Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-dh8gc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-20T00:35:20.986Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

MORE ON THE PRESERVATION OF LARGE CARDINALS UNDER CLASS FORCING

Part of: Set theory

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  13 September 2021

JOAN BAGARIA
Affiliation:
INSTITUCIÓ CATALANA DE RECERCA I ESTUDIS AVANÇATS (ICREA) BARCELONA, SPAIN and DEPARTAMENT DE MATEMÀTIQUES I INFORMÀTICA UNIVERSITAT DE BARCELONA, GRAN VIA DE LES CORTS CATALANES BARCELONA 585, 08007, SPAIN E-mail: [email protected]
ALEJANDRO POVEDA*
Affiliation:
DEPARTAMENT DE MATEMÀTIQUES I INFORMÀTICA UNIVERSITAT DE BARCELONA, GRAN VIA DE LES CORTS CATALANES BARCELONA 585, 08007, SPAIN Current address: EINSTEIN INSTITUTE OF MATHEMATICS HEBREW UNIVERSITY OF JERUSALEM JERUSALEM 91904, ISRAEL
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

We prove two general results about the preservation of extendible and $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinals under a wide class of forcing iterations (Theorems 5.4 and 7.5). As applications we give new proofs of the preservation of Vopěnka’s Principle and $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinals under Jensen’s iteration for forcing the GCH [17], previously obtained in [8, 27], respectively. We prove that $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinals are preserved by forcing with standard Easton-support iterations for any possible $\Delta _2$ -definable behaviour of the power-set function on regular cardinals. We show that one can force proper class-many disagreements between the universe and HOD with respect to the calculation of successors of regular cardinals, while preserving $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinals. We also show, assuming the GCH, that the class forcing iteration of Cummings–Foreman–Magidor for forcing $\diamondsuit _{\kappa ^+}^+$ at every $\kappa $ [10] preserves $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinals. We give an optimal result on the consistency of weak square principles and $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinals. In the last section prove another preservation result for $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinals under very general (not necessarily definable or weakly homogeneous) class forcing iterations. As applications we prove the consistency of $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinals with $\mathrm {{V}}=\mathrm {{HOD}}$ , and also with $\mathrm {GA}$ (the Ground Axiom) plus $\mathrm {V}\neq \mathrm {HOD}$ , the latter being a strengthening of a result from [14].

Type
Article
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2021. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Association for Symbolic Logic

1 Introduction

The present paper is a contribution to the long-standing program in set theory of studying the robustness of strong large-cardinal notions under forcing extensions. Specifically, we are interested in the section of the large-cardinal hierarchy ranging between extendible cardinals and Vopěnka’s Principle ( $\mathrm {VP}$ ).

In a groundbreaking work, Laver [Reference Laver19] proved that supercompactness, one of the most prominent large-cardinal properties, can be made indestructible under a wide range of forcing notions. Indeed, given a supercompact cardinal $\kappa $ , Laver showed that there is a forcing notion (the Laver preparation) that preserves the supercompactness of $\kappa $ and makes it indestructible under further ${<}\kappa $ -directed closed forcing.

Inspired by the work of Laver, several authors subsequently obtained similar results for other classical large-cardinal notions. For instance, Gitik and Shelah [Reference Gitik and Shelah13] show that a strong cardinal $\kappa $ can be made indestructible under so-called $\kappa ^+$ -weakly closed forcing satisfying the Prikry condition; Hamkins [Reference Hamkins15] uses the lottery preparation forcing to make various types of large cardinals indestructible under appropriate forcing notions. More recently, Brooke-Taylor [Reference Brooke-Taylor8] shows that $\mathrm {VP}$ is indestructible under reverse Easton forcing iterations of increasingly directed-closed forcing notions, without the need for any preparatory forcing. In the present paper we are concerned with the preservation by forcing of $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinals. This family of large cardinals was introduced in [Reference Bagaria, Casacuberta, Mathias and Rosickỳ2] (see also [Reference Bagaria1]) as a strengthening of the classical notion of extendibility and was shown to provide natural milestones on the road from supercompact cardinals up to $\mathrm {VP}$ . Extendible cardinals have experienced a renewed interest after Woodin’s proof of the HOD-Dichotomy [Reference Woodin29]. Also, $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinals have had remarkable applications in category theory and algebraic topology (see [Reference Bagaria, Casacuberta, Mathias and Rosickỳ2]). Thus, the investigation of the preservation of such cardinals under forcing is a worthwhile project, which may lead to further applications.

Recall (see [Reference Bagaria1]) that, for each $n<\omega $ , the class $C^{(n)}$ is the $\Pi _n$ -definable closed unbounded proper class of all ordinals $\alpha $ that are $\Sigma _n$ -correct, i.e., such that $V_\alpha $ is a $\Sigma _n$ -elementary substructure of $\mathrm {V}$ . Also, recall that a cardinal $\kappa $ is $C^{(n)}$ -extendible if for every $\lambda>\kappa $ there is an ordinal $\mu $ and an elementary embedding $j:V_\lambda \to V_\mu $ such that $\mathrm {crit}(j)=\kappa $ , $j(\kappa )>\lambda $ , and $j(\kappa )\in C^{(n)}$ .

It turns out that $\mathrm {VP}(\Pi _{n+1})$ , namely $\mathrm {VP}$ restricted to classes of structures that are $\Pi _{n+1}$ -definable, is equivalent to the existence of a $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinal. Hence $\mathrm {VP}$ is equivalent to the existence of a $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinal for each $n\geq 1$ (see [Reference Bagaria1] for details). It is in this sense that $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinals are canonical representatives of the large-cardinal hierarchy in the region between the first supercompact cardinal and $\mathrm {VP}$ .

In general, the preservation of very large cardinals by forcing is a delicate issue since it imposes strong forms of agreement between the ground model and the generic forcing extension. For example, suppose $\kappa \in C^{(n)}$ is inaccessible and $\mathbb {P}$ is a ${<}\kappa $ -distributive forcing notion. If $\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}}\text {"}\kappa \in \dot {C}^{(n)}\text {"}$ then $V_\kappa \prec _{\Sigma _n} V^{\mathbb {P}}$ . This underlines the fact that the more correct a large cardinal is, the harder it is to preserve its correctness under forcing, and therefore the more fragile it becomes. Indeed, one runs into trouble when seeking a result akin to Laver’s indestructibility for supercompact cardinals for stronger large cardinals such as extendible. This phenomenon was first pointed out by Tsaprounis in his Ph.D. thesis [Reference Tsaprounis26] and it was afterwards extensively studied in [Reference Bagaria, Hamkins, Tsaprounis and Usuba4], where the following theorem illustrates the fragility we just described.

Theorem 1.1 [Reference Bagaria, Hamkins, Tsaprounis and Usuba4].

Suppose that $V_\kappa \prec _{\Sigma _2} V_\lambda $ and $G\subseteq \mathbb {P}$ is a $\mathrm {V}$ -generic filter for nontrivial strategically ${<}\kappa $ -closed forcing $\mathbb {P}\in V_\eta $ , where $\eta \leq \lambda $ . Then for every $\theta \geq \eta $ ,

$$ \begin{align*} V_\kappa=V[G]_\kappa\nprec_{\Sigma_3} V[G]_\theta. \end{align*} $$

In particular, if $\kappa $ is an extendible cardinal and $\mathbb {P}$ is any nontrivial strategically ${<}\kappa $ -closed set forcing notion, then forcing with $\mathbb {P}$ destroys the extendibility of $\kappa $ . Moreover, the theorem implies that there is no hope to obtain indestructibility results for $\Sigma _3$ -correct large cardinals. Thus, if one aims for a general theory of preservation of $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinals one should concentrate on class forcing notions.

The structure of the paper is as follows: In Section 2 we prove that $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinals are uniformly characterizable in a Magidor-like way, i.e., similar to Magidor’s characterization of supercompact cardinals. This reinforces the fact that $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinals are a natural model-theoretic strengthening of supercompactness, first shown in [Reference Bagaria, Casacuberta, Mathias and Rosickỳ2] (see also [Reference Bagaria1]). This characterization of $C^{(n)}$ -extendibility is used in later sections for carrying out preservation arguments under class forcing. The same characterization has been independently given by Boney in [Reference Boney6], and also in [Reference Bagaria, Gitman and Schindler3] for the virtual forms of higher-level analogs of supercompact cardinals (i.e., n-remarkable cardinals) and virtual $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinals.

Section 3 is devoted to the analysis of some reflection properties of class forcing iterations that will be useful in later sections for the study of the preservation of $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinals. Two key notions are that of adequate iteration and $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _k$ -reflecting cardinal. For the same purpose, in Section 4 we introduce the notion of $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _k$ -supercompact cardinal and show how it relates to $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinals.

In Section 5 we define the notion of suitable iteration and prove a general result about the preservation of $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinals under a wide class of $\mathrm {ORD}$ -length forcing iterations (cf. Theorem 5.4). The prize we pay for considering such general iterations is that we just prove that any $C^{(n+1)}$ -extendible cardinal retains its $C^{(n)}$ -extendibility (cf. Corollary 5.14).

Section 6 is focussed on applications of Theorem 5.4. We give a new proof of Brooke-Taylor’s theorem on the preservation of $\mathrm {VP}$ [Reference Brooke-Taylor8]. The main advantage with respect to the original proof is that our technique allows for a finer control over the amount of Vopěnka’s Principle that is preserved.

In Section 7 we concentrate on a more concrete class of forcing iterations we call fitting and improve the results obtained in Section 5. Our main result here is Theorem 7.5. In Section 8 we give several applications of this theorem. First, we show that $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinals are preserved by standard Easton class-forcing iterations for any $\Delta _2$ -definable possible behaviour of the power-set function on regular cardinals. This extends the main result of [Reference Tsaprounis28]. Second, with an eye on Woodin’s HOD Conjecture, we explore briefly the connections between $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinals (and thus also $\mathrm {VP}$ ) with the principle $\mathrm {V}=\mathrm {HOD}$ . In particular, we prove that it is possible to force a complete disagreement, and in many possible forms, between $\mathrm {V}$ and $\mathrm {HOD}$ with respect to the calculation of successors of regular cardinals, while $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinals are preserved. Third, we show that, assuming the GCH, the class forcing iteration of Cummings–Foreman–Magidor that forces $\diamondsuit _{\kappa ^+}^+$ at every $\kappa $ ([Reference Cummings, Foreman and Magidor10]) preserves $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinals. Finally, we prove that $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinals are consistent with $\square _{\lambda ,\mathrm {cof}(\lambda )}$ for a proper class of singular cardinals $\lambda $ . This result is optimal in the sense explained in Section 8.4.

In Section 9, we address the question of the preservation of $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinals under general (non-weakly homogeneous, non-definable) suitable iterations. As applications of our analysis we prove the consistency of $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinals with $\mathrm {V}=\mathrm {HOD}$ , and also with $\mathrm {GA}+\mathrm {V}\neq \mathrm {HOD}$ . This latter is a strengthening of a result of Hamkins, Reitz, and Woodin [Reference Hamkins, Reitz and Woodin14].

2 A Magidor-like characterization of $C^{(n)}$ -extendibility

We shall prove that $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinals (defined in page 6 of the Introduction) can be characterized in a way analogous to the following characterization of supercompact cardinals due to Magidor.Footnote 1

Theorem 2.1 [Reference Magidor21].

For a cardinal $\delta $ , the following statements are equivalent $:$

  1. (1) $\delta $ is a supercompact cardinal.

  2. (2) For every $\lambda>\delta $ in $C^{(1)}$ and for every $a\in V_\lambda $ , there exist ordinals $\bar {\delta }<\bar {\lambda }<\delta $ and there exist some $\bar {a}\in V_{\bar {\lambda }}$ and an elementary embedding $j:V_{\bar {\lambda }}\longrightarrow V_\lambda $ such that $:$

    • $\mathrm {crit}(j)=\bar {\delta }$ and $j(\bar {\delta })=\delta $ .

    • $j(\bar {a})=a$ .

    • ${\bar {\lambda }}\in C^{(1)}$ .

The existence of a supercompact cardinal is thus characterized by a form of reflection for $\Sigma _1$ -correct strata of the universe, for it implies that any $\Sigma _1$ -truth (i.e., any $\Sigma _1$ sentence, with parameters, true in $\mathrm {V}$ ) is captured (up to some change of parameters) by some level below the supercompact cardinal. The following notion generalizes this reflection property to higher levels of complexity.

Definition 2.2 ( $\Sigma _n$ -supercompact cardinal).

Let $n\geq 1$ . A cardinal $\delta $ is said to be $\Sigma _n$ -supercompact if for every $\lambda>\delta $ in $C^{(n)}$ and $a\in V_\lambda $ , there exist $\bar {\delta }<\bar {\lambda }<\delta $ and $\bar {a}\in V_{\bar {\lambda }}$ , and there exists an elementary embedding $j:V_{\bar {\lambda }}\longrightarrow V_\lambda $ such that:

  • $\mathrm {crit}(j)=\bar {\delta }$ and $j(\bar {\delta })=\delta $ .

  • $j(\bar {a})=a$ .

  • ${\bar {\lambda }}\in C^{(n)}$ .

Lemma 2.3. For $n\geq 1$ , every $\Sigma _n$ -supercompact cardinal belongs to the class $C^{(n+1)}$ .

Proof We prove the lemma by induction on $n\geq 1$ . The base case $n=1$ follows by combining Magidor’s theorem (cf. Theorem 2.1) with the well-known fact that supercompact cardinals are $\Sigma _2$ -correct [Reference Kanamori18, Proposition 22.3]. Thus, we shall assume by induction that the lemma holds for n and prove it for $n+1$ .

Let $\delta $ be a $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -supercompact cardinal, and let $\varphi (x,y)$ be a $\Pi _{n+1}$ formula with $a\in V_\delta $ . Suppose first that $V_\delta $ satisfies the sentence $\exists x\varphi (x,a)$ and let $b\in V_\delta $ be a witness for it. Since $\delta $ is $\Sigma _n$ -supercompact, the induction hypothesis guarantees that $\delta \in C^{(n+1)}$ , so that $\varphi (b,a)$ is true.

Conversely, suppose that $\exists x\varphi (x,a)$ is true. Let $\lambda <\delta $ be such that $a\in V_\lambda $ . Let b be a witness for this formula and let $\mu \in C^{(n+2)}\setminus \delta ^+$ be such that $b\in V_\mu $ . Then, $V_\mu \models \exists x\varphi (x,a)$ . By the $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -supercompactness of $\delta $ we may find $\bar {\lambda },\bar {\delta }<\bar {\mu }<\delta $ , $\bar {\mu }\in C^{(n+2)}$ , $\bar {a}\in V_{\overline {\lambda }}$ , and $j:V_{\bar {\mu }}\rightarrow V_\mu $ such that $\mathrm {crit}(j)=\bar {\delta }$ , $j(\bar {\delta })=\delta $ , $j(\bar {\lambda })=\lambda $ , and $j(\bar {a})=a$ . In particular, $V_{\bar {\mu }}\models \exists x\varphi (x,\bar {a})$ . Notice that, by elementarity, $\bar {\lambda }<\bar {\delta }$ , hence $a=j(\bar {a})=\bar {a}$ , and thus $V_{\bar {\mu }}\models \exists x\varphi (x,a)$ . Finally, since $\bar {\mu }<\delta $ and $\bar {\mu }\in C^{(n+2)}$ , our induction hypothesis yields $V_{\bar {\mu }}\prec _{\Sigma _{n+1}}V_\delta $ . From this latter assertion it is clear that $V_\delta \models \exists x\varphi (x,a)$ , as wanted.

Theorem 2.4. For $n\geq 1$ , $\delta $ is a $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinal if and only if $\delta $ is $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -supercompact.

Proof Suppose that $\delta $ is $C^{(n)}$ -extendible. Fix any $\lambda>\delta $ in $C^{(n+1)}$ and $a\in V_\lambda $ . By $C^{(n)}$ -extendibility, let $\mu>\lambda $ in $C^{(n+1)}$ , and let $j: V_\mu \longrightarrow V_\theta $ be such that $\mathrm {crit}(j)=\delta $ , $j(\delta )>\mu $ and $j(\delta )\in C^{(n)}$ , for some ordinal $\theta $ . Notice that $j\upharpoonright V_{\lambda }\in V_\theta $ .

Claim 2.4.1. $V_\theta $ satisfies the following sentence $:$

$$ \begin{align*} \exists \bar{\lambda}<j(\delta)\;\exists \bar{\delta}<\bar{\lambda}\;\exists \bar{a}\in V_{\bar{\lambda}}\;\exists j^*: V_{\bar{\lambda}}\longrightarrow V_{j(\lambda)}\nonumber\\ (j^*(\bar{a})=j(a)\;\wedge\; j^*(\bar{\delta})=j(\delta)\;\wedge\; V_{\bar{\lambda}}\prec_{\Sigma_{n+1}} V_{j(\lambda)}).\nonumber \end{align*} $$

Proof of claim It is sufficient to show that $V_\lambda \prec _{\Sigma _{n+1}} V_{j(\lambda )}$ , for then the claim follows as witnessed by $\lambda $ , $\delta $ , a, and $j\upharpoonright V_\lambda $ .

On the one hand, notice that $V_\delta \prec _{\Sigma _{n+1}} V_\mu $ , because $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinals are $\Sigma _{n+2}$ -correct. By elementarity, this implies $V_{j(\delta )}\prec _{\Sigma _{n+1}} V_{\theta }$ . On the other hand, since $j(\delta )>\mu $ and $j(\delta )\in C^{(n)}$ , it is true that $V_\mu \prec _{\Sigma _{n+1}} V_{j(\delta )}$ and thus $V_\mu \prec _{\Sigma _{n+1}} V_{\theta }$ . In addition, since $\mu $ and $\lambda $ were both $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -correct, it is the case that $V_\lambda \prec _{\Sigma _{n+1}} V_\mu $ . Hence, $V_\lambda \prec _{\Sigma _{n+1}}V_\theta $ . Also, by elementarity, $V_{j(\lambda )}\prec _{\Sigma _{n+1}} V_{\theta }$ . Combining these two facts, we have that $V_\lambda \prec _{\Sigma _{n+1}} V_{j(\lambda )}$ .

By elementarity, $V_\mu $ satisfies the above sentence with the parameters $j(\delta )$ and $j(\lambda )$ replaced by $\delta $ and $\lambda $ , respectively. Hence, since $\mu \in C^{(n+1)}$ , the sentence is true in the universe. Since $\lambda $ was arbitrarily chosen in $C^{(n+1)}$ , this implies that $\delta $ is a $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -supercompact cardinal.

For the converse implication, let $\lambda $ be greater than $\delta $ and let us show that there exists an elementary embedding $j: V_\lambda \longrightarrow V_\theta $ , for some ordinal $\theta $ , such that $\mathrm {crit}(j)=\delta $ , $j(\delta )>\lambda $ , and $j(\delta )\in C^{(n)}$ . Take $\mu>\lambda $ in $C^{(n+1)}$ and let $\bar {\delta },\bar {\lambda }<\bar {\mu }$ and $j:V_{\bar {\mu }}\longrightarrow V_\mu $ be such that $\mathrm {crit}(j)=\bar {\delta }$ , $j(\bar {\delta })=\delta $ , $j(\bar {\lambda })=\lambda $ , and ${\bar {\mu }}\in C^{(n+1)}$ . Now notice that the sentence

(1) $$ \begin{align} \exists \alpha\;\exists j^*: V_{\bar{\lambda}}\longrightarrow V_\alpha\,(\mathrm{crit}(j^*)=\bar{\delta}\;\wedge\; j^*(\bar{\delta})>\bar{\lambda}\;\wedge\; {j^*(\bar{\delta})}\in C^{(n)}) \end{align} $$

is $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -expressible. Moreover, it is true in $\mathrm {V}$ as witnessed by $\lambda $ and j because $j(\bar {\delta })=\delta>\bar {\lambda }$ and $\delta \in C^{(n)}$ (cf. Lemma 2.3). Thus, since $V_{\bar {\mu }}$ is $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -correct and contains $\bar {\delta }$ and $\bar {\lambda }$ , it is also true in $V_{\bar {\mu }}$ . By elementarity, $V_\mu $ thinks that the sentence

$$ \begin{align*} \exists \alpha\;\exists j^*: V_{{\lambda}}\longrightarrow V_\alpha\,(\mathrm{crit}(j^*)={\delta}\;\wedge\; j^*({\delta})>{\lambda}\;\wedge\; {j^*(\delta)}\in C^{(n)}) \end{align*} $$

is true. Since $\mu \in C^{(n+1)}$ , the above displayed sentence is true in $\mathrm {V}$ and so $\delta $ is $\lambda $ - $C^{(n)}$ -extendible. As $\lambda $ was arbitrarily chosen, $\delta $ is a $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinal.

Remark 2.5. For $\lambda \in C^{(n)}$ , a cardinal $\delta $ is called $\lambda $ - $C^{(n)+}$ -extendible if it is $\lambda $ - $C^{(n)}$ -extendible, witnessed by some elementary embedding $j\colon V_\lambda \rightarrow V_\theta $ with $\theta \in C^{(n)}$ . Likewise, $\delta $ is called $C^{(n)+}$ -extendible if it is $\lambda $ - $C^{(n)+}$ -extendible for every $\lambda>\delta $ in $C^{(n)}$ (see [Reference Bagaria1, Section 4]). A close inspection of the preceding argument reveals that $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -supercompactness is actually equivalent to $C^{(n)+}$ -extendibility. This gives an alternative proof of [Reference Tsaprounis28, Corollary 3.5].

Corollary 2.6. A cardinal is extendible if and only if it is $\Sigma _2$ -supercompact.

A close inspection of the proof of Theorem 2.4 shows that the following holds:

Corollary 2.7. For $n\geq 1$ , a cardinal $\delta $ is $C^{(n)}$ -extendible if and only if for a proper class of $\lambda $ in $C^{(n+1)}$ , for every $\alpha < \lambda $ there exist $\bar {\delta }, \bar {\alpha }<{\bar {\lambda }}$ and an elementary embedding $j:V_{\bar {\lambda }}\longrightarrow V_\lambda $ such that $:$

  • $\mathrm {crit}(j)=\bar {\delta }$ and $j(\bar {\delta })=\delta $ .

  • $j(\bar {\alpha })=\alpha $ .

  • ${\bar {\lambda }}\in C^{(n+1)}$ .

In the light of the above results it is natural to define the class of $C^{(0)}$ -extendible cardinals as the class of supercompact cardinals. Note that since every $C^{(n+1)}$ -extendible cardinal is a limit of $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinals (see [Reference Bagaria1]), every $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -supercompact cardinal is a limit of $\Sigma _n$ -supercompact cardinals. It will become apparent in the following sections that the notion of $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -supercompactness is a useful reformulation of $C^{(n)}$ -extendibility in the context of class forcing.

3 Some reflection properties for class forcing iterations

In the sequel we will only work with ORD-length forcing iterations, since extendible cardinals are generally destroyed by set-size ones (see Theorem 1.1 and the related discussion).

If $\mathbb {P}$ is a forcing iteration, and G is $\mathbb {P}$ -generic over V, then for every ordinal $\lambda $ , we denote as customary by $G_\lambda $ the $\mathbb {P}_\lambda $ -generic filter induced by G, i.e., $G_\lambda :=G\cap \mathbb {P}_\lambda $ . Also, as usual we denote by $i_{G_\lambda }(\tau )$ the interpretation of the $\mathbb {P}_\lambda $ -name $\tau $ by the filter $G_\lambda $ .

For the main preservation results given in the following sections we will need to ensure that there are many cardinals $\lambda $ that satisfy $V_\lambda [G_\lambda ]=V[G]_\lambda $ .

Definition 3.1. Let $\mathbb {P}$ be a forcing iteration. A cardinal $\lambda $ is $\mathbb {P}$ -reflecting if $\mathbb {P}$ forces that $V[\dot {G}]_\lambda = V_\lambda [\dot {G}_\lambda ]$ .

Remark 3.2. Note that since the rank of $i_{G_\lambda }(\tau )$ in $V[G_\lambda ]$ is never bigger than the rank of $\tau $ in $\mathrm {V}$ , for any $\tau \in V^{\mathbb {P}_\lambda }$ , we clearly have

$$ \begin{align*}V_\lambda[G_\lambda]\subseteq V[G_\lambda]_\lambda \subseteq V[G]_\lambda.\end{align*} $$

Thus, $\mathbb {P}$ always forces “ $V_\lambda [\dot {G}_\lambda ]\subseteq V[\dot {G}]_\lambda $ .” Hence a cardinal $\lambda $ is $\mathbb {P}$ -reflecting if and only if $\mathbb {P}$ forces “ $V[\dot {G}]_\lambda \subseteq V_\lambda [\dot {G}_\lambda ]$ .”

Proposition 3.3. $K:=\{\lambda \mid \lambda \text { is } \mathbb {P}\text {-reflecting}\}$ is closed.

Proof Let $\kappa $ be an accumulation point of K. Let $p\in \mathbb {P}$ and $\tau \in V^{\mathbb {P}}$ be such that $p\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}}\tau \in V[\dot {G}]_\kappa $ . Since $\kappa $ is a limit cardinal there is $q\leq _{\mathbb {P}} p$ and $\lambda <\kappa $ such that $q\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}} \tau \in V[\dot {G}]_\lambda $ . Extending q if necessary, we may find $\theta \in K\cap \kappa $ above $\lambda $ such that $q\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}}\tau \in V[\dot {G}]_\lambda \subseteq V_\theta [\dot {G}_\theta ]$ . Thus, $\kappa \in K$ , as wanted.

The following proposition gives some sufficient conditions for a cardinal to be $\mathbb {P}$ -reflecting.

Proposition 3.4. Suppose $\lambda $ is an inaccessible cardinal and $\mathbb {P}$ is a forcing iteration such that : $\mathbb {P}_\lambda $ is a $\lambda $ -cc forcing which preserves the inaccessibility of $\lambda $ , $\mathbb {P}_\lambda \subseteq V_\lambda $ , and $\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}_{\lambda }}\text {"}\,\dot {\mathbb {Q}}$ is $\lambda $ -distributive,” where $\mathbb {P}\cong \mathbb {P}_{\lambda }\ast \mathbb {Q}$ . Then $\lambda $ is $\mathbb {P}$ -reflecting.

Proof On the one hand, by induction on the rank and using the fact that $\mathbb {P}_{\lambda }$ is $\lambda $ -cc and preserves the inaccessibility of $\lambda $ , one can easily show that $V[G_\lambda ]_\lambda \subseteq V_{\lambda } [G_\lambda ]$ .

On the other hand, as $\mathbb {P}_\lambda $ preserves the inaccessibility of $\lambda $ , $|V[G_\lambda ]_\lambda |=\lambda $ . Hence, since $\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}_{\lambda }}\text {"}\,\dot {\mathbb {Q}} \text { is } \lambda \text {-distributive},\text {"}$ and so $i_{G_\lambda }(\dot {\mathbb {Q}})$ does not add any new subsets of $V[G_\lambda ]_\lambda $ , we have

$$ \begin{align*} V[G]_\lambda \subseteq V[G_\lambda]_\lambda. \end{align*} $$

Hence, $V[G]_\lambda \subseteq V_\lambda [G_\lambda ]$ .

Let $\mathcal {L}$ denote the language of set theory augmented with an additional unary predicate $\mathbb {P}$ . We will denote by $\Sigma _k^{\mathcal {L}}$ (resp. $\Pi _k^{\mathcal {L}}$ ) the class of $\Sigma _k$ (resp. $\Pi _k$ ) formulae of $\mathcal {L}$ . This choice of language will be useful when working with expressions involving a given iteration $\mathbb {P}$ . For instance, we shall need to compute the complexity of the notion

$$ \begin{align*} \langle V_\alpha,\in,\mathbb{P}\cap V_\alpha\rangle\prec_{\Sigma_{k}^{\mathcal{L}}}\langle V,\in,\mathbb{P}\rangle \end{align*} $$

as a property of $\alpha $ , when $\mathbb {P}$ is a definable ORD-length forcing iteration.

Remark 3.5. For such $\mathbb {P}$ and $\alpha $ , since we are dealing with iterations it would perhaps seem more natural to consider the predicate $\mathbb {P}_\alpha $ instead of $\mathbb {P}\cap V_\alpha $ . However, if $\mathbb {P}_\alpha \subseteq V_\alpha $ (and so $\alpha $ is a limit ordinal and the direct limit is taken at stage $\alpha $ of the iteration), then we have $ \mathbb {P}\cap V_\alpha =\mathbb {P}_\alpha $ .

It is a well-known fact (see, e.g., [Reference Jech16, Section 13]) that the truth predicate (in the language of set theory) for $\Sigma _0$ formulae is $\Delta _1$ definable (i.e., both $\Sigma _1$ and $\Pi _1$ -definable); and in general, the truth predicate for $\Sigma _k$ (resp. $\Pi _k$ ) formulae, for $k\geq 1$ , is $\Sigma _k$ -definable (resp. $\Pi _k$ ). However, if $\mathbb {P}$ is a definable predicate, then the complexity (in the language of set theory) of the truth predicate for formulae in the language $\mathcal {L}$ depends naturally on the complexity of the definition of $\mathbb {P}$ .

Proposition 3.6. If $\mathbb {P}$ is either $\Sigma _m$ or $\Pi _m$ -definable, then the truth predicate $\vDash _{\Sigma _0^{\mathcal {L}}}$ for $\Sigma _0^{\mathcal {L}}$ formulae is $\Delta _{m+1} \ ($ i.e., both $\Sigma _{m+1}$ and $\Pi _{m+1})$ . In general, for $k\geq 1$ , the truth predicate $\vDash _{\Sigma _k^{ \mathcal {L}}}$ for $\Sigma _k^{\mathcal {L}}$ formulae $($ resp. $\vDash _{\Pi _k^{ \mathcal {L}}}$ for $\Pi _{k}^{\mathcal {L}}$ formulae) is $\Sigma _{m +k} \ ($ resp. $\Pi _{m+k})$ . If $\mathbb {P}$ is $\Delta _m$ -definable $($ with $m\geq 1)$ , then $\vDash _{\Sigma _0^{\mathcal {L}}}$ is $\Delta _m$ , and $\vDash _{\Sigma _k^{ \mathcal {L}}} \ ($ resp. $\vDash _{\Pi _k^{ \mathcal {L}}})$ is $\Sigma _{m +k-1} \ ($ resp. $\Pi _{m+k-1})$ .

Proof Note first that the only atomic formulas in the language $\mathcal {L}$ are of the form “ $x\in y$ ,” “ $x=y$ ,” or “ $x\in \mathbb {P}\,,$ ” where x and y are variable symbols. Hence, if $\mathbb {P}$ is $\Sigma _m$ (resp. $\Pi _m$ ) definable, then the formula $\text {"}x \in \mathbb {P}\,\text {"}$ is equivalent to a $\Sigma _m$ (resp. $\Pi _m$ ) formula of the language of set theory. It follows that a Boolean combination of atomic formulas of the language $\mathcal {L}$ is equivalent to a Boolean combination of $\Sigma _m$ and $\Pi _m$ formulas in the language of set theory. Hence, the truth predicate for Boolean combinations of atomic formulas in the language $\mathcal {L}$ is $\Delta _{m+1}$ definable. The same applies to formulas with bounded quantifiers. By induction on k one can now show (as in [Reference Jech16, Section 13]) that $\vDash _{\Sigma _k^{ \mathcal {L}}}$ (resp. $\vDash _{\Pi _k^{ \mathcal {L}}}$ ) is $\Sigma _{m +k}$ (resp. $\Pi _{m+k}$ ) definable.

If $\mathbb {P}$ is $\Delta _m$ -definable, with $m\geq 1$ , then “ $x\in \mathbb {P}$ ” is both $\Sigma _m$ and $\Pi _m$ -expressible. It easily follows that $\vDash _{\Sigma _0^{\mathcal {L}}}$ is $\Delta _m$ -definable, and by induction on k one readily shows that $\vDash _{\Sigma _k^{ \mathcal {L}}}$ (resp. $\vDash _{\Pi _k^{ \mathcal {L}}}$ ) is $\Sigma _{m +k-1}$ (resp. $\Pi _{m+k-1}$ ) definable.

Definition 3.7. For $k\geq 0$ and a predicateFootnote 2 $\mathbb {P}$ , we shall denote by $C^{(k)}_{\mathbb {P}}$ the class of all ordinals $\alpha $ such that

$$ \begin{align*} \langle V_\alpha,\in,\mathbb{P}\cap {V_\alpha}\rangle\prec_{\Sigma_{k}^{\mathcal{L}}}\langle V,\in,\mathbb{P}\rangle. \end{align*} $$

It is easily seen that $C^{(k)}_{\mathbb {P}}$ is a closed unbounded proper class, and $C^{(k+1)}_{\mathbb {P}}\subseteq C^{(k)}_{\mathbb {P}}$ , for each $k\geq 0$ . Notice that $C^{(0)}_{\mathbb {P}}$ is the class of all ordinals. Let us compute next the complexity of $C^{(k)}_{\mathbb {P}}$ , in the language of set theory, when $\mathbb {P}$ is a definable predicate.

Notation 3.8. For $m<\omega $ , we will denote by $\Gamma _m$ (resp. $\mathbf {\Gamma }_m$ ) the collection of all the formulas in the language of set theory that are either $\Sigma _m$ or $\Pi _m$ (resp. with parameters). In the sequel, expressions such as “X is $\Gamma _m$ ” should be read as “X is definable by a formula in $\Gamma _m$ .”

Proposition 3.9. The class $C^{(k)}_{\mathbb {P}}$ is

$$ \begin{align*} \begin{array}{ll} \Pi_{m+k}, & \text{if } k\geq1 \text{ and } \mathbb{P}\text{ is }\Gamma_m,\\ \Pi_{m+k-1},& \text{if } k,m\geq1 \text{ and } \mathbb{P}\text{ is }\Delta_m.\\ \end{array} \end{align*} $$

Proof The class $C^{(0)}_{\mathbb {P}}$ is $\Pi _0$ , being the class of all ordinals. If $k\geq 1$ , then we have that $\alpha \in C^{(k)}_{\mathbb {P}}$ if and only if $\alpha \in C^{(k-1)}_{\mathbb {P}}$ and

$$ \begin{align*}\forall X,Y (X=V_\alpha \wedge Y=\mathbb{P}\cap X \to \forall \bar{a}\in X\,\forall\varphi \in\Sigma^{\mathcal{L}}_k(\,\vDash_{\Sigma_k^{\mathcal{L}}}\varphi(\bar{a})\to\\[-36pt]\end{align*} $$
$$ \begin{align*} \langle X,\in,Y\rangle\vDash \varphi(\bar{a}))). \end{align*} $$

Now using induction on k and Proposition 3.6 the complexity of the class $C^{(k)}_{\mathbb {P}}$ is easily seen to be as desired.

It is well-known that if $\mathbb {P}$ is a set-forcing notion, then for every condition $p\in \mathbb {P}$ , and $\mathbb {P}$ -names $\tau _1,\ldots ,\tau _n$ , if $\varphi (x_1,\ldots ,x_n)$ is a $\Sigma _k$ (resp. $\Pi _k$ ) formula of the language of set theory, with $k\geq 1$ , then the sentence “ $p\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}} \varphi (\tau _1,\ldots ,\tau _n)$ ” is also $\Sigma _k$ (resp. $\Pi _k$ ), in the parameters $\mathbb {P}$ and $\tau _1,\ldots ,\tau _n$ . We shall see next that for definable ${\mathrm {ORD}}$ -length forcing iterations that satisfy some mild conditions the complexity of the forcing relation for $\mathbb {P}$ depends only on the complexity of the definition of $\mathbb {P}$ . Thus, if, e.g., $\mathbb {P}$ is $\Gamma _m$ -definable, then the forcing relation for $\Sigma _k$ formulae is $\Sigma _{m+k}$ -definable (Proposition 3.13).

Definition 3.10. Let $\mathbb {P}$ be a definable ${\mathrm {ORD}}$ -length forcing iteration. Then $\mathbb {P}$ is adequate if there is a sufficiently rich finite fragment $ZFC^*$ of ZFC which allows to define the forcing relation $\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}}$ for $\Delta _0$ -formulae of the language of set theory and proving the Forcing Theorem for such formulae, and there is a proper class of ordinals $\kappa $ such that $V_\kappa \models ZFC^*$ and $\mathbb {P}^{V_\kappa } =\mathbb {P}_\kappa $ (hence also $\mathbb {P}_\kappa =\mathbb {P}\cap V_\kappa $ ).Footnote 3

Although there are examples of definable class forcing notions $\mathbb {P}$ for which the forcing relation $\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}}$ is not definable (see [Reference Lücke, Njegomir, Holy, Krapf and Schlicht20, Section 7]), if $\mathbb {P}$ satisfies certain conditions, e.g., is either pretame (see [Reference Friedman12]), progressively-closed [Reference Reitz23], or suitable (Definition 5.1), then the forcing relation $\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}}$ is definable and the Forcing Theorem holds for $\mathbb {P}$ .

Proposition 3.11. Let $\mathbb {P}$ be adequate and let $ZFC^*$ be a finite fragment of ZFC which is sufficient for defining the forcing relation $\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}}$ for $\Delta _0$ -formulae of the language of set theory and proving the Forcing Theorem for such formulae. Suppose M is a transitive set and $\kappa \in M$ is such that $M_\kappa \models ZFC^\ast $ and $\mathbb {P}^{ M_\kappa } =\mathbb {P}_\kappa $ . Then, for every $\Delta _0$ -formula $\varphi $ of the language of set theory, every $p\in \mathbb {P}$ , and every $\mathbb {P}$ -name $\tau $ such that $p,\tau \in M_\kappa $ ,

$$ \begin{align*} p\Vdash_{\mathbb{P}} \varphi(\tau) \quad \mbox{ iff } \quad M_\kappa \models \text{"}p\Vdash_{\mathbb{P}_\kappa}\varphi(\tau).\text{"}\end{align*} $$

Proof Assume $p\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}} \varphi (\tau )$ . Suppose, for a contradiction, that $q\in \mathbb {P}_\kappa $ is such that $q\leq _{\mathbb {P}_\kappa } p$ and $M_\kappa \models \text {"}q\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}_\kappa } \neg \varphi (\tau ).\text {"}$ Suppose G is $\mathbb {P}$ -generic over V, with $q\in G$ . Then

$$ \begin{align*}V[G]\models \varphi (i_G(\tau)).\end{align*} $$

Note that, since $\mathbb {P}^{M_\kappa } =\mathbb {P}_\kappa $ , a direct limit is taken at $\kappa $ (for otherwise some conditions in $\mathbb {P}_\kappa $ would be proper classes in $M_\kappa $ ), and therefore being a dense subset of $\mathbb {P}_\kappa $ is absolute between M and V. Thus, $G_\kappa :=G\cap \mathbb {P}_\kappa $ is $\mathbb {P}_\kappa $ -generic over $M_\kappa $ . Also, since $\tau \in M_\kappa $ , hence $\tau \in M_\kappa ^{\mathbb {P}_\kappa }$ , $i_{G_\kappa }(\tau )\in M_\kappa [G_\kappa ]$ and $i_G(\tau )=i_{G_\kappa }(\tau )$ . Since $\varphi $ is $\Delta _0$ , hence absolute for transitive classes, $M_\kappa [G_\kappa ] \models \varphi (i_{G_\kappa }(\tau )).$ But as $q\in G_\kappa $ , this contradicts $M_\kappa \models \text {"}q\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}_\kappa }\neg \varphi (\tau ).\text {"}$

A similar argument proves the converse.

Corollary 3.12. Let $\mathbb {P}$ be adequate. Then, for every $\Delta _0$ -formula $\varphi $ , every $p\in \mathbb {P}$ , and every $\mathbb {P}$ -name $\tau $ , the sentence “ $p\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}} \varphi (\tau )$ ” is $:$

  1. (1) $\Delta _{1}^{\mathcal {L}},$

  2. (2) $\Delta _{m+1}$ , if $\mathbb {P}$ is $\Gamma _{m}$ -definable $($ some $m\geq 1)$ ,

  3. (3) $\Delta _{m}$ , if $\mathbb {P}$ is $\Delta _{m}$ -definable $($ some $m\geq 1)$ ,

with p and $\tau $ as parameters.

