Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-hc48f Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-29T17:13:01.179Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

What is an Empiricist? Wesley Clair Mitchell in Broader Perspective

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  11 June 2009

Abraham Hirsch
Affiliation:
Brooklyn College

Extract

The historian of economics encounters special difficulties in dealing with a heterodox economist. When one considers someone who is orthodox, basic notions can be taken for granted, and this enables the historian to zero in on meaningful issues without first having to provide an extensive introduction dealing with fundamental notions which have to be understood if the significance of what is being said is to be grasped. On the other hand, if one omits this step when dealing with the heterodox the analysis is not likely to be very meaningful. This special difficulty is much compounded where the heterodoxy is methodological, as it is with Wesley Clair Mitchell. What Mitchell tried to do was to reconstruct economics, to convince economists to adopt a different approach to the very way they conduct their inquiries. John Stuart Mill had laid down the law that extensive observation of specific experience was of no help in the attempt to derive economic theory, and mainstream economists generally went along with him on this. Mitchell disagreed and attempted to show that by building on different foundations a more “scientific” and useful economics could be derived. The interesting question for the historian of economics is: What can we learn from Mitchell's experience? It is here that we run into the problem that I noted at the outset.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 1988

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

Agassi, J. 1984. Foreward. In Berkson, and Wettersten, , Learning From Error, 1984.Google Scholar
Allen, Williams R. 1970. Modern Defenders of Mercantalism. History of Political Economy, fall.Google Scholar
Berkson, William and John, Wettersten. 1984. Learning From Error: Karl Popper's Psychology of Learning. La Salle, Ill.: Open Court Publishing Co.Google Scholar
Blaug, Mark. 1980. The Methodology of Economics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Boland, Lawrence A. 1984. Methodology: Reply. American Economic Review, SeptemberGoogle Scholar
Burke, T.E. 1983. The Philosophy of Karl Popper. Manchester: Manchester University Press.Google Scholar
Burns, Arthur F., ed. 1952. Wesley Clair Mitchell: The Economic Scientist. New York: National Bureau of Economic Research.Google Scholar
Cahn, Steven N., ed. 1987. New Studies in the Philosophy of John Dewey. Hanover, N.H.: Press of New England.Google Scholar
Dewey, John. 1929. The Quest For Certainty. New York: Minton, Balch.Google Scholar
Dewey, John. 1938. Logic: The Theory of Inquiry. New York: Henry Holt and Co.Google Scholar
Fodor, Jerry. 1984. Observation Reconsidered. Philosophy of Science, March.Google Scholar
Friedman, Milton. 1950. Wesley Clair Mitchell as an Economic Theorist. Journal of Political Economy, December. Reprinted in Burnes, Arthur F., ed., 1952Google Scholar
Hutchison, T.W. 1960. The Significance and Basic Postulates of Economic Theory. New York: Augustus M. Kelley.Google Scholar
Machlup, Fritz. 1955. The Problem of Verification in Economics. The Southern Economic Journal, July.Google Scholar
Margolis, Joseph. 1977. The relevance of Dewey's epistemology. In Cahn, Steven N., ed. New Studies in the Philosophy of John Dewey, 1977.Google Scholar
Mill, John Stuart. 1967. Collected Works, Essays On Economy Society. Robson, J.M., ed. Toronto: University of Toronto Press, vol. 4.Google Scholar
Mill, John Stuart. 1973. Collected Works, A System of Logic Ratiocinative and Inductive. Robson, J.M., ed. London: Rutledge and Kegan Paul, vols. 7 and 8.Google Scholar
Mitchell, Wesley Clair. 1950. The Backward Art of Spending Money and Other Essays. New York: Augustus M. Kelley.Google Scholar
Newton-Smith, W.H. 1981. The Rationality of Science. Boston: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
O'Hear, Anthony. 1980 Karl Popper. London: Routledge and Kegan PaulGoogle Scholar
Popper, Karl. 1959. The Logic of Scientific Discovery. London: Hutchinson.Google Scholar
Popper, Karl. 1982. Unended Quest: An Intellectual Biography. La Salle: Open Court.Google Scholar
Vickers, Douglas. 1959. Studies in the Theory of Money 1690–1776. Philadelphia: Childton Co.Google Scholar
White, Morton G. 1977. The Origin of Dewey's Instrumentalism. New York: Octagon Books of Farrar, Straus and Giraux.Google Scholar