The envelopes with B’s payments were later picked (but never opened) and distributed to the receivers. In contrast to the design of DWK, here, both options: to reveal or not reveal, required the same amount of effort (opening a folder), rendered equal consumption time delay, and required a positive action (commission).

Finally, in the non-transparent treatment, while all the dictators were making their decisions, receivers were asked to predict dictators’ choices, to report what they would choose if they were a dictator and what they hoped their matched dictator would choose. Footnote 2 Clearly, the answers to these questions had no effect on the dictators’ actions, but enabled us to confirm the clarity of the instructions, and the participants’ understanding of the experiment and its consequences.

3 Results

Overall, our results are similar to DWK’s results. As shown on Table 1, in the CIG baseline treatment, 78% of our dictators chose Action B, giving up one dollar of earnings to increase the receiver’s earnings by four dollars. In comparison, DWK, found that 74% of the dictators behaved altruistically; these proportions are statistically equal (Fisher Exact Test, p=1.00).

Table 1: Dictators’ decisions in all treatments.

In contrast to our baseline treatment, in our non-transparent treatment, the percentage of players choosing B (the altruistic choice) when the conflicting interest game (CIG) was played was only 22%. The null hypothesis that the proportion of dictators that acted selfishly when playing the CIG in the baseline and non-transparent treatments is the same can be rejected (Fisher Exact Test, p=0.028). Again, this result is similar to the findings in DWK, who report that only 37% of the subjects behaved altruistically in the CIG non-transparent condition as compared to 74% in the CIG baseline treatment.

As in DWK’s experiment, about half of our subjects chose to remain ignorant about the consequences of their actions. In fact, 53% of our subjects chose not to reveal information. As in DWK, among those who chose not to reveal information about the other’s earnings, 100% chose Action A (the selfish action). Finally, and in contrast to DWK, in our non-transparent treatment most of the participants who chose to reveal information in the CIG also chose the selfish option (Action A). The difference, however, is not statistically significant. With a bigger sample, we speculate that the difference may become significant. It is possible that participants who reveal and choose Action A feel less guilty about being selfish when they know that the receivers do not fully know whether the payoff matrix had been revealed to them (the dictators). Thus, even when one knows the consequences of one’s actions, the uncertainty regarding whether the receiver knows this may give the dictator some wiggle room to be selfish.

The existence of strategic ignorance was further reflected to us in the self-reported responses of receivers. Receivers were asked to imagine the motivation of dictators in their choice of folders. We transcribed some of the writings, most of which provided very similar arguments. For example, one participant said: “by looking in the do not reveal folder the decision will then be easier.” Another argued that a likely motivation for looking in the “do not reveal” folder would be “…to maximize payoffs…to remain blind to what they are doing to the other person.” Finally, someone suggested that “…it is better to remain in denial about the repercussions of the decisions one is making.

Overall, as show by the last two columns in Table 1, we evidently observe a clear tendency to be more selfish in the non-transparent treatment.

4 Discussion

In this comment we investigated the robustness of Dana et al.’s (2007) results to changes in the implementation of the experiment. In particular, we were concerned that in their design the revelation of information required an additional action (clicking a button on the computer screen). We believe that such action was not costless. Indeed, it is possible that a preference for strategic ignorance and the observed selfish behavior was motivated by the avoidance of an additional effort, by the avoidance of delayed consumption, and more importantly, by a preference for the current state (omission bias).

We designed an experiment that would control Footnote 3 for these possible confounds — in addition to making it double-blind — to see if we could replicate DWK’s main findings. Consistent with their results, we found that, when given a chance, most people would prefer to stay ignorant about the consequences of their actions on others’ earnings. We also observed an increase of selfish behavior in the non-transparent setup. Thus, DWK’s results are not an artifact of their experimental design. Our replication of their findings may further challenge experimental and behavioral economists into thinking about the motives for observed altruistic and fair behavior in the lab, and the role that situational factors may play in influencing them. Indeed, it does seem that participants do not particularly care much for the other’s well-being when the outcomes of their actions are not fully transparent.

Appendix A

Instructions

This is an experiment in the economics of decision-making. Several research institutions have provided funds for this research. You will be paid for your participation in the experiment. The exact amount you will be paid will depend on your and/or others’ decisions. Your payment will consist of the amount you accumulate plus a $5 participation bonus. You will be paid privately in cash at the conclusion of the experiment.

If you have a question during the experiment, raise your hand and an experimenter will assist you. Please do not talk, exclaim, or try to communicate with other participants during the experiment. Please put away all outside materials (such as book bags, notebooks) before starting the experiment. Participants violating the rules will be asked to leave the experiment and will not be paid.

How to participate in the experiment

In this experiment, each of you will play a game with one other person in the room. We will randomly match people into pairs. The grouping will be anonymous, meaning that no one will ever know which person in the room they played with. Each of you will be randomly assigned a role in this game. Your role will be player X or player Y. This role will also be kept anonymous. The difference between these roles will be described below. Thus, exactly one half of you will be a Player X and one half a Player Y. Also, each of you will be in a pair that includes exactly one of each of these types.

The game your pair will play will be like the one pictured below. Player X will choose one of two options: “A” or “B”. Player Y will not make any choice. Both players will receive payments based on the choice of Player X. The numbers in the table are the payments players receive. The payments in this table were chosen only to demonstrate how the game works. In the actual game, the payments will be different.

For example, if player X chooses “B”, then we should look in the square to the right of option “B” for the earnings. Here, Player X receives 3 dollars and Player Y receives 4 dollars. Notice that player X’s payment is in the lower left corner of the square, player Y’s payment is in the upper right corner.

At this point, to make sure that everyone understands the game, please answer the following questions:

In this example, if Player X chooses “B” then:

Player X receives __

Player Y receives __

In this example, if Player X chooses “A” then:

Player X receives __

Player Y receives __

Today’s game

Player X will be called one at a time to the back of the room. At station 1, there will be a folder in front of Player X. When Player X opens the folder they will see the game below.

Player X gets their highest payment of $6 by choosing A and they get a lower payment of $5 by choosing B. However, Player Y’s payoff is highest of $5 if Player X chooses B and lowest at $1 if Player X chooses A.

Inside the folder there will be two envelopes labeled Choice A and Choice B. Player X will remove the envelope with their choice of the pay-offs. Inside the envelope is Player X’s payment for the experiment today (including the $5 for participating). Player X may take their envelope with them when they leave the room.

NOTE: Player X may take only one envelope (Choice A or Choice B).

Player X’s choice which envelope they take will be anonymous. Thus Player Y and the experimenters will not know which envelope each Player X chose. When the game ends, we will pay each player privately.

Player X will take the folder they opened with them to station 2. At station 2, there is a box to drop the folder with the remaining envelope. Then at station 2, Player X will be asked to sign a payment form stating the amount of money they choose to receive. This is left anonymous by asking participants to sign the form using their Emory ID or Social Security number. The purpose of this form is to show those funding the experiment that their money was actually used in an experiment. Your choice will remain private and even the experimenters will not know what option you choose.

After all Player X’s have left the room, Player Y will be randomly matched with a Player X and will receive an envelope (with their pay-off inside) corresponding to the Choice Player X made and the game that was played. Player Y’s will then be asked to sign a payment sheet (a separate one from the one Player X’s used).

Summary

  • Player X will be called to the back of the room to Station 1.

  • At station 1 Player X will have to choose payoffs A or B by removing their choice envelope

  • At station 2 Player X will drop off their folder with the remaining envelope and sign a confidential payment sheet. They are then free to leave with their payment in their choice envelope.

  • Player Y will then be randomly matched with a Player X and will receive their payment for today’s experiment dependent upon Player X’s choice of payoffs.