Proof The proof of Proposition 3.11 shows that “ $p\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}} \varphi (\tau )$ ” holds if and only if

$$ \begin{align*} \forall M \, \forall \kappa ( M \mbox{ is a transitive set } \wedge \kappa \in M \wedge M_\kappa\models ZFC^\ast \wedge \mathbb{P}^{M_\kappa} =\mathbb{P}_\kappa \, \wedge \\[-36pt]\end{align*} $$
$$ \begin{align*}p,\tau \in M_\kappa \to M_\kappa \models \text{"}p\Vdash_{\mathbb{P}_\kappa}\varphi(\tau)\text{"})\end{align*} $$

and also if and only if

$$ \begin{align*} \exists M \exists \kappa (M \mbox{ is a transitive set } \wedge \kappa \in M \wedge M_\kappa\models ZFC^\ast \wedge \mathbb{P}^{M_\kappa} =\mathbb{P}_\kappa \, \wedge \\[-36pt]\end{align*} $$
$$ \begin{align*} p,\tau \in M_\kappa \wedge M_\kappa \models \text{"}p\Vdash_{\mathbb{P}_\kappa}\varphi(\tau)\text{"}). \end{align*} $$

Now the two displayed sentences above are easily seen to be $\Pi _1^{\mathcal {L}}$ and $\Sigma _1^{\mathcal {L}}$ , respectively, with p and $\tau $ as parameters.

Items (2) and (3) now follow easily from (1) and Proposition 3.6.

Proposition 3.13. Let $\mathbb {P}$ be adequate. Let $k\geq 1$ . Then, for every $\Sigma _k \ ($ resp. $\Pi _k)$ formula $\varphi (t)$ of the language of set theory, every $p\in \mathbb {P}$ , and every $\mathbb {P}$ -name $\tau $ , the sentence $\text {"}p\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}} \varphi (\tau )\text {"}$ is $:$

  1. (1) $\Sigma _{k}^{\mathcal {L}} \ ($ resp. $\Pi _{k}^{\mathcal {L}}).$

  2. (2) $\Sigma _{ m+k} \ ($ resp. $\Pi _{m+k})$ , if $\mathbb {P}$ is $\Gamma _{m}$ -definable $($ some $m\geq 1).$

  3. (3) $\Sigma _{ m+k-1} \ ($ resp. $\Pi _{m+k-1})$ , if $\mathbb {P}$ is $\Delta _{m}$ -definable $($ some $m\geq 1)$ .

Proof First, note that the class $V^{\mathbb {P}}$ of $\mathbb {P}$ -names is $\Delta _{1}^{\mathcal {L}}$ . Now given a $\Sigma _k$ formula $\exists x \forall y \exists z \ldots \psi (x,y,z,\ldots ,t)$ of the language of set theory, and given a condition $p\in \mathbb {P}$ and $\tau \in V^{\mathbb {P}}$ ,

$$ \begin{align*}p\Vdash_{\mathbb{P}} \exists x \forall y \exists z \ldots \psi (x,y,z,\ldots ,\tau)\end{align*} $$

if and only if

$$ \begin{align*}\exists \sigma (\sigma \in V^{\mathbb{P}} \wedge \forall \sigma' (\sigma'\in V^{\mathbb{P}} \to \exists \sigma"(\sigma"\in V^{\mathbb{P}} \wedge \ldots p\Vdash_{\mathbb{P}} \psi (\sigma ,\sigma ', \sigma", \tau)))).\end{align*} $$

Since $p\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}} \psi (\sigma ,\sigma ', \sigma ", \tau )$ is $\Delta _1^{\mathcal {L}}$ (Corollary 3.12), the last displayed sentence is $\Sigma _{k}^{\mathcal {L}}$ , as wanted.

Items (2) and (3) follow easily from (1) and Proposition 3.6.

Let us compute next the complexity of the notion of $\mathbb {P}$ -reflecting cardinal, for adequate $\mathbb {P}$ .

Proposition 3.14. Let $\mathbb {P}$ be adequate. Then the sentence “ $\kappa $ is a $\mathbb {P}$ -reflecting cardinal” is $:$

  1. (1) $\Pi _{2}^{\mathcal {L}}$ , with $\kappa $ as a parameter.

  2. (2) $\Pi _{m+2}$ , if $\mathbb {P}$ is $\Gamma _m$ -definable, with $m\geq 1$ .

  3. (3) $\Pi _{m+1 }$ , if $\mathbb {P}$ is $\Delta _m$ -definable, with $m\geq 1$ .

Proof Note that $\mathbb {P}$ forces $V[\dot {G}]_\kappa \subseteq V_\kappa [\dot {G}_\kappa ]$ if and only if the $\mathcal {L}$ -sentence

$$ \begin{align*} \forall p, \tau \,(\tau \in V^{\mathbb{P}} \wedge p\Vdash_{\mathbb{P}}\text{"}rk(\tau)<\kappa\text{"}\to \\[-36pt]\end{align*} $$
$$ \begin{align*} \exists \sigma, q\, (\sigma \in V^{\mathbb{P}}\wedge q\leq p\wedge rk(\sigma)<\kappa\wedge q\Vdash_{\mathbb{P}}\text{"}\sigma=\tau\text{"})) \end{align*} $$

holds in $\langle V,\in ,\mathbb {P}\rangle $ . Thus, since $V^{\mathbb {P}}$ is a $\Delta _1^{\mathcal {L}}$ -definable class, and the expressions “ $p\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}} rk(\tau )<\kappa $ ” and “ $q\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}}\sigma =\tau $ ” are also $\Delta _1^{\mathcal {L}}$ (Corollary 3.12), it is easily seen that the sentence “ $\kappa $ is a $\mathbb {P}$ -reflecting cardinal” is $\Pi _{2}^{\mathcal {L}}$ , with $\kappa $ as an additional parameter.

Items (2) and (3) follow easily from (1) using Proposition 3.6.

Let us consider, for the sake of conciseness, the following strengthening of the notion of $\mathbb {P}$ -reflecting cardinal (cf. Definition 3.1).

Definition 3.15. If $k\geq 1$ and $\mathbb {P}$ is an ${\mathrm {ORD}}$ -length forcing iteration, then a cardinal $\kappa $ is $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _k$ -reflecting if it is $\mathbb {P}$ -reflecting, belongs to $C^{(k)}_{\mathbb {P}}$ , and $\mathbb {P}\cap V_\kappa =\mathbb {P}_\kappa $ .

The next lemma will be crucial in future arguments.

Lemma 3.16. Suppose $\mathbb {P}$ is adequate. Then for every $k\geq 0$ , if $\kappa $ is $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _k$ -reflecting and $V_\kappa \models ZFC^*$ , then $\mathbb {P}$ forces $V[\dot {G}]_\kappa \prec _{\Sigma _k} V[\dot {G}]$ .

Proof The claim is clear for $k=0$ . So, assume inductively that $\mathbb {P}$ forces $V[\dot {G}]_\kappa \prec _{\Sigma _{k-1}} V[\dot {G}]$ . Notice that, as $\kappa $ is $\mathbb {P}$ -reflecting, any member of $V[\dot {G}]_\kappa $ is given by a $\mathbb {P}$ -name in $V_\kappa $ . Let $\varphi ({x})$ be a $\Sigma _k$ formula in the language of set theory and let $\tau \in V_\kappa $ be a $\mathbb {P}_\kappa $ -name such that $p\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}}\varphi (\tau )$ , for some $p\in \mathbb {P}$ . We only need to show that $p\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}} \text {"}V[\dot {G}]_\kappa \models \varphi (\tau ).\text {"}$

Claim 3.16.1. The set of conditions $q\in \mathbb {P}_\kappa $ such that $q\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}}\varphi (\tau )$ is dense below $p\restriction \kappa $ .

Proof of claim Suppose, aiming for a contradiction, that $p' \leq _{\mathbb {P}_\kappa } p\restriction \kappa $ is such that $q\not \Vdash _{\mathbb {P}}\varphi (\tau )$ , for all $q\leq _{\mathbb {P}_\kappa } p'$ . Since $\langle V_\kappa ,\in ,\mathbb {P}_\kappa \rangle \prec _{\Sigma _k}\langle V,\in ,\mathbb {P}\rangle $ , and for every $q\in \mathbb {P}_\kappa $ the sentence “ $q \not \Vdash _{\mathbb {P}} \varphi (\tau )$ ” is $\Pi _{k}^{\mathcal {L}}$ (Proposition 3.13), we have that “ $q\not \Vdash _{\mathbb {P}_\kappa } \varphi (\tau )$ ” holds in $\langle V_\kappa ,\in , \mathbb {P}_\kappa \rangle $ . Therefore,

$$ \begin{align*} \langle V_\kappa ,\in , \mathbb{P}_\kappa\rangle\models \text{"}p' \Vdash_{\mathbb{P}_\kappa} \neg \varphi(\tau).\text{"} \end{align*} $$

Again, since $\langle V_\kappa ,\in ,\mathbb {P}_\kappa \rangle \prec _{\Sigma _{k}}\langle V,\in ,\mathbb {P}\rangle $ , and the quoted displayed sentence is $\Pi _{k}^{\mathcal {L}}$ ,

$$ \begin{align*} \langle V,\in, \mathbb{P}\rangle \models \text{"}p' \Vdash_{\mathbb{P}} \neg \varphi(\tau),\text{"} \end{align*} $$

which yields the desired contradiction to the fact that $p\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}}\varphi (\tau )$ .

By the claim, $p\restriction \kappa \Vdash _{\mathbb {P}}\varphi (\tau )$ , and since $\langle V_\kappa ,\in ,\mathbb {P}_\kappa \rangle \prec _{\Sigma _{k}}\langle V,\in ,\mathbb {P}\rangle $ and the above sentence is $\Sigma ^{\mathcal {L}}_{k}$ we have

$$ \begin{align*} \langle V_\kappa,\in,\mathbb{P}_\kappa\rangle\vDash \text{"}p\restriction \kappa \Vdash_{\mathbb{P}_\kappa}\varphi (\tau).\text{"} \end{align*} $$

Thus, if G is $\mathbb {P}$ -generic over V, with $p\in G$ , then $V_\kappa [G_\kappa ]\models \varphi (i_{G_\kappa }(\tau ))$ . Hence, since $i_{G_\kappa }(\tau )=i_G(\tau )$ , and $\kappa $ is $\mathbb {P}$ -reflecting, $V[G]_\kappa \models \varphi (i_G(\tau ))$ , as wanted.

For future use, let us calculate the complexity of the predicate “ $\kappa $ is a $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _k$ -reflecting cardinal” for definable forcing iterations.

Proposition 3.17. Let $\mathbb {P}$ be adequate. Then the predicate “ $\kappa $ is $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _k$ -reflecting” is $:$

$$ \begin{align*} \begin{array}{ll} \Pi_{m+2}, & \text{ if } k=1 \text{ and } \mathbb{P} \text{ is } \Gamma_m.\\ \Pi_{m+k}, & \text{ if } k>1 \text{ and } \mathbb{P} \text{ is } \Gamma_m.\\ \Pi_{m+1}, & \text{ if } k=1 \text{ and } \mathbb{P} \text{ is } \Delta_m.\\ \Pi_{m+k-1},& \text{ if } k>1 \text{ and } \mathbb{P} \text{ is } \Delta_m. \end{array} \end{align*} $$

Proof First, the assertion “ $\mathbb {P}\cap V_\kappa =\mathbb {P}_\kappa $ ” is $\Pi _{m+1}$ (in the parameter $\kappa $ ) if $\mathbb {P}$ is $\Pi _m$ -definable, and $\Pi _m$ if $\mathbb {P}$ is $\Sigma _m$ -definable. For the quoted sentence holds if and only if:

$$ \begin{align*}\forall x (x\in \mathbb{P} \to ({\mathrm{rk}}(x)<\kappa \leftrightarrow {\mathrm{lh}}(x)<\kappa)).\end{align*} $$

Second, by Proposition 3.14, the sentence “ $\kappa $ is a $\mathbb {P}$ -reflecting cardinal” is $\Pi _{m+2}$ if $\mathbb {P}$ is $\Gamma _m$ -definable; and it is $\Pi _{m+1}$ if $\mathbb {P}$ is $\Delta _m$ -definable. Finally, as shown in Proposition 3.9, for $k\geq 0$ the class $C^{(k)}_{\mathbb {P}}$ is $\Pi _{m+k}$ if $\mathbb {P}$ is $\Pi _m$ or $\Sigma _m$ -definable; and it is $\Pi _{m+k-1}$ if $\mathbb {P}$ is $\Delta _m$ -definable.

An easy calculation now shows that the predicate “ $\kappa $ is a $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _k$ -reflecting cardinal” has the claimed complexity.

4 $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _n$ -supercompactness

The following definition gives a refinement of the notion of $\Sigma _n$ -supercompact cardinal, relative to definable iterations.

Definition 4.1 ( $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _n$ -supercompactness).

If $n\geq 1$ and $\mathbb {P}$ is an ${\mathrm {ORD}}$ -length forcing iteration, then a cardinal $\delta $ is $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _n$ -supercompact if there exists a proper class of $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _n$ -reflecting cardinals, and for every such cardinal $\lambda>\delta $ and every $a\in V_\lambda $ there exist $\bar {\delta }<\bar {\lambda }<\delta $ and $\bar {a}\in V_{\bar {\lambda }}$ , together with an elementary embedding $j: V_{\bar {\lambda }}\longrightarrow V_\lambda $ such that:

  1. (i) $\mathrm {crit}(j)=\bar {\delta }$ and $j(\bar {\delta })=\delta $ .

  2. (ii) $j(\bar {a})=a$ .

  3. (iii) $\bar {\lambda }$ is $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _n$ -reflecting.

The next proposition and corollary unveil the connection between the notions of $\Sigma _n$ -supercompact and $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _n$ -supercompact cardinals. For conciseness, let us denote by $\mathcal {S}^{\Sigma _n}$ , $\mathcal {S}^{\Sigma _n}_{\mathbb {P}}$ , and $\mathcal {E}^{(n)}$ the classes of $\Sigma _n$ -supercompact, $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _n$ -supercompact, and $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinals, respectively.

Proposition 4.2. Let $\mathbb {P}$ be an ${\mathrm {ORD}}$ -length forcing iteration, and suppose there is a proper class of $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _n$ -reflecting cardinals. Then,

  1. (1) $\mathcal {S}^{\Sigma _{n}}_{\mathbb {P}}\subseteq \mathcal {S}^{\Sigma _{n}}$ .

  2. (2) If $\mathbb {P}$ is adequate and $\Delta _2$ -definable, then $\mathcal {S}^{\Sigma _{3}}\subseteq \mathcal {S}^{\Sigma _1}_{\mathbb {P}}$ .

  3. (3) If $\mathbb {P}$ is adequate and $\Delta _{m+1}$ -definable, some $m\geq 1$ , and either m or n are greater than $1$ , then $\mathcal {S}^{\Sigma _{m+n}}\subseteq \mathcal {S}^{\Sigma _n}_{\mathbb {P}}$ .

In particular, if $\mathbb {P}$ is adequate and $\Delta _2$ , then every $\Sigma _2$ -supercompact cardinal is $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _1$ -supercompact $;$ and for every $n>1$ , a cardinal is $\Sigma _{n}$ -supercompact if and only if it is $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _{n}$ -supercompact.

Proof (1): Assume $\delta $ is $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _{n}$ -supercompact. Let $\lambda>\delta $ be a $\Sigma _{n}$ -correct cardinal and let $a\in V_\lambda $ . Let $\kappa>\lambda $ be a $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _n$ -reflecting cardinal. Notice that $V_\kappa \vDash \text {"}\lambda \in C^{(n)}.\text {"}$ By $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _n$ -supercompactness, there are $\bar {\delta } < \bar {\kappa }<\delta $ , with $\bar {\kappa }$ being $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _n$ -reflecting, and there are $\bar {a}\in V_{\bar {\kappa }}$ and $\bar {\lambda } <\bar {\kappa }$ , together with an elementary embedding $j:V_{\bar {\kappa }}\longrightarrow V_\kappa $ such that $\mathrm {crit}(j)=\bar {\delta } \ j(\bar {\delta })=\delta $ , $j(\bar {a})=a$ , and $j(\bar {\lambda })=\lambda $ . By elementarity, $V_{\bar {\kappa }}$ thinks that $\bar {\lambda }$ is a $\Sigma _{n}$ -correct cardinal. Since $\bar {\kappa }\in C^{(n)}$ , it follows that $\bar {\lambda }\in C^{(n)}$ .

