Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-lnqnp Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-24T05:24:12.887Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Spinozistic Selves

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  20 January 2020

SAMUEL NEWLANDS*
Affiliation:
UNIVERSITY OF NOTRE [email protected]

Abstract

Spinoza's Ethics promises a path for sweeping personal transformations, but his accounts face two sets of overarching problems. The first concerns his peculiar metaphysics of action and agents; the second his apparent neglect of the very category of persons. Although these are somewhat distinct concerns, they have a common, unified solution in Spinoza's system that is philosophically rich and interesting, both in its own right and in relation to contemporary work in moral philosophy. After presenting the core of the problem facing Spinoza's action theory, I turn to his overlooked account of selves, one that can be illuminated by contemporary work on so-called deep-self theories. I then show how Spinoza's distinctive account of selves prevents his action theory from collapsing into metaphysical incoherence, and conclude with an implication for Spinoza's broader account of transformation.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © American Philosophical Association 2020

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

I thank audiences and discussion partners at the University of Washington, the Early Modern Tahoe Workshop, the Chicago Early Modern Roundtable group, and the University of Notre Dame for their insightful feedback and challenges. I am especially grateful to two anonymous referees for their perceptive questions, objections, suggestions, and exemplary response times.

All references to Spinoza's writings refer to the internal references of the Ethics by part, type, and number (e.g., Ip33), with pagination from Gebhardt's (1925) Opera (cited by volume and page as ‘G’) where necessary. All translations are based on Edwin's Curley 1985 edition, Collected Works, vol. 1.

References

Bennett, Jonathan. (1984) A Study of Spinoza's ‘Ethics’. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett.Google Scholar
Borcherding, Julia. (2016) ‘A View from Nowhere? The Place of Subjectivity in Spinoza's Rationalism’. In Kaukua, Jari and Ekenberg, Tomas (eds.), Subjectivity and Selfhood in Medieval and Early Modern Philosophy (Dordrecht: Springer), 215–62.Google Scholar
Carlisle, Claire. (2017) ‘Spinoza's Acquiscentia’. Journal of the History of Philosophy, 55, 209–36.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Della Rocca, Michael. (1996) Representation and the Mind-Body Problem in Spinoza. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Descartes, René. (1985) The Philosophical Writings of Descartes. Vol. 1. Translated by Cottingham, John, Stoothoff, Robert, and Murdoch, Dugald. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Frankfurt, Harry G. (1988a) ‘Identification and Externality’. In Frankfurt, The Importance of What We Care About: Philosophical Essays (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 5868.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frankfurt, Harry G. (1988b) ‘Identification and Wholeheartedness’. In Frankfurt, The Importance of What We Care About: Philosophical Essays (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 159–76.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frankfurt, Harry G. (1988c) ‘Three Concepts’. In Frankfurt, The Importance of What We Care About: Philosophical Essays (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 4757.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frankfurt, Harry G. (2006) ‘Taking Ourselves Seriously’. In Satz, Debra (ed.), Taking Ourselves Seriously and Getting It Right (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press), 126.Google Scholar
Garrett, Don. (2008) ‘Representation and Consciousness in Spinoza's Naturalistic Theory of the Imagination’. In Huenemann, Charles (ed.), Interpreting Spinoza: Critical Essays (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 425.Google Scholar
Hübner, Karolina. (2015) ‘Spinoza on Negation, Mind-Dependence, and the Reality of the Finite’. In Melamed, Yitzhak Y. (ed.), The Young Spinoza: A Metaphysician in the Making (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 221–37.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kierkegaard, Søren. (2009) Concluding Unscientific Postscript to the Philosophical Crumbs. Translated by Hannay., AlastairCambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Koistinen, Olli. (2009) ‘Spinoza's Eternal Self’. In Miller, Jon (ed.), Topics in Early Modern Philosophy of Mind (Dordrecht: Springer), 151–69.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Löwe, Can Laurens. (2018) ‘John Duns Scotus versus Thomas Aquinas on Action-Passion Identity’. British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 26, 1027–44.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Marshall, Colin. (2012) ‘Spinoza on Destroying Passions with Reason’. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 85, 139–60.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Melamed, Yitzhak Y. (2013) Spinoza's Metaphysics: Substance and Thought. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagel, Thomas. (1979) ‘Subjective and Objective’. In Nagel, Mortal Questions (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 196213.Google Scholar
Newlands, Samuel. (2018) Reconceiving Spinoza. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Renz, Ursula. (2011) ‘The Definition of the Human Mind and the Numerical Difference between Subjects (2p11–2p13s)’. In Hampe, Michael, Renz, Ursula, and Schnepf, Robert (eds.), Spinoza's Ethics: A Collective Commentary (Leiden: Brill), 99118.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Renz, Ursula. (2010) Die Erklärbarkeit von Erfahrung: Realismus und Subjektivität in Spinozas Theorie des menschlichen Geistes. Frankfurt: Klostermann.Google Scholar
Rutherford, Donald. (1999) ‘Salvation as a State of Mind: The Place of Acquiescentia in Spinoza's Ethics’. British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 7, 447473.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schechtman, Marya. (1996) The Constitution of Selves. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Schickel, Joel A. (2011) ‘Descartes on the Identity of Passion and Action’. British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 19, 1067–84.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shoemaker, David. (2015) ‘Ecumenical Attributability’. In Clarke, Randolph, McKenna, Michael, and Smith, Angela M. (eds.), The Nature of Moral Responsibility: New Essays (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 115–40.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sripada, Chandra. (2016) ‘Self-Expression: A Deep Self Theory of Moral Responsibility’. Philosophical Studies, 173, 1203–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Spinoza, Baruch. (1985) The Collected Works of Spinoza. Vol. 1. Edited and translated by Curley, Edwin. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Spinoza, Baruch. (2002) The Complete Works. Translated by Shirley., Samuel Edited by Morgan, Michael L.. New York: Hackett.Google Scholar
Spinoza, Baruch. (2018) Ethics: Proved in Geometrical Order. Edited by Kisner, Matthew J.. Translated by Silverthorne, Michael and Kisner., Matthew J.Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Spinoza, Baruch. (1925) Opera. 4 vols. Edited by Gebhardt, Carl. Heidelberg: Carl Winter.Google Scholar
Strohminger, Nina, Knobe, Joshua, and Newman, George. (2017) ‘The True Self: A Psychological Concept Distinct from the Self’. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 12, 551–60.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed