Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-hc48f Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-28T19:41:16.341Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

“Decisions from experience” = sampling error + prospect theory: Reconsidering Hertwig, Barron, Weber & Erev (2004)

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2023

Craig R. Fox*
Affiliation:
Anderson School of Management and Department of Psychology University of California at Los Angeles
Liat Hadar
Affiliation:
Anderson School of Management University of California at Los Angeles
*
*Address Correspondence to: Craig R. Fox, UCLA Anderson School, 110 Westwood Plaza #D511, Los Angeles, CA 90095-1481, Voice: 310/206-3403, Email: [email protected]
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

According to prospect theory, people overweight low probability events and underweight high probability events. Several recent papers (notably, Hertwig, Barron, Weber & Erev, 2004) have argued that although this pattern holds for “description-based” decisions, in which people are explicitly provided with probability distributions over potential outcomes, it is actually reversed in “experience-based” decisions, in which people must learn these distributions through sampling. We reanalyze the data of Hertwig et al. (2004) and present a replication to determine the extent to which their phenomenon can be attributed to sampling error (a statistical rather than psychological phenomenon) versus underestimation of rare events (i.e., judgmental bias) versus actual underweighting of judged probabilities. We find that the apparent reversal of prospect theory in decisions from experience can be attributed almost entirely to sampling error, and are consistent with prospect theory and the two-stage model of decision under uncertainty (Fox & Tversky, 1998).

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
The authors license this article under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution 3.0 License.
Copyright
Copyright © The Authors [2006] This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/3.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.

Several recent papers have contrasted “decisions from description” with “decisions from experience”. In the former, people are explicitly provided probability distributions over potential outcomes; in the latter, probabilities and outcomes are not provided but must be learned by sampling from these distributions. Perhaps most notable is an experiment presented by Hertwig, Barron, Weber and Erev (Reference Hertwig, Barron, Weber and Erev2004, hereafter HBWE) that was also described in detail by Weber, Shafir and Blais (Reference Weber, Shafir and Blais2004) and Hertwig, Barron, Weber and Erev (Reference Hertwig, Barron, Weber, Erev, Fiedler and Juslin2005). In this experiment students either saw six decision problems (e.g., gain 4 points with probability .8; gain 0 otherwise; for a list of all lottery pairs see Table 1) or sampled outcomes (with replacement) from unlabeled buttons associated with these pairs of payoff distributions. After sampling draws from each button as many times as they wished, participants indicated which lottery they preferred to play once for real money. The authors characterize their results as follows: “In the case of decisions from description, people make choices as if they overweight the probability of rare events, as described by prospect theory....in the case of decisions from experience, in contrast, people make choices as if they underweight the probability of rare events.” They conclude their abstract with a “call for two different theories of risky choice.” Although we are sympathetic to the investigation of decisions from experience, we believe that the call for two different theories of risky choice is premature as HBWE’s results are driven almost entirely by sampling error and are consistent with prospect theory (hereafter PT, Kahneman & Tversky, Reference Kahneman and Tversky1979; Tversky & Kahneman, Reference Tversky and Kahneman1992) when it is applied to the probability distributions of outcomes that participants actually sampled.

Table 1 Percentage of choices consistent with prospect theory (PT) for each decision problem in Hertwig et al. (Reference Hertwig, Barron, Weber and Erev2004). H = option with the higher expected value; L = option with the lower expected value (the first number is the prize amount in points, the second number is the objective probability). Underlining indicates the choice predicted by PT, assuming objective probabilities and median value- and weighting-function parameters reported by Tversky & Kahneman (Reference Tversky and Kahneman1992). Entries in the last three columns indicates percentages of responses compatible with PT for decisions from description, and for decisions from experience assuming objective probabilities and probabilities experienced by participants, respectively.

To motivate our approach we note that economists since Knight (Reference Knight1921) have distinguished decisions under risk, in which objective probabilities of outcomes are known by the decision maker, from decisions under uncertainty, in which they are not. The experiment of HBWE thus compared decisions under risk (where lotteries were explicitly described) to decisions under uncertainty (where lotteries were unlabeled buttons). In decisions under uncertainty people’s beliefs may differ from so-called “objective” probabilities for a variety of reasons. First, experienced probabilities may differ from objective probabilities—as HBWE note, it follows from the binomial distribution that people are more likely to under-sample than over-sample low-probability events, and this sampling error will be more pronounced the lower the probability and the smaller the size of the sample taken.Footnote 1 Second, people judge the probabilities that they have experienced incorrectly. Thus, the question arises to what extent HBWE’s finding of “underweighting” can be attributed to: (1) sampling error (the difference between so-called “objective” probabilities and probabilities of outcomes that participants actually experienced); (2) judgment error (the difference between experienced probabilities and judged probabilities); and (3) probability weighting (the difference between judged probabilities and their impact on choices). Breaking down the source of “underweighting” is critical to the interpretation of HBWE’s results because sampling error is a statistical rather than psychological phenomenon, judgment error is a bias in belief rather than preference, and the weighting of these judged probabilities provides the most apt comparison to prospect theory.Footnote 2

If the predominant source of HBWE’s effect is sampling error, one would expect most choices to accord with prospect theory weights applied to the probabilities that participants actually observed. To test this notion we obtained HBWE’s raw data and tallied the participants in the experience condition (unlabeled buttons) whose choices were consistent with PT assuming “objective” probabilities (that were known only to the experimenter) versus “experienced” probabilities (proportions of events that participants observed).Footnote 3 For each gamble pair we calculated the percentage of participants who chose the higher PT-valued gamble assuming median value- and weighting-function parameters reported by Tversky and Kahneman (Reference Tversky and Kahneman1992). The results (see Table 1) are striking and consistent over all lottery pairs: although most participants “violate” PT when the analysis is applied to “objective” probabilities as presented in HBWE, most conform to the predictions of PT when applied to probabilities that participants experienced, at a similar rate to decisions from description.

In order to distinguish judgment error from probability weighting we replicated the method of HBWE, adding an elicitation of judged probabilities. We asked 46 students at Ben Gurion University to (1) sample outcomes from each pair of unlabeled lotteries, (2) choose their preferred lottery, and (3) recall the possible outcomes of each lottery and then estimate their respective probabilities, counterbalancing the order of judgment and choice tasks (a fuller account of this experiment will appear elsewhere; details can be obtained from the authors). The median correlation among respondents between judged and experienced probabilities was .97 and the median mean absolute error was .06, suggesting that participants were very accurate.Footnote 4 When Tversky & Kahneman’s (Reference Tversky and Kahneman1992) median value- and weighting-function parameters were applied to “objective” probabilities, most choices (60%) violated PT as in HBWE; however, when this analysis was applied to judged probabilities, most choices (63%) conformed to PT. Thus, participants apparently weighted judged probabilities in decisions from experience just as they tend to weight chance probabilities in decisions from description, consistent with Tversky & Fox’s (Reference Tversky and Fox1995) “two-stage model” of decision under uncertainty (see also Fox & Tversky, Reference Fox and Tversky1998; Wakker, Reference Wakker2004). We expect that this model would have fit even better had predictions been based on individually measured PT parameters, which are known to vary somewhat between participants, rather than group medians (see Gonzalez & Wu, Reference Wu and Gonzalez1999).

We note that HBWE do find some interesting patterns in their data. Notably, participants with small incentives are content to make decisions based on small samples of information, and more recently sampled information may have greater impact on their decisions. However, our internal analysis of HBWE’s data and our replication show that the so-called “underweighting” of low probability events in decisions from experience is driven almost entirely by a tendency to undersample low-probability events—a statistical property of the binomial distribution—and has almost nothing to do with underestimation of observed probabilities or a tendency to underweight these probabilities. Likelihood judgments correspond very closely with experienced probabilities and choices are consistent with overweighting low probabilities, as characterized by prospect theory. Thus, the call for “two different theories of risky choice” seems premature, and future research on decisions from experience might instead explore models of search rules (what information do people seek), models that terminate search (how much information do they seek), and models of bias in likelihood judgment.

