Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-tf8b9 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-23T18:48:52.591Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Ubuntu in Elephant Communities

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  12 December 2023

BIRTE WRAGE
Affiliation:
MESSERLI RESEARCH INSTITUTE (UNIVERSITY OF VETERINARY MEDICINE VIENNA, UNIVERSITY OF VIENNA, MEDICAL UNIVERSITY OF VIENNA) [email protected]
DENNIS PAPADOPOULOS
Affiliation:
MESSERLI RESEARCH INSTITUTE (UNIVERSITY OF VETERINARY MEDICINE VIENNA, UNIVERSITY OF VIENNA, MEDICAL UNIVERSITY OF VIENNA) [email protected]
JUDITH BENZ-SCHWARZBURG
Affiliation:
MESSERLI RESEARCH INSTITUTE (UNIVERSITY OF VETERINARY MEDICINE VIENNA, UNIVERSITY OF VIENNA, MEDICAL UNIVERSITY OF VIENNA) [email protected]
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

African (Bantu) philosophy conceptualizes morality through ubuntu, which emphasizes the role of community in producing moral agents. This community is characterized by practices that respond to and value interdependence, such as care, cooperation, and respect for elders and ancestral knowledge. While there have been attributions of morality to nonhuman animals in the interdisciplinary animal morality debate, this debate has focused on Western concepts. We argue that the ubuntu conception of morality as a communal practice applies to some nonhuman animals. African elephant communities are highly cooperative and structured around elders; they alloparent, protect their communities, mourn their dead, and pass on cultural knowledge between generations. Identifying these as important moral practices, ubuntu provides a theoretical framework to expand our ethical concern for elephants to their communities. In practice, this will deepen our understanding of the wrongness of atrocities like culling for population management or trophy hunting.

Type
Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of the American Philosophical Association

Introduction

In the 1990s, several African national parks saw a streak of gruesome massacres. For instance, between 1992 and 1997 Pilanesberg National Park, lost more than 40 white rhinos (Slotow et al. Reference Slotow, van Dyk, Poole, Page and Klocke2000), their bodies battered and with deep stab wounds. The unlikely perpetrators turned out to be adolescent male African elephants (henceforth: elephants) who had gone on a killing spree. While this behavior had been unheard of in elephants before, this was also a special generation of elephants in another regard: they were the first to reach adolescence after having been purposefully spared during the large-scale culling of elephants in previous decades (Slotow et al. Reference Slotow, van Dyk, Poole, Page and Klocke2000). As infants they witnessed the violent deaths of their mothers, aunts, and older siblings and were often also removed from their wider communities through relocation (Bradshaw and Schore Reference Bradshaw and Schore2007). In effect, they were not only traumatized, but also went on to miss the secondary socialization they would have normally received as youths from older males in so-called bachelor herds (Poole and Moss Reference Poole, Moss, Wemmer and Christen2008; Slotow et al. Reference Slotow, van Dyk, Poole, Page and Klocke2000). Left to their own devices, traumatized children turned into ‘delinquent’ teenagers (Slotow and Van Dyk Reference Slotow and van Dyk2001). In hopes of mitigating these unforeseen consequences of culling for population management, older elephant bulls were introduced into these populations, which immediately stopped the rhino killings and regulated aggression among the young elephants (Slotow et al. Reference Slotow, van Dyk, Poole, Page and Klocke2000).

According to the International Fund for Animal Welfare (IFAW), after widely shared objections put a stop to culling in the 90s (IFAW 2005), several African countries are revisiting debates about taking up culling for population management again (IFAW 2005; Muchinjo Reference Muchinjo2021), and some are considering lifting the ban on the international ivory trade (Stiles Reference Stiles2004; IFAW 2022). The commercial killing of elephants has also been used as a means to generate funds for conservation, rendering elephants into commodities serving a market-based, neoliberal global policy framework applied to biodiversity conservation (Batavia et al. Reference Batavia, Nelson, Darimont, Paquet, Ripple and Wallach2019; Hewitson and Sullivan Reference Hewitson and Sullivan2021). Welfare-oriented animal ethics has little to say against this. Suffering during killing is usually considered avoidable by implementing ‘humane’ methods, involving ‘appropriate calibre weapons’ targeting ‘clean kill’ spots in the frontal or temporal brain (Slotow et al. Reference Slotow, Blackmore, Henley, Trendler and Garaï2021). And the troubling case of traumatized survivors can be easily avoided—by leaving no survivors. Indeed, this has been recommended as a welfare-friendly strategy in conservation guidelines (Balfour et al. Reference Balfour, Dublin, Fennessy, Gibson, Niskanen and Whyte2007: 60ff.).

In this paper, we make a case that suggests that elephant communities matter and ought to be entitled to collective protections beyond species conservation, including ‘welfare-conscious’ conservation. We argue that elephants form moral communities on an ubuntu account. These communities are characterized by practices that affirm interdependence, such as care, cooperation, and respect for elders and ancestral knowledge (e.g., Gyekye Reference Gyekye, Gyekye and Wiredu2010a, Reference Gyekye, Gyekye and Wiredu2010b; Samkange and Samkange Reference Samkange and Samkange1980). Both ethical concern for individual welfare and valuing elephants primarily as a species fall short of capturing the full value such communities have. The recognition of ubuntu in elephants, in contrast, paves the way for deeper ethical concern for their communities as well as for individual elephants as irreplaceable community members, who arguably value and are valued by their communities.

Our application of ubuntu to elephant communities builds on other criticisms of the view that only human beings can be moral agents because morality allegedly requires moral reflection (e.g., Bekoff and Pierce Reference Bekoff and Pierce2009; Fitzpatrick Reference Fitzpatrick2017; Monsó and Andrews Reference Monsó, Andrews, Doris and Vargas2022; Rowlands Reference Rowlands2012). The attribution of morality to nonhuman animals focuses on nonreflective capacities such as empathic care (Monsó Reference Monsó2015; Wrage Reference Wrage2022), normative thinking (Andrews Reference Andrews2020; Fitzpatrick Reference Fitzpatrick2020), or cooperation (Duguid and Melis Reference Duguid and Melis2020; Papadopoulos Reference Papadopoulos2021). This debate, however, has not considered moral agency as a product of being part of a community, an idea central to ubuntu. If being in interdependent relationships, not the (reflective) rationality of autonomous individuals, leads to morality (Etieyibo Reference Etieyibo2017b; Metz Reference Metz2012), this changes what we should look for in nonhuman animals when we search for morality.

Our investigation is structured as follows: In section 1 we outline the sense in which ubuntu describes human moral communities. Then, in section 2, we show that, contrary to Kai Horsthemke's (Reference Horsthemke2015) claim that ubuntu is inherently anthropocentric, ubuntu can in principle describe nonhuman moral communities as well. In section 3 we operationalize the account of ubuntu by identifying seven morally important practices that make a moral community and show that elephants participate in each of them. Therefore, the ubuntu conception of a moral community paints a characteristic picture of elephant communities. Finally, in section 4, we outline two major ethical upshots of applying ubuntu to elephants. First, it offers a decolonial way of imagining interspecies relations. Second, it offers a strong case against culling and other interventions that disrupt the integrity and vitality of the community.

1. What is Ubuntu?

Ubuntu is an African moral philosophy that emphasizes the role of the community in producing moral beings. The word ‘ubuntu’ comes from the Nguni Bantu languages and related, albeit not identical, concepts are found in linguistic communities from the Niger-Congo language family, e.g. hunhu in Shona communities, often used interchangeably with ubuntu (Samkange and Samkange Reference Samkange and Samkange1980), or vumuntu in the Venda language, which picks out the specific in-context relationship a linguistic community has in their own place. Many African languages may have similar words, and the local specificity may be important in the establishment of local environmental or animal ethics (Gwaravanda Reference Gwaravanda and Chemuru2019). Here we focus on ubuntu broadly construed as an established and politically important short-hand for many conceptions of moral community that prioritize duties individuals have to their communities. By striving to fulfill these duties, these individuals realize their moral agency.

1.1 Moral Community in Ubuntu

The term ‘ubuntu’ etymologically breaks down into word fragments ‘ubu’, which signifies community, and ‘ntu’, which signifies a sense of vitality (Ngangah Reference Ngangah2019: 50). If we were to translate ubuntu we might call it ‘community vitality’. Such a translation takes ubuntu to be a vital force that flows through interpersonal relationships creating and sustaining the community and its members. This creative activity is expressed in John Mbiti's (Reference Mbiti1990) famous claim: ‘I am, because we are; and since we are, therefore I am’, which means:

Only in terms of other people does the individual become conscious of [their] own being, [their] own duties, [their] privileges and responsibilities towards other people. When [one] suffers, [one] does not alone but with the corporate group; when [one] rejoices, [one] rejoices not alone but with [one's kin], [one's] neighbours and [one's] relatives whether dead or living. (Mbiti Reference Mbiti1990: 106).

This account of being through community is simultaneously descriptive and normative. It is descriptive insofar as we understand ourselves, our suffering, and our joy through relationships. It is normative because those relationships come with duties, privileges, and responsibilities, such that each of us is a moral being responsible to others in our community. The vitality of ubuntu is both necessary for a community to exist and something for which we strive, such that each of us must do what is needed for a thriving community.

In the descriptive sense, the vitality of communities creates and sustains their community members. Individuals are the biological creation of the communion of their parents, who are created by their parents and so on, leading to the ancestors. Noah Komla Dzobo (Reference Dzobo, Gyekye and Wiredu2010a) explains that even this literal procreation is part of what is meant by the fundamental creative force in African ontology—inclusive of many Niger-Congo language communities like the Akan, Ewe, and Yoruba. He relies on literal instances of creation and dependence (sowing seeds, giving birth, etc.) as ways of capturing how each human being depends on their community for their very existence. Each of us relies on the abundance of our communities to be sustained and supported. This includes relying on ecological resources, the activity of other community members, and the knowledge kept by one's community and passed down from one generation to the next.

The relationships in which we find ourselves carry with them a moral force. Our identification with others through relationships is coextensive with the opportunities to care for others and contribute to their lives (Metz Reference Metz2013). We contribute to our communities in part because our relationships call on us to be someone and do something. Dzobo (Reference Dzobo, Gyekye and Wiredu2010a: 132) emphasizes that community leaders and elders are exemplars of the sort of person we should strive to become, because they ‘achieved a creative personality and productive life and [are] able to maintain a productive relationship with others’. This productivity need not mean they have created wealth, but that they have been part of a community and maintained relationships, uniting in them the poles of ‘self’ and ‘society’. Dzobo (Reference Dzobo, Gyekye and Wiredu2010b: 75) explains that elders typically have nyansa, a wisdom from experience that includes creative and supportive relationships as well as practicing good etiquette. With nyansa, elders maintain and cultivate the relationships that allow them to understand themselves as elders or leaders of a particular community.

The normative element of ubuntu emerges from the recognition that we are ‘someone’ relative to a community of others. If one recognizes they are a leader or elder, they are compelled to lead or guide; likewise, if we recognize we are a child or student, we are compelled to listen and learn. These identities are not static labels but associated with relationships and activities where understanding the relationship moves us toward the experience of being-in-a-community. When we fulfill duties that arise from community, ‘the opportunity for friendship and goodwill opens, whereas emphasis on individual entitlements may not necessarily be compatible with harmony and goodwill’ (Oyowe Reference Oyowe2013: 121). Further, these duties do not necessarily follow from our analytic knowledge about deontic imperatives or the pursuit of good consequences. Instead, ubuntu-centered moral education emphasizes that our knowledge of our duties unfolds before us in the context of community life (Etieyibo Reference Etieyibo2017b).

1.2 Muntu: Moral Agents in Ubuntu

In ubuntu philosophy, membership in the moral community entails protection and support for all members. However, there is an emphasis on the duties of community members to contribute to the community's vitality. This is captured in the concept ‘muntu’ that refers to the moral individual, whose morality comes from their social embeddedness. ‘Muntu’ carries the ‘ntu’ word fragment signifying vitality, suggesting that ‘muntu’ indicates a person who is vital to their community (Ngangah Reference Ngangah2019). This is often described in the language of a flow of vitality from community to individuals and back from individuals to community (Etieyibo Reference Etieyibo, Afolayan and Falola2017c). Following the descriptive sense of ubuntu, all community members are muntu, but some live up to this status better than others. This distinction leads some (e.g., Menkiti Reference Menkiti and Wright1984; Metz Reference Metz2012) to say that muntu comes in degrees. However, this does not mean that the duties owed to community members vary depending on their degree of virtuousness; all members of a moral community ought to be supported (Gyekye Reference Gyekye, Gyekye and Wiredu2010a). We can still recognize that some especially virtuous community members contribute more to the vitality of the community than others. There are many ways to contribute including being a good leader, wise elder, skilled provider, good parent, or protector of the community.

2. Anthropocentrism in Ubuntu

Before we can apply ubuntu to nonhuman animals, we must address the potential objection that ubuntu is inherently anthropocentric and thus cannot be extended to nonhuman animals. Those familiar with the term may have heard it translated or explained as meaning ‘humanness’, or ‘humanity’. This alone need not discourage us. While moral agency and responsibility are widely thought to be uniquely human qualities that set us apart from other animals (Delon, Reference Delonforthcoming; Korsgaard Reference Korsgaard, Macedo and Ober2006; Nussbaum Reference Nussbaum2006), this assumption is what sparked the animal morality debate in the first place (e.g., Rowlands Reference Rowlands2012). It is therefore not surprising to find ubuntu equated with humanity. But the implication that ubuntu excludes nonhuman animals can be challenged by looking at the capacities, practices, or relationships associated with ubuntu and at whether or not we find them in nonhuman animals.

Still, there has been explicit skepticism about the possibility of extending ubuntu to nonhuman animals on account of its anthropocentrism. Horsthemke (Reference Horsthemke2015, Reference Horsthemke2017) argues that anthropocentrism inherent in ubuntu and related concepts precludes the possibility of a uniquely African conception of animal ethics based on ubuntu philosophy. He stresses that even where the traditions and stories of communities that live by ubuntu philosophy value other entities like nonhuman animals, ancestral spirits, or the ecosystems in which they live, they do so in an anthropocentric way (Horsthemke Reference Horsthemke2015: 68, 74). This anthropocentrism has two dimensions. First, the value of nonhuman animals, ancestors, and spirits, even when they are revered, is explained with reference to what they do, or have done, for the human community (Horsthemke Reference Horsthemke2017: 123). Second, there is a hierarchy where God is at the top, ancestors and spirits are above living humans, who are above other animals, who are above inanimate things (Horsthemke Reference Horsthemke2017: 124-25). These features of ubuntu emphasize joint action as a community accompanied by reverence for elders, ancestors, and traditional practices. Horsthemke understands this as explicitly and exclusively valuing human communities, human ancestors, and human traditions, leaving little space to value nonhuman animals.

Horsthemke's (Reference Horsthemke2015, Reference Horsthemke2017) criticism of ubuntu in animal ethics is, partly, a response to Thaddeus Metz's (Reference Metz2012, Reference Metz2017) modal relationalism, which focuses on extending ubuntu to some nonhuman animals as members of the human moral community. Metz (Reference Metz2012) explains that as ubuntu philosophy treats relationships, like friendship, as constitutive of a moral community, nonhuman animals with whom we have close relationships ought to be included in our moral communities. He suggests that ‘the more a being is capable of being part of a friendly or loving relationship with [human beings], the greater [their] moral status’ (Metz Reference Metz2012: 394). This would make our companion animals candidate members of our moral community on account of their capacity to form empathic or loving relationships with us. Therefore, we have a hierarchy where some animals are more worthy of membership in a moral community than others according to their capacity to have an interpersonal relationship with human beings (see also Samuel and Fayemi Reference Samuel and Fayemi2020).

We can see another way in which ubuntu might be anthropocentric in Motsamai Molefe's (Reference Molefe2017) challenge to modal relationalism. Molefe asks us to imagine a Martian who has all the required moral capacities but no actual relationship with any human community; would they, therefore, lack moral standing despite moral capacity? Metz specifies that his view is about ‘modal’, in this case possible, relationships and not necessarily ‘actual’ relationships. As long as Martians with the relevant capacities could have relationships like friendship with human beings they would be worthy of moral consideration. However, this evaluation is still anthropocentric. By evaluating moral worth through someone's possible relationships with human beings, we center humanity as the sole standard for a moral community worthy of consideration. Such anthropocentric concerns may not be limited to modal relationalism but could extend to all ubuntu philosophy because actual relationships are often the ground on which communities determine their obligations.

However, there is another reading of ubuntu that escapes anthropocentrism. Instead of understanding the contributions of nonhuman animals, ancestors, and ecosystems as their source of value, Edwin Etieyibo suggests these contributions indicate interdependence and extend the sphere of what counts as ‘community’ beyond the contemporary human community (Etieyibo Reference Etieyibo2017a: 156–57). Ancestors are the progenitors of current individuals and provided us with the knowledge, traditions, and culture we now have. Simultaneously, a vital community depends on other living beings in numerous ways that cannot be reduced, for instance, to asymmetric relationships of use. Reducing this ontology of vital, causal relationships with ancestors and ecosystems to attributions of instrumental value by human beings misunderstands the causal ecological foundations of the vitality central to ubuntu. Taking ubuntu to be closely connected to ecology has characterized a reclaiming of the concept. This sense of ubuntu highlights the traditional African ways of valuing the ecological world and calling for transgressive and critical ways to approach growing ecological crises (e.g., Muashekele et al. Reference Muashekele, Winschiers-Theophilus, Rodil, Stanley, Muashekele, Abdelnour-Nocera, Makori, Robles-Flores and Bitso2022; Mutekwa and Musanga Reference Mutekwa and Musanga2013).

In this spirit we might reexamine the hierarchy Horsthemke proposed. Ubuntu is a community vitality that depends on creative force from above and below, the past and the future, the spiritual and ecological. It is not a hierarchy of rank but a collection that shows the many things around a community that constitute it. Lesley Le Grange (Reference Le Grange2015) contextualizes ubuntu as the normative element of what the Shona language calls ukama, or the relatedness of all things explicitly including nonhuman animals and ecosystems. Ukama emphasizes that the vitality of communities depends on respect for the larger whole. This limits the extent to which human communities might exploit the environment (Masaka Reference Masaka and Chemhuru2019).

In addition to limiting exploitation by human beings, ubuntu grounded in ukama suggests a more radically nonanthropocentric proposition. In his criticism of anthropocentric interpretations of ubuntu, Filip Maj suggests reframing the question of the moral status of animals and asks: ‘would it not be possible to grant animals a moral status based on their own capacity to commune, rather than our ability to commune with [them]?’ (Maj Reference Maj and Imafidon2020: 344). If we take it that the moral status provided by ubuntu requires a community's translation of ecological vitality into creative and supportive relationships, then there is no special reason to expect that human communities alone do this. We do not need to explore the capacities to engage with human communities, or even in human-like ways. Nonhuman animals also depend upon a larger world, so their behavior in their relationships and their ecological situation can inform us about their status as participants in a moral community. This status may exist pluralistically alongside other less socially dynamic but nonetheless valuable forms of life. However, where we find communities of participants who care for and respect one another, we ought to give them special moral consideration as a community, not just as individuals or a population.

3. Identifying Ubuntu Communities Across Species

Ubuntu offers a non-minimal way of conceptualizing a moral community. This means that we may find animals engaged in the relevant moral practices to varying degrees, but may still credit their community as a whole with ubuntu in some sense. Our goal in applying ubuntu to nonhuman animals then is to offer a theory that, first, accurately describes characteristic practices of that animal community and, second, reveals a bridge for respecting those communities as fellow moral communities. To evaluate whether or not a community is a moral community according to ubuntu we look for two clusters of characteristic practices based on two central values in ubuntu: care and respect. Together both clusters of practices recognize, respond to, and affirm interdependence, implicitly or explicitly acknowledging the profound connection between individual flourishing and community vitality.

First, in the care cluster we collate practices through which individuals contribute to the vitality of the community through caring for its members. Receiving, learning to provide, and providing care are crucial steps in one's moral becoming (Metz Reference Metz2013). Thus, care means self-actualization as a moral being and enabling others in their moral becoming. Both sustain the community as a moral community. Practices in this cluster can also be understood as affirming dependence and echoing care-related values such as compassion, altruism, or generosity (Etieyibo Reference Etieyibo2017b; Gyekye Reference Gyekye, Gyekye and Wiredu2010a; Metz Reference Metz2013; Ngangah Reference Ngangah2019).

Second, in the respect cluster we collate practices that imply or express appreciation of contributions to the community's vitality. An ubuntu community does not just ask one to contribute but also to recognize others’ contributions. This is because as communal beings we never ‘outgrow’ being dependent; rather, we grow into the reciprocity of interdependence. Practices in the respect cluster can also be understood as embracing one's own dependence on the community and its key members, such as elders and ancestors.

There are a handful of candidate nonhuman animals who seem to form ubuntu-like moral communities characterized by communal care and respect, such as elephants, bonobos, cetaceans, and possibly others (Tokuyama and Furuichi Reference Tokuyama and Furuichi2017; Nolte, Sterck, and Van Leeuwen Reference Nolte, Sterck and Leeuwen2023; Fox, Muthukrishna, and Shultz Reference Fox, Muthukrishna and Shultz2017). However, a full exploration of the range of species that might live in ubuntu-like communities falls outside our scope. Instead, we focus on African elephants as a paradigm case to develop a model of the features and implications of ubuntu in nonhuman animal communities. For the care cluster we find that elephants (1) care cooperatively, especially for infants, (2) provide help, (3) care for a wider community, and (4) defend the community. For the respect cluster we find that elephants (5) practice noncoercive leadership enabled by respect for elders, (6) celebrate births, and (7) mourn the death of community members, especially widely known matriarchs.

3.1 Alloparenting

Alloparenting, that is, caring for infants regardless of kinship, is one form of extending care to the community. Ubuntu emphasizes this sense of community coming together, not just to care for your immediate loved ones, but all members of the community. Etieyibo (Reference Etieyibo2017b) explains that on an ubuntu conception of moral education children develop a sense of morality through interaction with the community. It is neither abstract nor private. It need not be explicitly taught but is learned through living in a community, and so it is the community's duty to be an example and guide for all its children.

Female elephants—often sisters, sometimes friends—and their young live in tight-knit family units within large social networks of extended family, friends, and acquaintances, whom they flexibly join or temporarily separate from, depending on available resources or common interests (Poole and Moss Reference Poole, Moss, Wemmer and Christen2008). Alloparenting plays a central role in these matriarchal family units, providing a chance for all to learn caregiving skills while also increasing care for everyone. Indeed, it is not just children who are cared for but also less experienced caregivers; especially first-time mothers and their offspring receive extra support from more experienced group members (Poole and Moss Reference Poole, Moss, Wemmer and Christen2008).

Elephant infants depend on extensive care from their mother, aunts, and older siblings for years, and either remain with this natal family (in the case of females) or keep in close contact even as adults (in the case of males; Bates et al. Reference Bates, Lee, Njiraini, Poole, Sayialel, Sayialel, Moss and Byrne2008: 206). Adult male elephants, in turn, take on the secondary socialization of the adolescent males in separate bull herds. However, compared to their female counterparts, male elephants generally live more individualistic lives competing with each other (Poole and Moss Reference Poole, Moss, Wemmer and Christen2008).Thus, while male elephants play an important role in elephant communities, cooperation and care of infants is characteristic of the more tight-knit maternal family groups.

3.2 Helping Behavior

Helping others as a specific form of care can be viewed as an expression of generosity, leading to communal flourishing and moral development (Etieyibo Reference Etieyibo2017b). Elephants not only help each other in their care for offspring, but they also try to help disabled, injured, immobilized, and dying community members (Poole Reference Poole1998; Douglas-Hamilton et al. Reference Douglas-Hamilton, Bhalla, Wittemyer and Vollrath2006; Bates et al. Reference Bates, Lee, Njiraini, Poole, Sayialel, Sayialel, Moss and Byrne2008). For instance, they remove foreign objects, such as spears or tranquilizer darts, from conspecifics (Bates et al. Reference Bates, Lee, Njiraini, Poole, Sayialel, Sayialel, Moss and Byrne2008: 217f.), or assist mobility, helping others who are stuck in the mud or a ditch (Bates et al. Reference Bates, Lee, Njiraini, Poole, Sayialel, Sayialel, Moss and Byrne2008: 221). Assisting mobility is described by Bates et al. (2008: 221) as ‘occur[ring] on a daily basis’. Other helping behaviors involve protective behaviors, such as chasing away predators or shielding vulnerable group members from conspecifics (Bates et al. Reference Bates, Lee, Njiraini, Poole, Sayialel, Sayialel, Moss and Byrne2008: 212f.).

In light of these findings, elephants are taken to be capable of cognitively sophisticated forms of empathy that involve a degree of perspective-taking (Bates et al. Reference Bates, Lee, Njiraini, Poole, Sayialel, Sayialel, Moss and Byrne2008; Poole and Moss Reference Poole, Moss, Wemmer and Christen2008; Poole Reference Poole1998). Aside from the deep emotional bonds that elephants form, this capacity will be highly conducive to the concern for all community members that ubuntu hails, and it may facilitate peaceful and cooperative relations with mere acquaintances and other communities.

3.3 Maintaining Relationships in a Wider Community

What we have noted about elephants so far may still be viewed as a rather narrow concern for (chosen) family, based on deep emotional bonds, rather than care for the community. However, elephants are not just concerned with the well-being of their core family unit but also with their wider social network as they associate in dynamic fission-fusion societies. Elephants stay in touch over long distances by low frequency calls and constantly keep track auditorily of the location of dispersed groups (Byrne, Bates, and Moss Reference Byrne, Bates and Moss2009; O'Connell-Rodwell Reference O'Connell-Rodwell2007). Their alarm calls in response to danger, such as from bees or human beings, have been hypothesized to not just be expressions of emotional arousal but warnings to conspecifics in the area (Soltis et al. Reference Soltis, King, Douglas-Hamilton, Vollrath and Savage2014). Some of these will be friends or distant family; some may rather be viewed as neighbors.

Such distinctions are facilitated by elephants’ extraordinary working memory and hearing, and their ability for vocal recognition and discrimination (Byrne, Bates, and Moss Reference Byrne, Bates and Moss2009). Adult female elephants were found to be able to recognize and discriminate between around 100 conspecifics by their calls alone (McComb et al. Reference McComb, Moss, Sayialel and Baker2000), which reflects the vastness of their social networks far beyond the core family. Crucially, these elephants know each other as individuals to whom they have distinct relationships, not merely as fellow elephants. For example, reunions with bonded groups will be celebrated in sometimes exuberant greeting ceremonies (Poole and Moss Reference Poole, Moss, Wemmer and Christen2008: 87–88).

3.4 Protecting the Community

Care for the community and its members will not only be expressed within the community, but also in a generally peaceful but, where necessary, protective conduct in intercommunity relations. Colin Chasi (Reference Chasi2021) explains that ubuntu is often described as pacifist, but that this fails to acknowledge the violence done in the name of ubuntu, especially counterviolence to protect communities and, in particular, the anticolonial revolutionary violence that was used to bring apartheid in South Africa to an end. Chasi describes cases where ubuntu is used to justify counterviolence, emphasizing a sense of community under attack. That is, willingness, at least by some, to protect the community is a necessary part of community flourishing.

Elephants cooperatively defend their communities and protect them preemptively against external threats (Archie, Moss, and Alberts Reference Archie, Moss, Alberts, Moss, Croze and Lee2011). For instance, elephants assume protective formations when they cross rivers (Zambezi Grande 2022) or open terrain where they may feel vulnerable (Elephantvoices 2022a; Poole and Granli Reference Poole and Granli2021). Calves will be shielded by older herd members, who form a defensive circle around them when there is a threat (Elephantvoices 2022b). Elephants also cooperate to retrieve infants that have been kidnapped by other elephants (Poole and Moss Reference Poole, Moss, Wemmer and Christen2008: 80; Bates et al. Reference Bates, Lee, Njiraini, Poole, Sayialel, Sayialel, Moss and Byrne2008: 215), and they fight off predators and retrieve group members that have been separated from the herd by predators or have got lost (Bates et al. Reference Bates, Lee, Njiraini, Poole, Sayialel, Sayialel, Moss and Byrne2008: 212f.).

Protective behavior may not be limited to spontaneous responses to potential or imminent danger. Elephants sometimes appear to retaliate in sophisticated ways against those who have harmed them. Bates et al. (2008: 211) describe elephant coalitions to retaliate against threats from other elephant groups. But also in conflict with other species, such as human beings, elephants are capable of fine-grained discrimination concerning who has harmed them in the past and therefore poses a threat (McComb et al. Reference McComb, Shannon, Sayialel and Moss2014). While elephants usually avoid human beings and human livestock, there have been reports of aggressive behavior in response to human activity (Kioko et al. Reference Kioko, Moore, Moshofsky, Nonnamaker, Ebanietti, Thompson, Kiffner, Kiffner, Bond and Lee2022). Moreover, elephant communities that face predation from the Maasai, an indigenous Central-African community whose territory includes parts of Kenya and Tanzania, have been observed to attack their cattle, which seems to be a group-specific response to predation not observed elsewhere (Elephantvoices 2022c). If these are indeed retaliatory behaviors, for which elephants seem to have the necessary cognitive capacities, it may be even more urgent that human beings understand elephants as invested in their own communities.

Taken together, elephant communities are characterized by care through a variety of practices that respond to the dependence of communal beings. Care is neither limited to parental care nor to the immediate relational level, but a practice the community as a whole is engaged in. Care is the practice through which infants are inducted into the moral community as they learn to care for others in turn. All members of the community receive care and grow into their individual role in the community through being engaged in care. The community stands together against external threats. While these practices respond to dependence with care, a moral community also engages in practices that imply respect for those we depend on.

3.5 Respecting the Role of Elders and Ancestral Knowledge

In ubuntu, our relationships call on us to respect those others upon whom we have depended. This includes our ancestors, our living parents and elders as well as those long passed (Gyekye Reference Dzobo, Gyekye and Wiredu2010b). To evaluate whether community members respect the contributions of others we might assess whether or not the elders or knowledgeable and able community members are looked to for leadership as one form of recognizing their contributions. Specifically, we would expect as a characteristic feature of the community an orientation toward ancestral knowledge through noncoercive leadership by experienced elders.

Elephant communities rely on the leadership, experience, care, and social integration of their elders in many ways. As noted above, elephants form large social networks over their lifetimes (McComb et al. Reference McComb, Moss, Sayialel and Baker2000). Shannon et al. (Reference Shannon, Slotow, Durant, Sayialel, Poole, Moss and McComb2013) found that the negative effects of social disruption in elephants persist for decades, and Shifra Goldenberg and George Wittemyer (Reference Goldenberg and Wittemyer2017, Reference Goldenberg and Wittemyer2018) likewise found that orphaning and dispersal from the natal group are associated with social costs in female elephants that impact their fitness in the long term. Because elephants are so reliant on their communities, integration in a social network is not an automatic by-product of aging but largely dependent on previous integration of an elephant's mother and female relatives.

Experienced matriarchs have been described as ‘repositories of social knowledge’ in the literature (McComb et al. Reference McComb, Moss, Durant, Baker and Sayialel2001). By virtue of their long-term memory and good cognitive mapping skills (Byrne, Bates, and Moss Reference Byrne, Bates and Moss2009) elephants are capable of accumulating vast knowledge over their extensive lifespans, for example, about the environment including other species, the location of remote and rarely frequented waterholes, seasonally accessible resources, migratory routes, the disabling of electric fences, the dangers associated with Land Cruisers, snares, helicopters, and so on (Poole Reference Poole1998: 97–98). Elephants are also capable of highly sophisticated discrimination between individuals and social groups even in other species and can therefore relate to those others in highly specific ways. For instance, elephants were found to be capable of differentiating between two different ethnic groups, gender, and age in human beings based on acoustic cues in their voices alone (McComb et al. Reference McComb, Shannon, Sayialel and Moss2014). In one of those groups, but not the other, men traditionally hunt elephants. Elephants were found to respond defensively to adult male voices in the former group (see also Poole Reference Poole1998: 98).

This cultural knowledge held by experienced group members may be transferred in different ways. Naïve group members may learn through observation, from role models, or from what has been described as a rudimentary form of teaching. Indeed, elephants have to learn many things before they become adult members of their communities—what to eat, how to play, and even how to care for others (Poole Reference Poole1998: 94–95). They socially learn about the locations of waterholes, including underground waterholes, and traditional migratory routes (Poole Reference Poole1998: 97), tool-use to switch flies (Hart and Hart Reference Hart and Hart1994), crop-raiding (Chiyo, Moss, and Alberts Reference Chiyo, Moss and Alberts2012), disabling of electric fences (Poole Reference Poole1998: 97), or in one unique group the mining of salt (Bowell, Warren, and Redmond Reference Bowell, Warren and Redmond1996). The case of the salt-mining elephants may be an especially striking example of preserving ‘ancestral knowledge’ in elephants, because this is a cultural practice that has shaped the environment for generations of elephants.

Knowledge that is acquired socially, and maybe even social norms, also inform the competitive behavior between males: Older elephants are more tolerant of inexperienced bulls who approach them during courtship and who observe and possibly learn from them (Poole and Moss Reference Poole, Moss, Wemmer and Christen2008: 82; Poole Reference Poole1998: 95). In turn, orphaned male elephants, who lacked the secondary socialization in a bull herd, were found to be dysfunctionally aggressive among each other and show abnormal sexual behavior toward rhinos; this aberrant behavior stopped when older bulls were reintroduced into the group (Bradshaw et al. Reference Bradshaw, Schore, Brown, Poole and Moss2005). Conversely, in what has been called an instance of ‘rudimentary teaching’, elephant mothers have been found to demonstrate proper courting behavior to their adolescent daughters approaching sexual maturity (Poole and Moss Reference Poole, Moss, Wemmer and Christen2008: 81).

Importantly, this guidance by elders is not hierarchical. Experienced matriarchs are respected leaders in elephant communities, and this is not a matter of achieving dominance through strength, but of being respected for their leadership qualities. Long-time elephant researchers Phyllis Lee and Cynthia Moss found that ‘wild female African elephants exhibit personality traits of leadership’, meaning that they are competent negotiators of individual interests, capable of ‘affect[ing] the behavior of others in the absence of aggressive dominance’ (Lee and Moss Reference Lee and Moss2012: 224). Their small study focused on 11 members of one especially successful family they had been observing for 38 years at the time. They found that ‘unlike some other captive large mammals, the personality of wild female savannah elephants appears to be better described by traits of social engagement than by assertiveness, with aggressiveness negatively associated with social skills’ (Lee and Moss Reference Lee and Moss2012: 228). Lee and Moss view leadership in elephants as sustained by respect, which elephants gain for their problem-solving ability and social permissiveness (Lee and Moss Reference Lee and Moss2012: 229).

The famous dictum, ‘In Africa, when an old man dies, a library burns’ (Hampâté Bâ Reference Hampâté Bâ1960), seems apt for elephants as well. When a matriarch is prematurely taken from her family, the community loses wisdom that has been gained over a lifetime and can only be passed on over time and in stable relationships. In turn, the matriarch learned about the environment, its local geography, and how to survive and lead from her ancestors, and so on for generations. This learning from elders is not enforced through dominance hierarchies, but involves the group members’ assent. Knowledge transfer from, leadership by, and respect for elders show that in elephant communities a sense of togetherness or communal spirit produces respect for individuals through the interdependent practices and knowledge of that community.

3.6 Celebrating Birth

Ubuntu values not just the greatest contributors, leaders, and elders, but all community members as being through others is not unilateral (Metz Reference Metz2013). Dzobo (Reference Dzobo, Gyekye and Wiredu2010a: 132) describes procreation as one of the ways people contribute to their communities in a profound way. Children are the embodied vitality of a community, and the community depends on them for its sustained existence, albeit in a different sense than it depends on its elders. The significance accorded to birth is thus at least partially grounded in the appreciation of and respect for the community as a whole.

We find that birth marks a special occasion in elephant communities. Joyce Poole (Reference Poole1998: 90–91, our emphases) writes:

One of the extraordinary aspects of elephants’ behavior is their emotionally demonstrative nature. It is hard to watch elephants’ remarkable behavior during a family or bond group greeting ceremony, the birth of a new family member, a playful interaction, . . . and not imagine that they feel strong emotions which could best be described by words such as joy, happiness, love, feelings of friendship, exuberance, amusement, pleasure, compassion, relief, and respect. . . . I believe that they are moved by complex emotional responses to situations that are important to the integrity of their society.

As Poole suggests, celebrating the birth of a new community member may indeed be connected to respect. Don Ross (Reference Ross2023) describes how among free-foraging elephants he worked with in South Africa a new mother would present their newborn to trusted human beings. If the chosen person failed to ‘fuss over’ the baby for what was deemed the appropriate amount of time, that person would be given the cold shoulder by the mother for several months. It may be that celebrating the calf is a sign not just of respect for the calf or their mother, but also of inclusion in that moral community where it is presumed that the calf is cause for celebration.

3.7 Mourning Death

The connectedness to the community that is celebrated in the context of birth is mirrored in the mourning of death. Angela Roothaan (Reference Roothaan and Chemuru2019) describes mourning practices in an interspecies African context as a form of felt perception. A community with ubuntu has individuals who feel a relatedness to others, which for humans is experienced partly in our shared affection for ancestors and departed loved ones (Gyekye Reference Dzobo, Gyekye and Wiredu2010b).

Elephants generally show a high interest in the remains of all conspecifics (McComb, Baker, and Moss Reference McComb, Baker and Moss2006; Douglas-Hamilton et al. Reference Douglas-Hamilton, Bhalla, Wittemyer and Vollrath2006; Goldenberg and Wittemyer Reference Goldenberg and Wittemyer2020), while they are uninterested in the remains of other nonhuman animals and show no preferential interest in the remains of relatives (McComb, Baker, and Moss Reference McComb, Baker and Moss2006). Observations of close attention to dying and dead elephants have been widely reported. Douglas-Hamilton et al. (Reference Douglas-Hamilton, Bhalla, Wittemyer and Vollrath2006) observed the reactions of elephants to a dying matriarch: elephants that were not nearby and had a friendly relationship with the dying matriarch travelled to check on her and attempted to help her get back on her feet. After her death, elephants continued to visit and congregated around her and investigated her corpse with careful touch. Poole (Reference Poole1998: 99) observed similar attempts at helping dead or dying conspecifics and an interest in the bones of conspecifics as well as elephants picking up and carrying elephant remains back to the site of their death. Furthermore, Poole (Reference Poole1998: 99) notes the solemn atmosphere when an elephant has died: ‘The behavior of elephants around their dead or around elephant bones is silent, gentle and contemplative’. Goldenberg and Wittemyer (Reference Goldenberg and Wittemyer2020: 119) conclude in their review on the matter: ‘The apparent emotionality and widely reported inter-individual differences involved in elephant responses to the dead deserve further study’.

Since these observations there has been more conceptual work on animals’ understanding of death (Monsó Reference Monsó2022; Monsó and Osuna-Mascaró Reference Monsó and Osuna-Mascaró2021). Arguably, true mourning would require some concept of death. On Susana Monsó and Antonio Osuna-Mascaró's (Reference Monsó and Osuna-Mascaró2021) account, elephants will indeed be strong candidates for being able to acquire a concept of death, because they are cognitively complex and, unfortunately, likely to have repeated opportunity to witness the death of conspecifics and to interact with dead conspecifics to learn about their state. Moreover, elephants form deep social bonds, which could motivate grief.

While elephants may not engage in complex mourning practices, their behavior around their dead, on the backdrop of their complex socioemotional capacities and relationships, indicates an understanding of the significance of death, adding to the similarities between human and elephant moral communities.

4. Moral Standing for Elephant Communities

Elephants demonstrate a substantial investment in the flourishing of the community in various domains characteristic of ubuntu. Together, the individual practices we discuss suggest that elephants practice ubuntu, form moral communities, and therefore, at least as a group, practice a kind of moral agency. This indicates that elephants are not just worthy of respect as individuals as argued in debates on nonhuman personhood (Comstock et al. Reference Comstock, Crozier, Fenton, John, Syd M, Johnson, Nobis, Peña-Guzmán, Rocha, Rollin and Sebo2020; Nisha Reference Nisha2017), they are also part of moral communities valuable as a whole.

We think that ubuntu identifies an important moral truth with its appreciation of the community, a truth that has largely been neglected in mainstream Western moral philosophy. Specifically, ubuntu is suited to make a unique contribution to animal ethics because it provides a theoretical framework to consider the value of nonhuman animal communities that does not reduce to valuing species. Moreover, its emphasis on the community does not come at the cost of valuing individuals; rather, ubuntu calls us to value individuals as beings in particular relationships. We outline these implications here.

4.1 Ubuntu Interspecies Relationships

Ubuntu extended to nonhuman moral communities strongly resonates with recent claims for zoopolitical agency in wild nonhuman animals (Donaldson and Kymlicka Reference Donaldson and Kymlicka2011; Meijer Reference Meijer2019). The finding that elephants (and likely other species) have ubuntu indicates a possible new imaginary for zoopolitical agency because it highlights the interdependence of agency and community. In this way ubuntu becomes an alternative or addition to animal politics based on ‘citizenship’, ‘sovereignty’ (Donaldson and Kymlicka Reference Donaldson and Kymlicka2011), ‘democracy’ (Meijer Reference Meijer2019), or ‘property’ (Bradshaw Reference Bradshaw2020).

Ubuntu as vital thriving of and within the community is sustained through communal care and leadership by elders. This communal flourishing with informed leaders, in turn, depends on sustainable and stable relationships with the ecosystem and neighboring communities, including other species. This interdependent relationship means human beings ought to support and respect the community building, wisdom of age, and peaceful traditions of elephant communities.

Ubuntu and ukama have been employed in international relations (Chirindo Reference Chirindo2016; Madise and Isike Reference Madise and Isike2020). We conjecture that like other elements of international relations (Derham and Mathews Reference Derham and Mathews2019; Fougner Reference Fougner2021), ubuntu might also have the power to describe normative interspecies relations, between human and nonhuman moral communities. Ubuntu and ukama are already starting to be referred to in decolonial environmental conservation (Okpoko Reference Okpoko2022; Mawere Reference Mawere2014). In addition to critiquing the power structures and targeting actual political decision-makers (Lanjouw Reference Lanjouw2021), ubuntu thus applied could help challenge the prevailing worldviews (Mabele et al. Reference Mabele, Sandroni, Collins and Rubis2021) and ‘diversify the Euro-centric knowledge landscape’ (Mokuku Reference Mokuku2017: 1) in conservation efforts.

