Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-hc48f Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-21T04:46:15.640Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

More Seriously Wrong, More Importantly Right

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  30 January 2019

THOMAS HURKA*
Affiliation:
DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY UNIVERSITY OF [email protected]

Abstract

Commonsense morality divides acts into those that are right and those that are wrong, but it thinks some wrong acts are more seriously wrong than others, for example, murder than breaking a promise. This has several implications. If an act is more seriously wrong, you should feel more guilt about it and, other things equal, you are more blameworthy for it and can deserve more punishment; we may also need to consider serious wrongness when choosing in conditions of risk or moral uncertainty. This paper examines how one act can be more seriously wrong than another, and, when it is, what makes this so. More specifically, it considers a number of different views about the ground of serious wrongness and explores the possibility that this may be different when acts violate deontological versus consequentialist duties. It also asks whether there is a parallel concept that admits of degrees on the side of rightness, one of being, as we can say, more importantly right. It aims to expand the scope of deontic theory from binary questions about right versus wrong to ones whose answers admit of degrees.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © American Philosophical Association 2019 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

Earlier versions of this paper were presented at Syracuse University, Hebrew University of Jerusalem, University of Toronto, Princeton University, Brown University, Haverford College, University of Pennsylvania, City University of New York, New York University (as the Mala Kamm Memorial Lecture), Oxford University, University of Warwick, Tulane University, Australian National University, Australian Catholic University, and MIT. I am grateful to audiences on all these occasions for comments and encouragement and am especially grateful to Selim Berker, Mitchell Berman, Brad Cokelet, Stephen Darwall, David Estlund, Johann Frick, Brad Inwood, Shelly Kagan, Frances Kamm, Kacper Kowalczyk, Seth Lazar, Adam Lerner, Michael Moore, Stephen Perry, Arthur Ripstein, Daniel Schwartz, Holly Smith, Victor Tadros, Sergio Tenenbaum, Hasko von Kriegstein, and two referees for this journal.

References

Aquinas, St. Thomas. (1981) Summa Theologiae. Translated by Fathers of the English Dominican Province. Westminster, MD: Christian Classics.Google Scholar
Beardsley, Elizabeth L. (1957) ‘Moral Worth and Moral Credit’. Philosophical Review, 66, 304–28.Google Scholar
Berman, Mitchell N., and Farrell, Ian P.. (2011) ‘Provocation Manslaughter as Partial Justification and Partial Excuse’. William and Mary Law Review, 52, 1027–109.Google Scholar
Brown, Campbell. (2016) ‘The Rightest Theory of Degrees of Rightness’. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 19, 2129.Google Scholar
Calder, Todd. (2005) ‘Kant and Degrees of Wrongness’. Journal of Value Inquiry, 39, 229–44.Google Scholar
Darwall, Stephen. (2010) ‘But It Would Be Wrong’. In Paul, Ellen Frankel, Miller, Fred D. Jr., and Paul, Jeffery (eds.), Moral Obligation (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 135–57.Google Scholar
Donagan, Alan. (1977) The Theory of Morality. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Ewing, A. C. (1947) The Definition of Good. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Gert, Joshua. (2004) Brute Rationality: Normativity and Human Action. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Graham, Peter A. (2010) ‘In Defense of Objectivism about Moral Obligation’. Ethics, 121, 88115.Google Scholar
Guerrero, Alexander A. (2007) ‘Don't Know, Don't Kill: Moral Ignorance, Culpability, and Caution’. Philosophical Studies, 136, 5997.Google Scholar
Hurka, Thomas, and Shubert, Esther. (2012) ‘Permissions to Do Less Than the Best: A Moving Band’. In Timmons, Mark (ed.), Oxford Studies in Normative Ethics, vol. 2 (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 127.Google Scholar
Jackson, Frank. (1991) ‘Decision-Theoretic Consequentialism and the Nearest and Dearest Objection’. Ethics, 101, 461–82.Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel. (1998) Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals. Translated by Gregor, Mary. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Laertius, Diogenes. (1998) ‘Lives of the Philosophers’. In Inwood, Brad and Gerson, L. P. (eds.), Hellenistic Philosophy, 2d ed. (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett), 190203.Google Scholar
Lazar, Seth. (Forthcoming) ‘Deontological Decision Theory and the Grounds of Subjective Permissibility’. In Timmons, Mark (ed.), Oxford Studies in Normative Ethics (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Lockhart, Ted. (2000) Moral Uncertainty and Its Consequences. New York: Oxford University.Google Scholar
Parfit, Derek. (2017) On What Matters. Vol. 3. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Peterson, Martin. (2013) The Dimensions of Consequentialism: Ethics, Equality and Risk. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Olsen, Kristian. (2018) ‘Subjective Rightness and Minimizing Expected Objective Wrongness’. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 99, 417–41.Google Scholar
Ross, W. D. (1930) The Right and the Good. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Scanlon, T. M. (1998) What We Owe to Each Other. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Scanlon, T. M. (2007) ‘Wrongness and Reasons: A Re-examination’. In Shafer-Landau, Russ (ed.), Oxford Studies in Metaethics, vol. 2 (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 520.Google Scholar
Scanlon, T. M. (2008) Moral Dimensions: Permissibility, Meaning, Blame. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Sepielli, Andrew. (2009) ‘What to Do When You Don't Know What to Do’. In Shafer-Landau, Russ (ed.), Oxford Studies in Metaethics, vol. 4 (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 528.Google Scholar
Sidgwick, Henry. (1907) The Methods of Ethics. 7th ed. London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Smith, Holly M. (1983) ‘Culpable Ignorance’. Philosophical Review, 92, 543–71.Google Scholar
Strawson, P. F. (1962) ‘Freedom and Resentment’. Proceedings of the British Academy, 48, 125.Google Scholar
Wallace, R. Jay. (1994) Responsibility and the Moral Sentiments. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Williams, Bernard. (1973) ‘Ethical Consistency’. In Williams, Problems of the Self (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 166–86.Google Scholar