Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-fbnjt Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-20T04:35:46.442Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

THE SOLIDITY AND NONSOLIDITY OF INITIAL SEGMENTS OF THE CORE MODEL

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  23 October 2018

GUNTER FUCHS
Affiliation:
MATHEMATICS, THE GRADUATE CENTER OF THE CITY UNIVERSITY OF NEW YORK 365 FIFTH AVENUE, NEW YORK, NY 10016, USA and MATHEMATICS, COLLEGE OF STATEN ISLAND OF CUNY STATEN ISLAND, NY 10314, USAE-mail:[email protected]: http://www.math.csi.cuny/edu/∼fuchs
RALF SCHINDLER
Affiliation:
INSTITUT FÜR MATHEMATISCHE LOGIK UND GRUNDLAGENFORSCHUNG UNIVERSITÄT MÜNSTER EINSTEINSTR. 62, 48149 MÜNSTER, GERMANYE-mail:[email protected]: https://ivv5hpp.uni-muenster.de/u/rds/

Abstract

It is shown that $K|{\omega _1}$ need not be solid in the sense previously introduced by the authors: it is consistent that there is no inner model with a Woodin cardinal yet there is an inner model W and a Cohen real x over W such that $K|{\omega _1}\,\, \in \,\,W[x] \setminus W$. However, if ${0^{\rm{\P}}}$ does not exist and $\kappa \ge {\omega _2}$ is a cardinal, then $K|\kappa$ is solid. We draw the conclusion that solidity is not forcing absolute in general, and that under the assumption of $\neg {0^{\rm{\P}}}$, the core model is contained in the solid core, previously introduced by the authors.

It is also shown, assuming ${0^{\rm{\P}}}$ does not exist, that if there is a forcing that preserves ${\omega _1}$, forces that every real has a sharp, and increases $\delta _2^1$, then ${\omega _1}$ is measurable in K.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © The Association for Symbolic Logic 2018 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

Claverie, B. and Schindler, R., Increasing ${u_2}$ by a stationary set preserving forcing , this JOURNAL, vol. 74 (2009), no. 1, pp. 187200.Google Scholar
Fuchs, G., Neeman, I., and Schindler, R., A criterion for coarse iterability. Archive for Mathematical Logic, vol. 49 (2010), no. 4, pp. 447467.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fuchs, G. and Schindler, R., Inner model theoretic geology, this JOURNAL, vol. 81 (2016), no. 3, pp. 972996.Google Scholar
Harrington, L., Long projective wellorderings. Annals of Mathematical Logic, vol. 12 (1977), no. 1, pp. 124.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jensen, R. B., The core model for nonoverlapping extender sequences, handwritten notes.Google Scholar
Jensen, R. B., ${\cal L}$-forcing, handwritten notes.Google Scholar
Jensen, R. B., On some problems of Mitchell, Welch, and Vickers, handwritten notes, 1990.Google Scholar
Steel, J. R. and Welch, P. D., ${\rm{\Sigma }}_3^1$ absoluteness and the second uniform indiscernible. Israel Journal of Mathematics , vol. 104 (1998), pp. 157190.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Woodin, W. H., The Axiom of Determinacy, Forcing Axioms, and the Nonstationary Ideal, DeGruyter, Berlin, 1999.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zeman, M., Inner Models and Large Cardinals, DeGruyter, Berlin, 2002.CrossRefGoogle Scholar