4.2 Protecting the Integrity of the Community

Applied to elephant communities, integrating ubuntu into conservation might mean emphasizing conservation strategies that take into account the leadership, autonomous decision-making, and practices that elephants respect in their own communities (Mumby and Plotnik Reference Mumby and Plotnik2018; Ndlovu et al. Reference Ndlovu, Devereux, Chieffe, Asklof and Russo2016; Plotnik and Jacobson Reference Plotnik and Jacobson2022). As our initial anecdote of the adolescent orphans on a killing spree indicates, peaceful coexistence of elephant communities and other species hinges on the integrity of elephant communities. While the mitigation strategy to relocate older bulls as leaders superficially appears to have had the intended effect and even in some sense acknowledges the importance of elders, it remains reductive in light of the rich picture of elephant communal life we have painted.

For instance, ‘rehabilitating’ the orphans required severing the older bulls’ previous social ties and likely impoverished their communities. Such a treatment of individuals as mere exchangeable specimens is a standard occurrence in our dealings with wild animals, especially in the context of traditional conservation with both wild and captive animals. Ethicists have argued that conservation assumes the right to sacrifice the lives and well-being of individuals for the sake of preserving their or other species (Benz-Schwarzburg Reference Benz-Schwarzburg2020: 337–38; Castelló and Santiago-Ávila Reference Castelló and Santiago-Ávila2022) or maintaining ‘highly valuable’ captive breeding populations (ORF [Österreichischer Rundfunk] 2023). With ubuntu, we gain a more profound grasp of the irreplaceable value of individual community members.

Moreover, while the orphans’ maladaptive social behavior stopped once older bulls were reintroduced into the population (Slotow et al. Reference Slotow, van Dyk, Poole, Page and Klocke2000), Gay Bradshaw and Allen Schore (Reference Bradshaw and Schore2007: 429–30) have identified an increase of psychopathologies usually associated with captivity in wild populations that have suffered the disruption of social contexts due to poaching or culling. They explain: ‘In all cases described, individuals exhibiting abnormal behaviors were either translocated cull orphans, progeny of cull survivors, or reared under highly irregular herd structures’ (Bradshaw and Schore Reference Bradshaw and Schore2007: 431). The lasting negative impact of human beings and anthropogenic environmental changes on elephant communities and their interactions with the environment can hardly be overstated: ‘Starvation, culls, poaching, habitat reduction and isolation, and translocation have significantly changed traditional socialization patterns and skewed elephant demographics’ (Bradshaw and Schore Reference Bradshaw and Schore2007: 429). Many wild elephants now live without the guidance of experienced elders; many are single mothers (Bradshaw and Schore Reference Bradshaw and Schore2007: 429f.).

Ubuntu is then not just evident in thriving elephant communities. The disruption of elephant communities echoes the communal nature of elephants as well. Their integration in a wider world and their contributions to its vitality depend on their own community integrity and vice versa. Interspecies ubuntu further undermines the view that individual elephants are interchangeable. Each community member contributes in some form, is respected, and participates in affective and informative relationships that sustain the vitality of the community. Where this is made impossible through human intervention, such as in captivity, elephants live a diminished life as the kinds of beings they are. If we want to see thriving interspecies communities including elephants, then individuals and their relationships must not be sacrificed.

5. Conclusion

We have made the case that elephants form communities that have the core characteristics of a moral community according to ubuntu. Elephant communities are characterized by mutual care and cooperation, with respected elders at their heart whose loss is mourned and often has a lasting impact on the community. Elephants behave in ways that show they individually value and contribute to their communities, and the intergenerational community contributes to the psychological health and well-being of individual elephants. An irregular community without elders is usually dysfunctional, tending to lead to needless violence and suffering. Elephants and their communities coconstitute each other in complex morally relevant ways.

The value of elephant communities as moral communities goes largely unacknowledged in human-elephant relations moderated by the predominant Western ethical frameworks. In addition to the familiar calls for the rights of individual animals, ubuntu calls on us to recognize families and communities whose autonomy, leadership, and vitality ought to be protected in their own right. Ubuntu already fosters intercommunity respect among human beings but may apply more broadly than generally imagined: elephants also ought to be considered under the umbrella of intrinsically valuable communities and be encountered accordingly.

Footnotes

The authors thank Kristin Andrews for inspiring this paper and for helpful comments. A previous draft of this paper was presented at the Departmental Colloquium of the Department of Philosophy, Queen's University, Canada, and to the Animals in Philosophy, Politics, Law, and Ethics group at Queen's University, Canada. We thank the attendants for their helpful comments. This research was funded by the Austrian Science Fund (FWF) under grant number P31466-G32, and by the University of Veterinary Medicine Vienna.

References

Andrews, Kristin. (2020) ‘Naïve Normativity: The Social Foundation of Moral Cognition’. Journal of the American Philosophical Association, 6, 3656.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Archie, Elizabeth, Moss, Cynthia, and Alberts, Susan. (2011) ‘Friends and Relations: Kinship and the Nature of Female Elephant Social Relationships’. In Moss, Cynthia, Croze, Harvey, and Lee, Phyllis (eds.), The Amboseli Elephants: A Long-Term Perspective on a Long-lived Mammal (Chicago: University of Chicago Press), 238–45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Balfour, D., Dublin, H., Fennessy, J., Gibson, D., Niskanen, L., and Whyte, I.. (2007) Review of Options for Managing the Impacts of Locally Overabundant African Elephants. Gland, Switzerland: The World Conservation Union (IUCN).Google Scholar
Batavia, Chelsea, Nelson, Michael Paul, Darimont, Chris, Paquet, Paul, Ripple, William, and Wallach, Arian. (2019) ‘The Elephant (Head) in the Room: A Critical Look at Trophy Hunting’. Conservation Letters, 12, e12565.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bates, Lucy, Lee, Phyllis, Njiraini, Norah, Poole, Joyce, Sayialel, Katito, Sayialel, Soila, Moss, Cynthia, and Byrne, Richard. (2008) ‘Do Elephants Show Empathy?Journal of Consciousness Studies, 15, 204–5.Google Scholar
Bekoff, Marc, and Pierce, Jessica. (2009) Wild Justice. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Benz-Schwarzburg, Judith. (2020) Cognitive Kin, Moral Strangers? Linking Animal Cognition, Animal Ethics & Animal Welfare. Brill.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bowell, Rob, Warren, Andrew, and Redmond, Ian. (1996) ‘Formation of Cave Salts and Utilization by Elephants in the Mount Elgon Region, Kenya’. Geological Society, London, Special Publications, 113, 6379.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bradshaw, Gay, and Schore, Allan. (2007) ‘How Elephants Are Opening Doors: Developmental Neuroethology, Attachment and Social Context’. Ethology, 113, 426–36.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bradshaw, Gay, Schore, Allan, Brown, Janine, Poole, Joyce, and Moss, Cynthia. (2005) ‘Elephant Breakdown’. Nature, 433, 807.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bradshaw, Karen. (2020) Wildlife as Property Owners: A New Conception of Animal Rights. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Byrne, Richard, Bates, Lucy, and Moss, Cynthia. (2009) ‘Elephant Cognition in Primate Perspective’. Comparative Cognition & Behavior Reviews, 4, 115.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Castelló, Pablo, and Santiago-Ávila, Francisco. (2022) ‘Conservation after Sovereignty: Deconstructing Australian Policies against Horses with a Plea and Proposal’. Hypatia 37, 136–63.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chasi, Colin. (2021) Ubuntu for Warriors. Trenton: Africa World Press.Google Scholar
Chirindo, Kundai. (2016) ‘Bantu Sociolinguistics in Wangari Maathai's Peacebuilding Rhetoric’. Women's Studies in Communication, 39, 442–59.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chiyo, Patrick, Moss, Cynthia, and Alberts, Susan. (2012) ‘The Influence of Life History Milestones and Association Networks on Crop-Raiding Behavior in Male African Elephants’. PLoS ONE, 7, e31382.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Comstock, Gary, Crozier, G. K. D., Fenton, Andrew, John, Tyler, Syd M, L.. Johnson, Robert Jones, Nobis, Nathan, Peña-Guzmán, David, Rocha, James, Rollin, Bernard, and Sebo, Jeff. (2020) ‘The Philosophers’ Brief on Elephant Personhood’. New York State Appellate Court, No. 260441/16.Google Scholar
Delon, Nicolas. (Forthcoming) ‘Letting Animals off the Hook’. Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy.Google Scholar
Derham, Tristan, and Mathews, Freya. (2019) ‘Elephants as Refugees’. People and Nature, 2, 103–10.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Donaldson, Sue, and Kymlicka, Will. (2011) Zoopolis: A Political Theory of Animal Rights. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Douglas-Hamilton, Iain, Bhalla, Shivani, Wittemyer, George, and Vollrath, Fritz. (2006) ‘Behavioural Reactions of Elephants Towards a Dying and Deceased Matriarch’. Applied Animal Behaviour Science, 100, 87102.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Duguid, Shona, and Melis, Alicia. (2020) ‘How Animals Collaborate: Underlying Proximate Mechanisms’. Wiley Interdisciplinary Reviews: Cognitive Science, 11, e1529.Google ScholarPubMed
Dzobo, Noah Komla. (2010a) ‘The Image of Man in Africa’. In Gyekye, Kame and Wiredu, Kwasi (eds.), Person and Community: Ghanaian Philosophical Studies (Washington: Council for Research in Values and Philosophy), 123–36.Google Scholar
Dzobo, Noah Komla. (2010b) ‘Knowledge and Truth: Ewe and Akan Conceptions’. In Gyekye, Kame and Wiredu, Kwasi (eds.), Person and Community: Ghanaian Philosophical Studies (Washington: Council for Research in Values and Philosophy), 7182.Google Scholar
Elephantvoices. (2022c) ‘Elephants Learn from Others’. Accessed May 23, 2022. https://www.elephantvoices.org/elephant-sense-a-sociality-4/elephants-learn-from-others.html.Google Scholar
Etieyibo, Edwin. (2017a) ‘Anthropocentrism, African Metaphysical Worldview, and Animal Practices: A Reply to Kai Horsthemke’. Journal of Animal Ethics, 7, 145–62.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Etieyibo, Edwin. (2017b) ‘Moral Education, Ubuntu and Ubuntu-Inspired Communities’. South African Journal of Philosophy, 36, 311–25.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Etieyibo, Edwin. (2017c) ‘Ubuntu and the Environment’. In Afolayan, Adeshina and Falola, Toyin (eds.), The Palgrave Handbook of African Philosophy (New York: Palgrave Macmillan), 633–57.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fitzpatrick, Simon. (2017) ‘Animal Morality: What is the Debate About?’ Biology & Philosophy, 32, 1151–83.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fitzpatrick, Simon. (2020) ‘Chimpanzee Normativity: Evidence and Objections’. Biology & Philosophy, 35, 45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fougner, Tore. (2021) ‘Engaging the “Animal Question” in International Relations’. International Studies Review, 23, 862–86.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fox, Kieran, Muthukrishna, Michael, and Shultz, Susanne. (2017) ‘The Social and Cultural Roots of Whale and Dolphin Brains’. Nature Ecology & Evolution, 1, 16991705.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Goldenberg, Shifra, and Wittemyer, George. (2017) ‘Orphaned Female Elephant Social Bonds Reflect Lack of Access to Mature Adults’. Scientific Reports, 7, 14408.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Goldenberg, Shifra, and Wittemyer, George. (2018) ‘Orphaning and Natal Group Dispersal Are Associated with Social Costs in Female Elephants’. Animal Behaviour, 143, 18.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldenberg, Shifra, and Wittemyer, George. (2020) ‘Elephant Behavior Toward the Dead: A Review and Insights from Field Observations’. Primates, 61, 119–28.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gwaravanda, Ephraim Taurai. (2019) ‘Ubuntu Environmental Ethics: Conceptions and Misconceptions’. In Chemuru, Munamato (ed.), African Environmental Ethics (Cham: Springer Nature), 7992.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gyekye, Kwame. (2010a) ‘Person and Community in Akan Thought’. In Gyekye, Kwame and Wiredu, Kwasi (eds.), Person and Community: Ghanaian Philosophical Studies (Washington, DC: Council for Research in Values and Philosophy), 101–22.Google Scholar
Gyekye, Kwame. (2010b) ‘Death and the Afterlife in African Culture’. In Gyekye, Kwame and Wiredu, Kwasi (eds.), Person and Community: Ghanaian Philosophical Studies (Washington, DC: Council for Research in Values and Philosophy), 137–52.Google Scholar
Hampâté Bâ, Amadou. (1960) ‘Discourse at the African Commission of UNESCO’. Public speech given December 1, 1960. Accessed May 13, 2022. https://www.ina.fr/ina-eclaire-actu/audio/phd86073514/discours-de-hamadou-hampate-ba-a-la-commission-afrique-de-l-unesco.Google Scholar
Hart, Benjamin, and Hart, Lynette. (1994) ‘Fly Switching by Asian Elephants: Tool Use to Control Parasites’. Animal Behaviour, 48, 3545.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hewitson, Lee John, and Sullivan, Sian. (2021) ‘Producing Elephant Commodities for “Conservation Hunting” in Namibian Communal-Area Conservancies’. Journal of Political Ecology, 28, 124.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Horsthemke, Kai. (2015) Animals and African Ethics. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Horsthemke, Kai. (2017). ‘Animals and African Ethics’. Journal of Animal Ethics, 7, 119–44.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
IFAW. (2005) ‘The Debate on Elephant Culling: An Overview’. https://www.ifaw.org/resources/debate-elephant-culling-south-africa.Google Scholar
IFAW. (2022) ‘World Governments Reject Bid to Reopen Ivory Trade’. November 18, 2022. https://www.ifaw.org/international/press-releases/world-governments-reject-bid-reopen-ivory-trade.Google Scholar
Kioko, John, Moore, Sophie, Moshofsky, Kathleen, Nonnamaker, Anne, Ebanietti, Blaise, Thompson, Katherine, and Kiffner, Christian. (2022) ‘Characterizing Elephant-Livestock Interactions Using a Social-Ecological Approach’. In Kiffner, Christian, Bond, Monica and Lee, Derek (eds.), Tarangire: Human-Wildlife Coexistance in a Fragmented Ecosystem (Cham: Springer), 277–29.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Korsgaard, Christine. (2006) ‘Morality and the Distinctiveness of Human Action’. In Macedo, Stephen and Ober, Josiah (eds.), Primates and Philosophers: How Morality Evolved (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press), 98119.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lanjouw, Annette. (2021) ‘De-colonizing Conservation in a Global World’. American Journal of Primatology, 83, e23258.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lee, Phyllis, and Moss, Cynthia. (2012) ‘Wild Female African Elephants (Loxodonta Africana) Exhibit Personality Traits of Leadership and Social Integration’. Journal of Comparative Psychology, 126, 224–32.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Le Grange, Lesley. 2015. ‘Ubuntu/Botho as Ecophilosophy and Ecosophy’. Journal of Human Ecology, 49, 301–8.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mabele, Mathew, Sandroni, Laila, Collins, Ariadne, and Rubis, June. (2021) ‘What Do We Mean by Decolonizing Conservation? A Response to Lanjouw 2021’. Conviva [blog], October 7.Google Scholar
