Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-r5fsc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-23T17:20:12.327Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

A NOTE ON THE STRONG ERDŐS–HAJNAL PROPERTY FOR GRAPHS WITH BOUNDED VC-MINIMAL COMPLEXITY

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  15 November 2024

YAYI FU*
Affiliation:
THE MATHEMATICS DEPARTMENT UNIVERSITY OF NOTRE DAME NOTRE DAME, IN USA
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Inspired by Adler’s idea on VC minimal theories [1], we introduce VC-minimal complexity. We show that for any $N\in \mathbb {N}^{>0}$, there is $k_N>0$ such that for any finite bipartite graph $(X,Y;E)$ with VC-minimal complexity $< N$, there exist $X'\subseteq X$, $Y'\subseteq Y$ with $|X'|\geq k_N |X|$, $|Y'|\geq k_N |Y|$ such that $X'\times Y' \subseteq E$ or $X'\times Y'\cap E=\emptyset $.

Type
Article
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Association for Symbolic Logic

1. Introduction

Erdős–Hajnal conjecture [Reference Erdös and Hajnal8] says for any graph H there is $\epsilon>0$ such that if a graph G does not contain any induced subgraph isomorphic to H then G has a clique or an anti-clique of size $\geq |G|^\epsilon $ . More generally, we say a family of finite graphs has the Erdős–Hajnal property if there is $\epsilon>0$ such that for any graph G in the family, G has a clique or an anti-clique of size $\geq |G|^\epsilon $ . A family of finite graphs has the strong Erdős–Hajnal property if there is $\epsilon>0$ such that for any graph $G=(V,E)$ in the family, there exist $X,Y\subseteq V$ such that $X\cap Y=\emptyset $ , $|X|\geq \epsilon |V|$ , $|Y|\geq \epsilon |V|$ , and $X\times Y\subseteq E$ or $X\times Y\subseteq \neg E$ . The strong Erdős–Hajnal property implies the Erdős-Hajnal property (see [Reference Alon, Pach, Pinchasi, Radoičić and Sharir2, Theorem 1.2.]). Malliaris and Shelah proved in [Reference Malliaris and Shelah12] that the family of stable graphs has the Erdős–Hajnal property. Chernikov and Starchenko gave another proof for stable graphs in [Reference Chernikov and Starchenko3] and in [Reference Chernikov and Starchenko4] they proved that the family of distal graphs has the strong Erdős–Hajnal property. In general, we are interested in whether the family of bounded VC-dimension (i.e., NIP [Reference Simon14]) graphs, which contains both stable graphs and distal graphs, has the Erdős–Hajnal property. Motivation for studying this problem was given in [Reference Fox, Pach and Suk10], which also gave a lower bound $e^{(\log n)^{1-o(1)}}$ for largest clique or anti-clique in a graph with bounded VC-dimension. In this paper, we consider graphs of bounded VC-minimal complexity, a special case of NIP graphs. Roughly speaking, we say a bipartite graph $(X,Y;E)$ has VC-minimal complexity $<N$ if for all $a\in X$ , the set $\{y\in Y: (a,y)\in E\}$ is a finite union of Swiss Cheeses such that the sum of the number of holes and the number of Swiss Cheeses is $<N$ . We will show that the strong Erdős–Hajnal property holds for the family of finite bipartite graphs $(X,Y;E)$ of bounded VC-minimal complexity. One example is definable relations $E(x,y)$ with $|x|=1,|y|=1$ in $ACVF$ (algebraically closed valued field). Since $ACVF$ allows Swiss Cheese decomposition [Reference Holly11], given any $\mathcal {M}\models ACVF$ and any definable relation $E \subseteq M\times M$ , the family $\{(X,Y;E_{\upharpoonright X\times Y}):X,Y$ finite subsets of $M\}$ has bounded VC-minimal complexity, and thus the strong Erdős–Hajnal property holds. This partially generalizes [Reference Chernikov and Starchenko4, Example 4.11(2)].

