Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-jkksz Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T14:03:01.855Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Recursive categoricity and persistence

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  12 March 2014

Terrence Millar*
Affiliation:
Department of Mathematics, University of Wisconsin, Madison, Wisconsin 53706

Extract

This paper is concerned with recursive structures and the persistance of an effective notion of categoricity. The terminology and notational conventions are standard. We will devote the rest of this paragraph to a cursory review of some of the assumed conventions. If θ is a formula, then θk denotes θ if k is zero, and ¬θ if k is one. If A is a sequence with domain a subset of ω, then A n denotes the sequence obtained by restricting the domain of A to n. For an effective first order language L, let {ci i<ω} be distinct new constants, and let {θ i i<ω} be an effective enumeration of all sentences in the language L ∪ {ci j<ω}. An infinite L-structure is recursive iff it has universe ω and the set is recursive, where cn is interpreted by n. In general we say that a set of formulas is recursive if the set of its indices with respect to an enumeration such as above is recursive. The ∃-diagram of a structure is recursive if the structure is recursive and the set and θ i is an existential sentence} is also recursive. The definition of “the ∀∃-diagram of is recursive” is similar.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Association for Symbolic Logic 1986

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCE

[1] Gončarov, S. S., Self-stability and computable families of constructivizations, Algébra i Logika, vol. 14 (1975), pp. 647680; English translation, Algebra and Logic , vol. 14 (1975), pp. 392–408.Google Scholar