Footnotes

*

This work was supported in part by the Fulbright Program and the UCLA-BGU Program at the UCLA International Institute.

1 To illustrate, consider an “experience-based” choice between (a) a 2.5% chance of 32 points or (b) a 25% chance of 3 points (Decision 6 in HBWE). If 100 participants sample outcomes from each lottery eight times (approximately the median number reported in HBWE) one would expect 82 participants to sample exclusively zero outcomes for lottery (a) but only 10 participants to sample exclusively zero outcomes for lottery (b). Thus, one would expect 73 participants to face an apparent choice between (a) receive nothing or (b) possibly receive 3 points. HBWE characterize the choice of option (b) in this case as “underweighting” of the low-probability event because—unbeknownst to participants — the first lottery has a higher expected value than the second lottery.

2 The two-stage model of decision under uncertainty holds that prospect theory’s inverse-S shaped weighting function can be applied to judged probabilities (Fox & Tversky, Reference Fox and Tversky1998). Strictly speaking, PT calls for an alternative measure such as “bounded subadditivity” for decisions under uncertainty (Tversky & Fox, Reference Tversky and Fox1995; see also Wu & Gonzalez, Reference Wu and Gonzalez1999). However, the data of HBWE do not lend themselves to such alternative measures.

3 We thank Greg Barron for providing us with these data.

4 Of course the high correlation between judged and experienced probabilities may be somewhat inflated by the wide range of “objective” probabilities used in this experiment. However, if we examine the low probability lotteries (p = .025 ‒ . 25) and high probability lotteries (p= .8 - 1) separately, the correlations remain quite high: .84 and .98, respectively.

References

Fox, C. R. & Tversky, A. (1998). A belief-based account of decision under uncertainty. Management Science, 44, 879-895.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gonzalez, R. & Wu, G. (1999). On the shape of the probability weighting function. Cognitive Psychology, 38, 129-166.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hertwig, R. Barron, G. Weber, E. U. & Erev, I. (2004). Decisions from experience and the effect of rare events in risky choice. Psychological Science, 15, 534-539.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hertwig, R. Barron, G. Weber, E. U. & Erev, I. (2005). The role of information sampling in risky choice. Chapter in Fiedler, K. & Juslin, P. (Eds.) Information Sampling as a Key to Understanding Adaptive Cognition. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kahneman, D. & Tversky, A. (1979). Prospect Theory: An Analysis of Decision Under Risk. Econometrica, 47, 263-291.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Knight, F. (1921). Risk, Uncertainty, and Profit. Boston, MA: Houghton-Mifflin.Google Scholar
Tversky, A. & Fox, C. R. (1995). Weighting Risk and Uncertainty. Psychological Review, 102, 269-283.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tversky, A. & Kahneman, D. (1992). Advances in Prospect Theory: Cumulative Representations of Uncertainty, Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 5, 297-323.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wakker, P. P. (2004). On the Composition of Risk Preference and Belief. Psychological Review, 111, 236-241.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weber, E. U. Shafir, S. & Blais, A. R. (2004). Predicting risk sensitivity in humans and lower animals: Risk as variance or coefficient of variation. Psychological Review, 111, 430-445.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Wu, G. & Gonzalez, R. (1999). Nonlinear decision weights in choice under uncertainty. Management Science, 45, 74-85.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Figure 0

Table 1 Percentage of choices consistent with prospect theory (PT) for each decision problem in Hertwig et al. (2004). H = option with the higher expected value; L = option with the lower expected value (the first number is the prize amount in points, the second number is the objective probability). Underlining indicates the choice predicted by PT, assuming objective probabilities and median value- and weighting-function parameters reported by Tversky & Kahneman (1992). Entries in the last three columns indicates percentages of responses compatible with PT for decisions from description, and for decisions from experience assuming objective probabilities and probabilities experienced by participants, respectively.