Recently, in [Reference Nguyen, Scott and Seymour13], Nguyen, Scott, and Seymour proved that any family of finite graphs with bounded VC-dimension has the Erdős–Hajnal property, which gave another proof that any family of finite graphs with bounded VC-minimal complexity has the Erdős–Hajnal property.

In addition to its relation with the Erdős–Hajnal property, the strong Erdős–Hajnal property is of independent interest. On one hand, in model theory, partitioned formulas and hence bipartite graphs are often used (e.g., definition of stable formulas and definition of NIP formulas). On the other hand, in [Reference Erdos, Hajnal and Pach9, Theorem 1], Erdős, Hajnal, and Pach proved the following fact:

Fact 1.1. Let H be a fixed graph with k vertices. Any H-free graph with n vertices or its complement has a complete bi-partite subgraph with $\lfloor (n/k)^{1/(k-1)}\rfloor $ vertices in its classes.

This fact roughly says that given a fixed H, for any H-free graph, there exists in it or in its complement a complete bipartite graph of polynomial size. So it’s natural to ask when we can find in a graph or its complement a complete bipartite graph of linear size. A random graph argument in [Reference Choromanski, Falik, Liebenau, Patel and Pilipczuk5] together with results in [Reference Chudnovsky, Scott, Seymour and Spirkl6] characterized families of graphs that are defined by omitting a finite set of graphs and satisfy the strong Erdős–Hajnal property: If a family of graphs is defined by omitting a finite set of graphs, then it has the strong Erdős–Hajnal property iff it omits some forest together with its complement. We will show that the family of all forests has bounded VC-minimal complexity and thus, the case of bounded VC-minimal complexity is not covered in [Reference Chudnovsky, Scott, Seymour and Spirkl6]. It is also an example where a family of graphs has bounded VC-minimal complexity and is not defined by omitting a finite set of graphs.

We will prove the following main theorem:

Theorem 1.2. For $N>0$ , let $k_N=\dfrac {1}{2^{N+4}}$ . If a finite bipartite graph $(X,Y;E)$ has VC-minimal complexity $<N$ then there exist $X'\subseteq X$ , $Y'\subseteq Y$ with $|X'|\geq k_N|X|$ , $|Y'|\geq k_N|Y|$ such that $X'\times Y'\subseteq E$ or $X'\times Y'\cap E=\emptyset $ .

2. Preliminaries

The following Definitions 2.1, 2.2, 2.5 are based on notions in [Reference Adler1].

Definition 2.1. Given a set U, a family of subsets $\Psi =\{B_i:i\in I\}\subseteq \mathcal {P}(U)$ , where I is some index set, is called a directed family if for any $B_i,B_j\in \Psi $ , $B_i\subseteq B_j$ or $B_j \subseteq B_i$ or $B_i\cap B_j=\emptyset $ .

Definition 2.2. Given a directed family $\Psi $ of subsets of U, a set $B\in \Psi $ is a called a $\Psi $ -ball. A set $S \subseteq U$ is a $\Psi $ -Swiss cheese if $S = B \setminus (B_0 \cup \dots \cup B_n)$ , where each of $B,B_0,\dots ,B_n$ is a $\Psi $ -ball. We will call B an outer ball of S, and each $B_i$ is called a hole of S.

Definition 2.3. A graph G is a pair $(V,E)$ where V is a finite set of vertices and $E\subseteq V\times V$ is a binary symmetric anti-reflexive relation.

Definition 2.4. A bipartite graph is a triple $(X,Y;E)$ where X, Y are finite sets and $E\subseteq X\times Y$ .

Notation. Given a bipartite graph $(X,Y;E)$ , $a\in X$ , $S\subseteq Y$ , we define $E(a,S)$ as the set $\{b\in S: (a,b)\in E\}$ .

Definition 2.5. Given a finite bipartite graph $(X,Y;E)$ , we say it has VC-minimal complexity $<N$ if there is a directed family $\Psi $ of subsets of Y such that for each $a\in X$ , $E(a,Y)$ is a finite disjoint union of $\Psi $ -Swiss cheeses and the number of outer balls $+$ the number of holes $<N$ . That is, $E(a,Y)=(B_{11}\setminus (B_{12}\cup \dots \cup B_{1d(1)}))$ $\dot \cup $ $\cdots $ $\dot \cup $ $(B_{s1}\setminus (B_{s2}\cup \dots \cup B_{sd(s)}))$ where $d(1)+\dots +d(s)<N$ .

3. Proof

Theorem 3.1. For $N>0$ , let $k_N=\dfrac {1}{2^{N+4}}$ . If a finite bipartite graph $(X,Y;E)$ has VC-minimal complexity $<N$ then there exist $X'\subseteq X$ , $Y'\subseteq Y$ with $|X'|\geq k_N|X|$ , $|Y'|\geq k_N|Y|$ such that $X'\times Y'\subseteq E$ or $X'\times Y' \cap E=\emptyset $ .

Proof. We prove by induction on N. If $N=1$ then for all $a\in X$ , $E(a,Y)=\emptyset $ . So $X\times Y\subseteq \neg E$ .

Suppose true for N and we show for $N+1$ .

Let $(X,Y;E)$ be a finite bipartite graph with VC-minimal complexity $<N+1$ . Then there is a directed family $\Psi $ such that for each $a\in X$ ,

$$ \begin{align*} E(a,Y)=(B^a_{11}\setminus (B^a_{12}\cup\dots\cup B^a_{1d(1)}))\dot\cup\cdots \dot\cup(B^a_{s_a1}\setminus (B^a_{s_a2}\cup\dots\cup B^a_{s_ad(s_a)})), \end{align*} $$

where the $B^a_{kl}$ ’s are $\Psi $ -balls and $d(1)+\dots +d(s_a)<N+1$ . Consider the finite family

$$ \begin{align*} \mathcal{F}:=\{B^a_{kl}:a\in X, k,l\in\mathbb{N}\}\cup\{Y\}. \end{align*} $$

Since $\mathcal {F}$ is finite and $|Y|\geq \frac {1}{8}|Y|$ , there is a minimal $Z\in \mathcal {F}$ such that $|Z|\geq \frac {1}{8}|Y|$ (minimal with respect to the partial order $\subseteq $ ). Let

$$ \begin{align*} \mathcal{F}':=\{B^a_{kl}:a\in X, k,l\in\mathbb{N}, B^a_{kl}\subsetneq Z\}. \end{align*} $$

Let $C_1,\dots ,C_m$ be maximal elements in $\mathcal {F}'$ . Then $\forall a\in X$ , $\forall k,l \in \mathbb {N}$ , $\forall t\in \{1,\dots ,m\}$ , if $B^a_{kl}\subsetneq Z$ then $B^a_{kl}\cap C_t=\emptyset $ or $B^a_{kl}\subseteq C_{t}$ . Let $R=Z\setminus (C_1\cup \dots \cup C_{m})$ .

Claim 3.2. $\forall a\in X$ , $E(a,R)=R$ or $E(a,R)=\emptyset $ .

Proof. $E(a,Y){\kern-1.2pt}={\kern-1.2pt}(B^a_{11}{\kern-1.5pt}\setminus{\kern-1.5pt} (B^a_{12}{\kern-1.2pt}\cup \dots \cup{\kern-1.2pt} B^a_{1d(1)}))$ $\dot \cup $ $\dots $ $\dot \cup $ $(B^a_{s_a1}{\kern-1.2pt}\setminus{\kern-1.2pt} (B^a_{s_a2}{\kern-1.2pt}\cup \dots \cup{\kern-1.2pt} B^a_{s_ad(s_a)}))$ . Suppose $E(a,R)\neq \emptyset $ . Then for some $k\in \{1,\dots ,s_a\}$ ,

$$ \begin{align*} (B^a_{k1}\setminus (B^a_{k2}\cup\dots\cup B^a_{kd(k)}))\cap R\neq\emptyset. \end{align*} $$

May assume $(B^a_{11}\setminus (B^a_{12}\cup \dots \cup B^a_{1d(1)}))\cap R\neq \emptyset $ . So $B^a_{11}\cap Z\neq \emptyset $ . Since Z is Y or a $\Psi $ -ball, $B^a_{11}\subsetneq Z$ or $B^a_{11}\supseteq Z$ . If $B^a_{11}\subsetneq Z$ then $B^a_{11}\subseteq C_1\cup \dots \cup C_{m}$ and $B^a_{11}\cap R=\emptyset $ , a contradiction. Hence $B^a_{11}\supseteq Z$ . Similarly, for any hole $K\in \{B^a_{12},\dots ,B^a_{1d(1)}\}$ , if $K\cap R\neq \emptyset $ , then $K\subsetneq Z$ or $K\supseteq Z$ . If $K\subsetneq Z$ then $K\subseteq C_1\cup \dots \cup C_{m}$ and $K\cap R=\emptyset $ , a contradiction. If $K\supseteq Z$ , then

$$ \begin{align*} (B^a_{11}\setminus (B^a_{12}\cup\dots\cup B^a_{1d(1)}))\cap R\subseteq (B^a_{11}\setminus (B^a_{12}\cup\dots\cup B^a_{1d(1)}))\cap Z=\emptyset, \end{align*} $$

a contradiction. Hence we must have $Z\subseteq B^a_{11}$ and $K\cap R=\emptyset $ for all $K\in \{B^a_{12},\dots ,B^a_{1d(1)}\}$ . So $R\subseteq B^a_{11}\setminus (B^a_{12}\cup \dots \cup B^a_{1d(1)})\subseteq E(a;Y)$ .

Since $R\cup C_1\cup \dots \cup C_m=Z$ and $|Z|\geq \frac {1}{8}|Y|$ , by Claim 3.2, we may assume that $|C_1\cup \dots \cup C_{m}|\geq \frac {1}{16}|Y|$ .

Let $t_0$ be smallest such that $|C_1\cup \dots \cup C_{t_0}|\geq \frac {1}{32}|Y|$ . Because $|C_1\cup \dots \cup C_{t_0-1}|<\frac {1}{32}|Y|$ and $|C_{t_0}|<\frac {1}{8}|Y|$ (by minimality of Z),

$$ \begin{align*} \frac{1}{32}|Y|\leq|C_1\cup\dots\cup C_{t_0}|\leq(\frac{1}{32}+\frac{1}{8})|Y|. \end{align*} $$

Let $C:=C_1\cup \dots \cup C_{t_0}$ .

Consider

$$ \begin{align*} A_1:=\{a\in X:\exists k,l\in\mathbb{N}, B^a_{kl}\subseteq C\}, \end{align*} $$
$$ \begin{align*} A_2:=\{a\in X:\forall k,l\in\mathbb{N}, B^a_{kl}\nsubseteq C\}. \end{align*} $$

Since $A_1\cup A_2=X$ , we have $|A_1|\geq \frac {1}{2}|X|$ or $|A_2|\geq \frac {1}{2}|X|$ .

Suppose $|A_1|\geq \frac {1}{2}|X|$ . For $a\in A_1$ ,

$$ \begin{align*} E(a,Y\setminus C)&=((B^a_{11}\setminus B^a_{12}\cup\dots\cup B^a_{1d(1)})\cap(Y\setminus C))\dot\cup\dots\\& \quad\ \dot\cup((B^a_{s_a1}\setminus B^a_{s_a2}\cup\dots\cup B^a_{s_ad(s_a)})\cap (Y\setminus C))\\&=(((B^a_{11}\cap (Y\setminus C))\setminus (B^a_{12}\cap (Y\setminus C))\cup\dots\cup (B^a_{1d(1)}\cap(Y\setminus C)))\dot\cup\dots \\& \quad\ \dot\cup(B^a_{s_a1}\cap(Y{\kern-1pt}\setminus{\kern-1pt} C))\setminus (((B^a_{s_a2}\cap(Y{\kern-1pt}\setminus{\kern-1pt} C))\cup\dots\cup (B^a_{s_ad(s_a)}\cap(Y{\kern-1pt}\setminus{\kern-1pt} C)))). \end{align*} $$

Since $a\in A_1$ , for some $B^a_{kl}$ , $B^a_{kl}\subseteq C$ . If $B^a_{kl}$ is an outer ball, say $B^a_{kl}=B^a_{11}$ , then

$$ \begin{align*} E(a,Y\setminus C)&=((B^a_{21}\cap (Y\setminus C))\setminus (B^a_{22}\cap (Y\setminus C))\cup\dots\cup (B^a_{2d(2)}\cap(Y\setminus C)))\dot\cup\dots\\& \quad\ \dot\cup (B^a_{s_a1}\cap(Y\setminus C))\setminus (((B^a_{s_a2}\cap(Y\setminus C))\cup\dots\cup (B^a_{s_ad(s_a)}\cap(Y\setminus C)))). \end{align*} $$

If $B^a_{kl}$ is a hole, say $B^a_{kl}=B^a_{12}$ , then

$$ \begin{align*} E(a,Y\setminus C)&=((B^a_{11}\cap (Y\setminus C))\setminus (B^a_{13}\cap (Y\setminus C))\cup\dots\cup (B^a_{1d(1)}\cap(Y\setminus C)))\dot\cup\dots \\& \quad\ \dot\cup(B^a_{s_a1}\cap(Y\setminus C))\setminus (((B^a_{s_a2}\cap(Y\setminus C))\cup\dots\cup (B^a_{s_ad(s_a)}\cap(Y\setminus C)))).\end{align*} $$

Hence $(A_1, Y\setminus C; E)$ is a bipartite graph of VC-minimal complexity $<N$ such that for any $a\in A_1$ , $E(a,Y\setminus C)$ is a disjoint union of $\Psi '$ -Swiss cheeses, where

$$ \begin{align*} \Psi':=\{D\cap (Y\setminus C): D\in\Psi\}. \end{align*} $$

By inductive hypothesis, there exist $F\subseteq A_1$ , $G\subseteq Y\setminus C$ with

$$ \begin{align*} |F|\geq k_N|A_1|\geq \frac{1}{2}k_N|X|, \end{align*} $$
$$ \begin{align*} |G|\geq k_N|Y\setminus C|\geq (1-\frac{1}{32}-\frac{1}{8})k_N|Y|, \end{align*} $$

such that $F\times G\subseteq E$ or $F\times G\subseteq \neg E$ . So the conclusion holds for $N+1$ .

Suppose $|A_2|\geq \frac {1}{2}|X|$ . Then $\forall a\in A_2$ , $\forall k,l\in \mathbb {N}$ , $B^a_{kl}\nsubseteq C$ .

Claim 3.3. $\forall a\in A_2$ , $E(a,C)=\emptyset $ or $E(a,C)=C$ .

Proof. We first show that for all $a\in A_2$ , for all $k,l\in \mathbb {N}$ , if $B^a_{kl}\cap C\neq \emptyset $ then $C\subseteq B^a_{kl}$ .

Fix $a\in A_2$ and $k,l\in \mathbb {N}$ . If $B^a_{kl}\cap C\neq \emptyset $ , then $B^a_{kl}\cap Z\neq \emptyset $ . So $B^a_{kl}\subsetneq Z$ or $B^a_{kl}\supseteq Z$ . If $B^a_{kl}\subsetneq Z$ , then $B^a_{kl}\subseteq C_t$ for some $t\in \{1,\dots ,m\}$ . But since $B^a_{kl}\nsubseteq C$ , $B^a_{kl}\cap C=\emptyset $ , a contradiction. Hence we must have $B^a_{kl}\supseteq Z$ when $B^a_{kl}\cap C\neq \emptyset $ . Thus $\forall a\in A_2$ , $\forall k,l\in \mathbb {N}$ , $B^a_{kl}\cap C=\emptyset $ or $B^a_{kl}\supseteq C$ .

For $a\in A_2$ , if $E(a,C)\neq \emptyset $ , may assume $C\cap (B^a_{11}\setminus (B^a_{12}\cup \dots \cup B^a_{1d(1)}))\neq \emptyset $ . So $C\cap B^a_{11}\neq \emptyset $ and $C\subseteq B^a_{11}$ . For any hole $K\in \{B^a_{12},\dots ,B^a_{1d(1)}\}$ , if $C\cap K\neq \emptyset $ , then $C\subseteq K$ and $C\cap B^a_{11}\setminus (B^a_{12}\cup \dots \cup B^a_{1d(1)}))=\emptyset $ , a contradiction. So for any hole K, $C\cap K=\emptyset $ . Thus $C\subseteq (B^a_{11}\setminus (B^a_{12}\cup \dots \cup B^a_{1d(1)}))$ . Hence $\forall a\in A_2$ , $E(a,C)=\emptyset $ or $E(a,C)=C$ .

So the conclusion holds for $N+1$ (because $|A_2|\geq \frac {1}{2}|X|$ and $|C|\geq \frac {1}{32}|Y|$ ).

4. Corollary

We can apply Theorem 3.1 to VC-minimal theories (ACVF in particular). The following notions and fact about VC-minimal theories come from [Reference Adler1]. We rephrase them as in [Reference Cotter and Starchenko7] for notational convenience.

Definition 4.1 [Reference Adler1, Definition 5][Reference Cotter and Starchenko7, Definition 2.1(1)]

A set of formulae $\Psi = \{\psi _i(x, \bar {y_i}) : i \in I\}$ is called a directed family if for any $\psi _0(x, \bar {y_0}), \psi _1(x, \bar {y_1}) \in \Psi $ and any parameters $\bar {a_0}, \bar {a_1}$ taken from any model of T, one of the following is true:

(i): $\psi _0(x, \bar {a_0}) \subseteq \psi _1(x, \bar {a_1})$ ;

(ii): $\psi _1(x, \bar {a_1}) \subseteq \psi _0(x, \bar {a_0})$ ;

(iii): $\psi _0(x, \bar {a_0}) \cap \psi _1(x, \bar {a_1}) = \emptyset $ .

Definition 4.2 [Reference Adler1, Definition 3][Reference Cotter and Starchenko7, Definition 2.1(2)]

A theory T is VC-minimal if there is a directed family $\Psi $ such that for any formula $\varphi (x,\bar {y})$ and any parameters $\bar {c}$ taken from any model of T, $\varphi (x,\bar {c})$ is equivalent to a finite boolean combination of formulae $\psi _i(x,\bar {b_i})$ , where each $\psi _i \in \Psi $ .

Fact 4.1 [Reference Adler1, Proposition 7][Reference Cotter and Starchenko7, Theorem 2.6]

Fix T a VC-minimal theory and a directed family of formulae $\Psi $ for T. For every formula $\tau (x,\bar {y})$ , there are a finite set $\Psi _0 \subseteq \Psi $ and natural numbers $n_1$ and $n_2$ such that for every parameter tuple $\bar {a}$ , $\tau (x,\bar {a})$ can be decomposed as the union of at most $n_1$ disjoint Swiss cheeses, each of them having at most $n_2$ holes, such that all balls appearing in the decomposition are instances of formulae in $\Psi _0$ .

By Fact 4.1, for any VC-minimal theory T, any model $\mathcal {M}\models T$ and any definable relation $E(x,\bar {y})\subseteq M\times M^{|\bar {y}|}$ , there is $N\in \mathbb {N}^{>0}$ such that for any finite disjoint $X,Y\subseteq M$ , the bipartite graph $(X,Y;E)$ has VC-minimal complexity $<N$ . Thus we have the following:

Corollary 4.1.1. Given a VC-minimal theory T, a model $\mathcal {M}\models T$ and an $\mathcal {L}$ -formula $\varphi (x,\bar {y},\bar {z})$ , let $N\in \mathbb {N}^{>0}$ satisfy: for any $\bar {b}\in M^{|\bar {y}|}$ , $\bar {c}\in M^{|\bar {z}|}$ , $\varphi (x,\bar {b},\bar {c})$ can be decomposed as the union of at most $n_1$ disjoint Swiss cheeses, each of them having at most $n_2$ holes, with $n_1n_2<N$ . Then for any fixed $\bar {c}\in M^{|\bar {z}|}$ , any pair of finite sets $X\subseteq M$ , $Y\subseteq M^{|\bar {y}|}$ , there exist $X'\subseteq X$ , $Y'\subseteq Y$ such that $|X'|\geq \dfrac {1}{2^{N+4}}|X|$ , $Y'\geq \dfrac {1}{2^{N+4}}|Y|$ , and $\forall x\in X'$ $\forall \bar {y}\in Y'$ $\varphi (x,\bar {y},\bar {c})$ or $\forall x\in X'$ $\forall \bar {y}\in Y'$ $\neg \varphi (x,\bar {y},\bar {c})$ .

Remark ([Reference Chernikov and Starchenko4, Example 4.11(2)] shows)

Let $\mathcal {M}\models ACVF_{0,0}$ and let a formula $\varphi (\bar {x}, \bar {y},\bar {z})$ be given. Then there is some $\delta = \delta (\varphi )> 0$ such that for any definable relation $E(\bar {x}, \bar {y}) = \varphi (\bar {x}, \bar {y},\bar {c})$ for some $\bar {c}\in M^{|\bar {z}|}$ and finite disjoint $X\subseteq M^{|\bar {x}|}$ , $Y\subseteq M^{|\bar {y}|}$ , there are some $X'\subseteq X$ , $Y'\subseteq Y$ with $|X'| \geq \delta |X|$ , $|Y'|\geq \delta |Y|$ and $X'\times Y'\subseteq E$ or $X'\times Y'\subseteq \neg E$ . By [Reference Holly11], $ACVF$ has Swiss Cheese decomposition and thus is a VC-minimal theory. So by Corollary 4.1.1, the same conclusion also holds in $ACVF_{p,q}$ for nonzero $p,q$ when $|\bar {x}|=1$ .

Note: [Reference Chernikov and Starchenko4, Example 4.11(2)] allows $|\bar {x}|>1$ and $|\bar {y}|>1$ for definable relations $E(\bar {x},\bar {y})$ in $ACVF_{0,0}$ . But for positive characteristics, when $|\bar {x}|>1$ , $|\bar {y}|>1$ , there is a counter example given in [Reference Chernikov and Starchenko4, Proposition 6.2]:

Fact 4.2 [Reference Chernikov and Starchenko4, Proposition 6.2]

Let $p>0$ , and let $\mathbb {F}= \mathbb {F}_p^{alg}$ . For a set of points $P \subseteq \mathbb {F}^2$ and a set of lines L in $\mathbb {F}^2$ we denote by $I(P,L) \subseteq P \times L$ the incidence relation, i.e., $I(P,L) = \{(p,l) \in P \times L : p \in l\}$ . Then for all constants $\delta> 0$ , there exist a finite (sufficiently large) set of points $P \subseteq \mathbb {F}^2$ and a finite (sufficiently large) set of lines L in $\mathbb {F}^2$ such that for all $P_0 \subseteq P$ and $L_0 \subseteq L$ with $|P_0| \geq \delta |P|$ , $|L_0| \geq \delta |L|$ , $I(P_0,L_0) \neq \emptyset $ .

Thus the strong Erdős–Hajnal property fails for I in $\mathbb {F}$ and we cannot generalize Corollary 4.1.1 to the case where both $|\bar {x}|>1$ and $|\bar {y}|>1$ .

Remark. In [Reference Chudnovsky, Scott, Seymour and Spirkl6], Chudnovsky, Scott, Seymour, and Spirkl proved the following fact:

Fact 4.3 [Reference Chudnovsky, Scott, Seymour and Spirkl6, 1.2]

For every forest H, there exists $\epsilon> 0$ such that for every graph G with $|G|> 1$ that is both H-free and $\overline {H}$ -free, there is a pair of disjoint subsets $(A, B)$ with $|A|, |B| \geq \epsilon |G|$ such that $A\times B\subseteq E$ or $A\times B\cap E=\emptyset $ .

The family of forests can be shown to have VC-minimal complexity $\leq 2$ and thus the VC-minimal case is not covered in [Reference Chudnovsky, Scott, Seymour and Spirkl6].