Appendix B

Instructions

This is an experiment in the economics of decision-making. Several research institutions have provided funds for this research. You will be paid for your participation in the experiment. The exact amount you will be paid will depend on your and/or others’ decisions. Your payment will consist of the amount you accumulate plus a $5 participation bonus. You will be paid privately in cash at the conclusion of the experiment.

If you have a question during the experiment, raise your hand and an experimenter will assist you. Please do not talk, exclaim, or try to communicate with other participants during the experiment. Please put away all outside materials (such as book bags, notebooks) before starting the experiment. Participants violating the rules will be asked to leave the experiment and will not be paid.

How to participate in the experiment

In this experiment, each of you will play a game with one other person in the room. We will randomly match people into pairs. The grouping will be anonymous, meaning that no one will ever know which person in the room they played with. Each of you will be randomly assigned a role in this game. Your role will be player X or player Y. This role will also be kept anonymous. The difference between these roles will be described below. Thus, exactly one half of you will be a Player X and one half a Player Y. Also, each of you will be in a pair that includes exactly one of each of these types.

The game your pair will play will be like the one pictured below. Player X will choose one of two options: “A” or “B”. Player Y will not make any choice. Both players will receive payments based on the choice of Player X. The numbers in the table are the payments players receive. The payments in this table were chosen only to demonstrate how the game works. In the actual game, the payments will be different.

For example, if player X chooses “B”, then we should look in the square to the right of option “B” for the earnings. Here, Player X receives 3 dollars and Player Y receives 4 dollars. Notice that player X’s payment is in the lower left corner of the square, player Y’s payment is in the upper right corner.

At this point, to make sure that everyone understands the game, please answer the following questions:

In this example, if Player X chooses “B” then:

Player X receives __

Player Y receives __

In this example, if Player X chooses “A” then:

Player X receives __

Player Y receives __

Today’s game

Player X will be called one at a time to the back of the room. At station 1, there will be two folders in front of player X. One is labeled REVEAL Y’S PAYOFFS and the other is labeled DO NOT REVEAL Y’S PAYOFFS.

NOTE: Player X may only open ONE folder (either REVEAL Y’S PAYOFFS or DO NOT REVEAL Y’S PAYOFFS)

If Player X opens the REVEAL Y’S PAYOFFS folder, they will see one of the two games pictured below that they will play in today’s experiment. The actual game you will play (game 1 or game 2 below) was determined by a coin flip before the experiment. The probability of each game is thus exactly ½.

Notice that both games are the same except that Player Y’s payments are flipped between the two. In both games, Player X gets their highest payment of $6 by choosing A and they get a lower payment of $5 by choosing B. However, Player Y’s payoff of either $5 or $1 is dependent upon which game is being played. Note the only thing that differs between the two games is the payments for Player Y.

At this point, to make sure that everyone understands the game if Player X opens the REVEAL PLAYER Y’S PAYOFFS folder, please answer the following questions:

In both games, which action gives player X his or her highest payment of $6? __

If Player X chooses B, then Player Y receives __

  1. a) $5

  2. b) $1

  3. c) either $5 or $1

If Player X opens the DO NOT REVEAL Y’S PAYOFF folder they will see the game pictured below.

Hence by opening this folder, Player X chooses to leave the payoffs for Player Y NOT REVEALED. By opening this folder, Player X chooses not to know if game 1 or game 2 (above) is being played and only know his/her own payoffs and not those of Player Y.

Note: regardless of which folder Player X chooses to open, the payoffs for Player Y are the same. Hence in each experiment either game 1 or game 2 above will be played, which was determined by a coin flip before the experiment began. X’s choice of payoffs (A or B) will mean the same thing for Y and is not effected by which folder Player X chooses to open.

Inside either folder there will be two envelopes labeled Choice A and Choice B. Player X will remove the envelope with their choice of the pay-offs. Inside the envelope is Player X’s payment for the experiment today (including the $5 for participating). Player X may take their envelope with them when they leave the room.

NOTE: Player X may take only one envelope (Choice A or Choice B).

Player X’s choice of looking in the REVEAL Y’S PAYOFFS or DO NOT REVEAL Y’S PAYOFFS folder and which envelope they take will be anonymous. Thus Player Y and the experimenters will not know if X knows which game is being played and which envelope each Player X chose. When the game ends, we will pay each player privately.

Player X will take the folder they choose to open with them to station 2. At station 2, there is a box to drop the folder with the remaining envelope. Then at station 2, Player X will be asked to sign a payment form stating the amount of money they choose to receive. This is left anonymous by asking participants to sign the form using their Emory ID or Social Security number. The purpose of this form is to show those funding the experiment that their money was actually used in an experiment. Your choice will remain private and even the experimenters will not know what option you choose or what folder you personally used to make your choice.

After all Player X’s have left the room, Player Y will be randomly matched with a Player X and will receive an envelope (with their pay-off inside) corresponding to the Choice Player X made and the game that was played. Player Y’s will then be asked to sign a payment sheet (a separate one from the one Player X’s used).

While Player X’s are making their decisions, Player Y’s will be asked to fill out a form predicting what decisions they believe Player X’s will make.

Summary

  • Player X will be called to the back of the room to Station 1.

  • At station 1 Player X will have 2 decisions:

    1. 1. to look in REVEAL Y’S PAYOFFS or DO NOT REVEAL Y’S PAYOFFS folder

    2. 2. to choose payoffs A or B by removing their choice envelope

  • At station 2 Player X will drop off their folder with the remaining envelope and sign a confidential payment sheet. They are then free to leave with their payment in their choice envelope.

  • Player Y will then be randomly matched with a Player X and will receive their payment for today’s experiment dependent upon Player X’s choice of payoffs.

  • As Player X is making their decisions, Player Y will fill out a form that is kept anonymous and is only viewed by the experimenters.

Appendix C: Forms for Player Y

  1. 1. Which folder do you believe most Player X’s will look in? Why?

  2. 2. What will stop Player X’s from looking in the other folder that the one you predicted above?

  3. 3. Which folder do you want Player X to look in?

  4. 4. What folder would you look in if you were Player X?

Footnotes

*

We would like to thank Rachel Croson, Catherine Eckel, Charles Noussair, and the participants of the 2008 North American Economics Science Association meetings for their helpful comments.

1 We would like to introduce a caveat. Here, we interpret the act of making a choice (either reveal or not reveal) as commission. Consequently, the lack of action is an omission. However, it is unclear what people truly think an omission is. It is possible that, although action is required to make a choice, “DO NOT reveal player Y’s payoffs” may still be perceived as an omission.

2 This form can be found in Appendix C.

3 Please note caveat in footnote 1.

References

Andreoni, J. (1989). Giving with impure altruism: applications to charity and Ricardian Equivalence. Journal of Political Economy, 97, 14471458.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Andreoni, J. (1990). Impure altruism and donations to public goods: A theory of warm glow giving. The Economic Journal, 100, 464477.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Becker, G. (1974). A theory of social interactions. Journal of Political Economy, 82, 10631093.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bolton, G. E., Katok, E., & Zwick, R. (1998). Dictator game giving: rules of fairness versus acts of kindness. International Journal of Game Theory 27, 269299.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carrillo, J., & Mariotti, T. (2000). Strategic ignorance as a self-disciplining device. Review of Economic Studies, 67, 529544.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dana, J., Cain, D. M., & Dawes, R. M. (2006). What you don’t know won’t hurt me: Costly (but quiet) exit in dictator games. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 100, 193201.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dana, J., Weber, R., & Kuang, J. (2007). Exploiting moral wriggle room: experiments demonstrating an illusory preference for fairness. Economic Theory, 33, 6780.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Konow, J. (2000). Fair shares: accountability and cognitive dissonance in allocation decisions. American Economic Review, 90, 10721091.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ritov, I., & Baron, J. (1995). Outcome knowledge, regret, and omission bias. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 64, 119127.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Figure 0

Table 1: Dictators’ decisions in all treatments.