Madise, Dikeledi, and Isike, Christopher. (2020) ‘Ubuntu Diplomacy: Broadening Soft Power in an African Context’. Journal of Public Affairs, 20, e2097.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maj, Filip. (2020) ‘The Animal Other in Thaddeus Metz's Modal Ubuntu Ethics’. In Imafidon, Elvis (ed.), Handbook of African Philosophy of Difference (Berlin: Springer Nature), 333–46.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Masaka, Dennis. (2019) ‘Moral Status of Nonhuman Animals from an African Perspective: In Defense of Moderate Anthropocentric Thinking’. In Chemhuru, Munamato (ed.), African Environmental Ethics (Cham: Springer Nature), 223–38.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mawere, Munyaradzi. (2014) Environmental Conservation through Ubuntu and Other Emerging Perspectives. Bamenda: Langaa RPCIG.Google Scholar
Mbiti, John. (1990) African Religions & Philosophy. Oxford: Heinemann Educational Publishers. Originally published 1969.Google Scholar
McComb, Karen, Baker, Lucy, and Moss, Cynthia. (2006) ‘African Elephants Show High Levels of Interest in the Skulls and Ivory of Their Own Species’. Biology Letters, 2, 2628.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
McComb, Karen, Moss, Cynthia, Durant, Sarah, Baker, Lucy, and Sayialel, Soila. (2001) ‘Matriarchs as Repositories of Social Knowledge in African Elephants’. Science, 292, 491–94.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
McComb, Karen, Moss, Cynthia, Sayialel, Soila, and Baker, Lucy. (2000) ‘Unusually Extensive Networks of Vocal Recognition in African Elephants’. Animal Behaviour, 59, 1103–9.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
McComb, Karen, Shannon, Graeme, Sayialel, Katito, and Moss, Cynthia. (2014) ‘Elephants Can Determine Ethnicity, Gender, and Age from Acoustic Cues in Human Voices’. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 111, 5433–38.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Meijer, Eva. (2019) When Animals Speak: Toward an Interspecies Democracy. New York: New York University Press.Google Scholar
Menkiti, Ifeanyi. (1984) ‘Person and Community in African Traditional Thought’. In Wright, Richard (ed.), African Philosophy: An Introduction (Lanham: University Press of America), 171–82.Google Scholar
Metz, Thaddeus. (2012) ‘An African Theory of Moral Status: A Relational Alternative to Individualism and Holism’. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 15, 387402.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Metz, Thaddeus. (2013) ‘The Western Ethic of Care or an Afro-communitarian Ethic? Specifying the Right Relational Morality’. Journal of Global Ethics, 9, 7792.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Metz, Thaddeus. (2017) ‘How to Ground Animal Rights on African Values: Reply to Horsthemke’. Journal of Animal Ethics, 7, 163–74.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mokuku, Tšepo. (2017) ‘The Connotations of Botho Philosophy and its Potential Contribution Towards Environmental Conservation: The Case of Tlokoeng Community in Lesotho’. Environmental Education Research, 23, 1230–48.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Molefe, Motsamai. (2017) ‘A Critique of Thad Metz's African Theory of Moral Status.’ South African Journal of Philosophy, 36, 195205.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Monsó, Susana. (2015) ‘Empathy and Morality in Behaviour Readers’. Biology & Philosophy, 30, 671–90.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Monsó, Susana. (2022) ‘How to Tell if Animals Can Understand Death’. Erkenntnis, 87, 117–36.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Monsó, Susana, and Andrews, Kristin. (2022) ‘Animal Moral Psychologies’. In Doris, John M. and Vargas, Manuel (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Moral Psychology (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 388420.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Monsó, Susana, and Osuna-Mascaró, Antonio. (2021) ‘Death is Common, so is Understanding It: The Concept of Death in Other Species’. Synthese, 199, 2251–75.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Muashekele, Chris, Winschiers-Theophilus, Heike, Rodil, Kasper, Stanley, Colin, and Muashekele, Hina. (2022) ‘The Chronicles of Kunene: The Lion, the Omuhimba and the Drone.’ In Abdelnour-Nocera, José, Makori, Elisha Ondieki, Robles-Flores, Jose Antonio, and Bitso, Constance (eds.), Innovation Practices for Digital Transformation in the Global South (Springer: Cham), 149–64.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Muchinjo, Enock. (2021) ‘Zimbabwe's Elephant Culling Plans Stir Debate’. AlJazeera (5 June2021). Accessed November 14, 2022. https://www.aljazeera.com/features/2021/6/5/zimbabwe-elephant-culling-plan-stirs-debate.Google Scholar
Mumby, Hannah, and Plotnik, Joshua. (2018) ‘Taking the Elephants’ Perspective: Remembering Elephant Behavior, Cognition and Ecology in Human-elephant Conflict Mitigation’. Frontiers in Ecology and Evolution, 6, 122.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mutekwa, Anias, and Musanga, Terrence. (2013) ‘Subalternizing and Reclaiming Ecocentric Environmental Discourses in Zimbabwean Literature: (Re)Reading Doris Lessing's the Grass is Singing and Chenjerai Hove's Ancestors’. Interdisciplinary Studies in Literature and Environment, 20, 239–57CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ndlovu, Mduduzi, Devereux, Emma, Chieffe, Melissa, Asklof, Kendra, and Russo, Alicia. (2016) ‘Responses of African Elephants Towards a Bee Threat: Its Application in Mitigating Human-elephant Conflict’. South African Journal of Science, 112, 5256.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ngangah, Innocent. (2019) ‘Vital Force, Personhood, and Community in African Philosophy: An Ontological Study’. The International Journal of Humanities & Social Studies, 7, 4855.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nisha, Poyyaprath. (2017). ‘Ban and Benevolence: Circus, Animals and Indian State.’ The Indian Economic & Social History Review, 54, 239–66.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nolte, Suska, Sterck, Elisabeth, and Leeuwen, Edwin Van. (2023) ‘Does Tolerance Allow Bonobos to Outperform Chimpanzees on a Cooperative Task? A Conceptual Replication of Hare et al., 2007’. Royal Society Open Science, 10, 220194.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nussbaum, Martha. (2006) Frontiers of Justice. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
O'Connell-Rodwell, Caitlin. (2007) ‘Keeping an ‘Ear’ to the Ground: Seismic Communication in Elephants’. Physiology, 22, 287–94.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Okpoko, Mercy Osemudiame. (2022) ‘“Interconnectedness with Nature”: The Imperative for an African-centered Eco-philosophy in Forest Resource Conservation in Nigeria’. Ethics, Policy & Environment, 25, 2136.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
ORF (Österreichischer Rundfunk). (2023) ‘Elefantenbulle Abu kehrte nach Wien zurück’. Accessed June 10, 2023. https://wien.orf.at/stories/3208908/.Google Scholar
Oyowe, Anthony. (2013) ‘Strange Bedfellows: Rethinking Ubuntu and Human Rights in South Africa’. African Human Rights Law Journal, 13, 103–24.Google Scholar
Papadopoulos, Dennis. (2021) ‘Shared Intentionality in Nonhuman Great Apes: A Normative Model.’ Review of Philosophy and Psychology, October. https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-021-00594-x.Google Scholar
Plotnik, Joshua, and Jacobson, Sarah. (2022) ‘A “Thinking Animal” in Conflict: Studying Wild Elephant Cognition in the Shadow of Anthropogenic Change’. Current Opinion in Behavioral Sciences, 46, 101148.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Poole, Joyce. (1998) ‘An Exploration of a Commonality Between Ourselves and Elephants’. Etica & Animali, 9 (Special Issue on Nonhuman Personhood), 85110.Google Scholar
Poole, Joyce, and Granli, Petter. (2021) ‘The Elephant Ethogram: A Library of African Elephant Behavior’. Accessed May 23, 2022. https://www.elephantvoices.org/elephant-ethogram.html.Google Scholar
Poole, Joyce, and Moss, Cynthia. (2008) ‘Elephant Sociality and Complexity: The Scientific Evidence’. In Wemmer, Christen and Christen, Catherine (eds.), Elephants and Ethics: Toward a Morality of Coexistence (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press), 6998.Google Scholar
Roothaan, Angela. (2019) ‘Decolonizing Human-Animal Relations in an African Context: The Story of the Mourning’. In Chemuru, Munamato (ed.), African Environmental Ethics (Cham: Springer Nature), 240–55.Google Scholar
Ross, Don. (2023) ‘Economic Agency for Elephants’. Talk presented at the Animal Morality Conference, Vetmeduni Vienna, Austria, February 22–24, 2023.Google Scholar
Rowlands, Mark. (2012) Can Animals Be Moral? Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Samkange, Stanlake, and Samkange, Tommie Marie. (1980) Hunhuism or Ubuntuism: A Zimbabwe Indigenous Political Philosophy. Salisbury: Graham Publishing.Google Scholar
Samuel, Olusegun Steven, and Fayemi, Ademola Kazeem. (2020) ‘A Critique of Thaddeus Metz's Modal Relational Account of Moral Status’. Theoria, 67, 2844.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shannon, Graeme, Slotow, Rob, Durant, Sarah, Sayialel, Katito, Poole, Joyce, Moss, Cynthia, and McComb, Karen. (2013) ‘Effects of Social Disruption in Elephants Persist Decades After Culling’. Frontiers in Zoology, 10, 62.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Slotow, Rob, Blackmore, Andrew, Henley, Michelle, Trendler, Karen, and Garaï, Marion. (2021) ‘Could Culling of Elephants Be Considered Inhumane and Illegal in South African Law?’ Journal of International Wildlife Law & Policy, 24, 181206.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Slotow, Rob, and van Dyk, Gus. (2001) ‘Role of Delinquent Young “Orphan” Male Elephants in High Mortality of White Rhinoceros in Pilanesberg National Park, South Africa’. Koedoe, 44, 8594.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Slotow, Rob, van Dyk, Gus, Poole, Joyce, Page, Bruce, and Klocke, Andre. (2000) ‘Older Bull Elephants Control Young Males’. Nature, 408, 425–26.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Soltis, Joseph, King, Lucy, Douglas-Hamilton, Iain, Vollrath, Fritz, and Savage, Anne. (2014) ‘African Elephant Alarm Calls Distinguish Between Threats from Humans and Bees’. PLoS ONE, 9, e89403.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Stiles, Daniel. (2004) ‘The Ivory Trade and Elephant Conservation’. Environmental Conservation, 31, 309–21.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tokuyama, Nahoko, and Furuichi, Takeshi. (2017) ‘Leadership of Old Females in Collective Departures in Wild Bonobos (Pan Paniscus) at Wamba’. Behavioral Ecology and Sociobiology, 71, 55.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wrage, Birte. (2022) ‘Caring Animals and Care Ethics’. Biology & Philosophy, 37, 18.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Zambezi Grande. (2022) ‘The Magic of the Elephant's River Crossing’. Accessed May 23, 2022. https://www.zambezigrande.com/uncategorized/the-magic-of-the-elephants-river-crossing/.Google Scholar