For a forest H, $v\in V(H)$ , let $B_{v,\triangleleft }$ denote the set of the predecessor of v and $B_{v,\triangleright }$ denote the set of successors of v. Consider the family $\mathcal {F}_{H}:=$ $\{B_{v,\triangleleft }, B_{v,\triangleright }: v\in H\}$ . $\mathcal {F}_H$ is directed: Let $v, w\in V(H)$ . If $B_{v,\triangleleft }\cap B_{w,\triangleright }\neq \emptyset $ , then since $B_{v,\triangleleft }$ is a singleton, $B_{v,\triangleleft }\subseteq B_{w,\triangleright }$ . Similarly, if $B_{v,\triangleleft }\cap B_{w,\triangleleft }\neq \emptyset $ , then $B_{v,\triangleleft }\subseteq B_{w,\triangleleft }$ . If $B_{v,\triangleright }\cap B_{w,\triangleright }\neq \emptyset $ , then $v=w$ and $B_{v,\triangleright }= B_{w,\triangleright }$ .

For any $v\in V(H)$ , $E_v=B_{v,\triangleleft } \sqcup B_{v,\triangleright }$ . So given any forest $H=(V(H),E)$ and disjoint $X,Y\subseteq V(H)$ , the bipartite graph $(X,Y;E)$ has VC-minimal complexity $\leq 2$ .

Acknowledgments

The author is grateful to her advisor Sergei Starchenko and the referee for reading the paper and giving helpful suggestions.

Funding

The author was partially supported by the NSF research grant DMS-1800806.

References

REFERENCES

Adler, H., Theories controlled by formulas of vapnik-chervonenkis codimension 1, preprint, 2008.Google Scholar
Alon, N., Pach, J., Pinchasi, R., Radoičić, R., and Sharir, M., Crossing patterns of semi-algebraic sets . Journal of Combinatorial Theory, Series A, vol. 111 (2005), no. 2, pp. 310326.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chernikov, A. and Starchenko, S., A note on the erdős-hajnal property for stable graphs . Proceedings of the American Mathematical Society, vol. 146 (2018), no. 2, pp. 785790.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chernikov, A. and Starchenko, S., Regularity lemma for distal structures . Journal of the European Mathematical Society, vol. 20 (2018), no. 10, pp. 24372466.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Choromanski, K., Falik, D., Liebenau, A., Patel, V., and Pilipczuk, M., Excluding Hooks and their complements, preprint, 2015, arXiv:1508.00634.Google Scholar
Chudnovsky, M., Scott, A., Seymour, P., and Spirkl, S., Pure pairs. I. Trees and linear anticomplete pairs . Advances in Mathematics, vol. 375 (2020), p. 107396.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cotter, S. and Starchenko, S., Forking in vc-minimal theories . The Journal of Symbolic Logic, vol. 77 (2012), no. 4, pp. 12571271.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Erdös, P. and Hajnal, A., Ramsey-type theorems . Discrete Applied Mathematics, vol. 25 (1989), nos. 1–2, pp. 3752.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Erdos, P., Hajnal, A., and Pach, J., A ramsey-type theorem for bipartite graphs . Geombinatorics, vol. 10 (2000), no. 2, pp. 6468.Google Scholar
Fox, J., Pach, J., and Suk, A., Erdős–Hajnal conjecture for graphs with bounded vc-dimension . Discrete & Computational Geometry, vol. 61 (2019), no. 4, pp. 809829.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Holly, J. E., Canonical forms for definable subsets of algebraically closed and real closed valued fields . The Journal of Symbolic Logic, vol. 60 (1995), no. 3, pp. 843860.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Malliaris, M. and Shelah, S., Regularity lemmas for stable graphs . Transactions of the American Mathematical Society, vol. 366 (2014), no. 3, pp. 15511585.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nguyen, T., Scott, A., and Seymour, P., Induced subgraph density. vi. Bounded vc-dimension, preprint, 2023, arXiv:2312.15572.Google Scholar
Simon, P., A Guide to NIP Theories, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2015.CrossRefGoogle Scholar