(2) and (3): Assume $\delta $ is $\Sigma _3$ -supercompact (in case (2), i.e., $m=n=1$ ) or $\Sigma _{m+n}$ -supercompact, in case (3). Let $\lambda>\delta $ be $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _{n}$ -reflecting, and let $\kappa>\lambda $ be a $\Sigma _{m+n}$ -correct cardinal. Since being a $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _{n}$ -reflecting cardinal is a $\Pi _{3}$ property (case (2)), and a $\Pi _{m+n}$ property otherwise (case (3)), $V_\kappa $ thinks that $\lambda $ is $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _{n}$ -reflecting (cf. Proposition 3.17). By our assumption, there exist $\bar {\delta }<\bar {\lambda }<\bar {\kappa }<\delta $ with $\bar {\kappa }\in C^{(3)}$ (case (2)), or $\bar {\kappa }\in C^{(m+n)}$ , otherwise, and there exists an elementary embedding $j:V_{\bar {\kappa }}\longrightarrow V_\kappa $ such that $\mathrm {crit}(j)=\bar {\delta }$ , $j(\bar {\delta })=\delta $ , and $j(\bar {\lambda })=\lambda $ . By elementarity, $V_{\bar {\kappa }}$ thinks that $\bar {\lambda }$ is $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _{n}$ -reflecting. Since $V_{\bar {\kappa }}\prec _{\Sigma _{3}}V$ (case (2)), or $V_{\bar {\kappa }}\prec _{\Sigma _{m+n}}V$ , otherwise, $\bar {\lambda }$ is $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _{n}$ -reflecting in $\mathrm {V}$ . Thus, the restriction $j\upharpoonright V_{\bar {\lambda }}$ witnesses the $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _n$ -supercompactness of $\delta $ .

The proposition above together with Theorem 2.4 yields the following:

Corollary 4.3. Suppose $\mathbb {P}$ is an ${\mathrm {ORD}}$ -length forcing iteration and there is a proper class of $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -reflecting cardinals. Then,

  1. (1) $\mathcal {S}^{\Sigma _{n+1}}_{\mathbb {P}}\subseteq \mathcal {E}^{(n)}$ .

  2. (2) If $\mathbb {P}$ is adequate and $\Delta _{m+1}$ -definable, some $m\geq 1$ , then $\mathcal {E}^{(m+n)}\subseteq \mathcal {S}^{\Sigma _{n+1}}_{\mathbb {P}}$ .

In particular, if $\mathbb {P}$ is adequate and $\Delta _{2}$ -definable, then for every $n\geq 1$ , every $C^{(n+1)}$ -extendible is $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -supercompact.

5 Suitable iterations

The following is a property enjoyed by many well-known ORD-length forcing iterations, such as Jensen’s canonical class forcing for obtaining the global GCH [Reference Jensen17], or the McAloon class-forcing iteration for forcing $\mathrm {V=HOD}$ [Reference McAloon22]. The property will be needed to prove a general result (Theorem 5.4) about the preservation of $C^{(n)}$ -extendibility.

Definition 5.1 (Suitable iterations).

An ${\mathrm {ORD}}$ -length forcing iteration $\mathbb {P}$ is suitable if it is the direct limit of an Easton support iterationFootnote 4 $\langle \langle \mathbb {P}_\alpha :\,\alpha \in {\mathrm {ORD}}\rangle ,\,\langle \dot {\mathbb {Q}}_\alpha :\,\alpha \in {\mathrm {ORD}}\rangle \rangle $ with the property that for each $\lambda \in {\mathrm {ORD}}$ there is some $\theta \in {\mathrm {ORD}}$ greater than $\lambda $ such that

$$ \begin{align*} \Vdash_{\mathbb{P}_\nu} \text{"}\,\dot{\mathbb{Q}}_{\nu} \text{ is } \lambda\text{-directed closed}\,\text{"} \end{align*} $$

for all $\nu \geq \theta $ .

It is well-known that for suitable $\mathrm {ORD}$ -length forcing iterations $\mathbb {P}$ , the forcing relation $\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}}$ is definable, the forcing theorem holds, and forcing with $\mathbb {P}$ preserves ZFC (see [Reference Friedman12] or [Reference Reitz23]). The condition of eventual $\lambda $ -directed closedness in the definition above can be strengthened on a club proper class. Namely,

Proposition 5.2. Let $\mathbb {P}$ be a suitable iteration. The class

$$ \begin{align*} C(\mathbb{P}):=\{\lambda: \forall\eta\geq\lambda, \Vdash_{\mathbb{P}_{\eta}} \text{"}\dot{\mathbb{Q}}_{\eta} \text{ is } \lambda\text{-directed closed"}\} \end{align*} $$

is a club class.

Proof Closedness is obvious. As for unboundedness, fix any $\lambda $ and build inductively a sequence $\{\theta _n\}_{n\in \omega }$ of ordinals greater than $\lambda $ such that for all $\eta \geq \theta _{n+1}$ ,

$$ \begin{align*} \Vdash_{\mathbb{P}_{\eta}}\text{"}\dot{\mathbb{Q}}_{\eta} \text{ is } \theta_n\text{-directed closed."} \end{align*} $$

Notice now that $\theta ^*:=\sup _n\theta _n$ is an element of C.

The next theorem establishes some sufficient conditions for the preservation of $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinals under definable iterations. Recall that a partial ordering $\mathbb {P}$ is weakly homogeneous if for any $p,q\in \mathbb {P}$ there is an automorphism $\pi $ of $\mathbb {P}$ such that $\pi (p)$ and q are compatible.

In the case of definable ORD-length forcing iterations we define weak homogeneity as follows:

Definition 5.3. A $\Gamma _m$ -definable ORD-length forcing iteration $\mathbb {P}$ is weakly homogeneous if there exists a $\Gamma _m$ formula $\varphi (x,y, z_1, z_2, z_3)$ such that for every $\alpha $ , $\mathbb {P}_\alpha $ forces that for every $\dot {p},\dot {q}\in \dot {\mathbb {Q}}_{\alpha }$ , $\varphi (x,y, \dot {p},\dot {q},\alpha )$ defines an automorphism $\pi $ of $\dot {\mathbb {Q}}_{\alpha }$ such that $\pi (\dot {p})$ and $\dot {q}$ are compatible.

Let us note that if $\mathbb {P}$ is a weakly homogeneous $\Gamma _m$ -definable iteration, and $\lambda $ is $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Gamma _m$ -reflecting, then $\mathbb {P}_\lambda $ is also a weakly homogeneous iteration in $V_\lambda $ , with the same formula witnessing it. Also notice that, for every $\alpha $ , $\mathbb {P}_\alpha $ forces that the remaining part of the iteration is weakly homogeneous. Indeed, in $V^{\mathbb {P}_\alpha }$ , for every $p,q\in \mathbb {P}_{[\alpha , {\mathrm {ORD}})}$ , the map $\pi $ given by: $\pi (x)=y$ iff for all $\beta>0$ ,

$$ \begin{align*} \Vdash_{\mathbb{P}_{ [ \alpha , \alpha +\beta)}}\text{"}\varphi (x(\beta), y(\beta), p(\beta), q(\beta), \beta)\text{"} \end{align*} $$

is a definable automorphism of $\dot {\mathbb {P}}_{[\alpha , {\mathrm {ORD}})}$ (with parameters $\dot {p}$ and $\dot {q}$ ) such that forces $\pi (\dot {p})$ and $\dot {q}$ to be compatible.

Theorem 5.4. Let $m,n\geq 1$ and $m\leq n$ . Let $\mathbb {P}$ be an adequate $\Delta _{m+1}$ -definable and weakly homogeneous suitable iteration. Suppose there is a proper class of $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -reflecting cardinals. If $\delta $ is a $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -supercompact cardinal, then

$$ \begin{align*} \Vdash_{\mathbb{P}} \text{"}\delta \text{ is } C^{(n)}\text{-extendible."} \end{align*} $$

Proof Suppose G is $\mathbb {P}$ -generic over $\mathrm {V}$ . By Corollary 2.7 and Lemma 3.16, it is sufficient to take an arbitrary $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -reflecting cardinal $\lambda>\delta $ and any $\alpha <\lambda $ , and find a $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -reflecting cardinal $\bar {\lambda }$ , ordinals $\bar {\delta }, \bar {\alpha }<\bar {\lambda }$ , and an elementary embedding $j: V[G]_{\bar {\lambda }}\longrightarrow V[G]_\lambda $ such that $\mathrm {crit}(j)=\bar {\delta }$ , $j(\bar {\delta })=\delta $ , and $j(\bar {\alpha })=\alpha $ .

So pick a $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -reflecting cardinal $\lambda>\delta $ and any $\alpha <\lambda $ . Since $\delta $ is $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -supercompact there exist $\bar {\delta }<\bar {\lambda }< \delta $ and $\bar {\alpha }<\bar {\lambda }$ , together with an elementary embedding $j: V_{\bar {\lambda }}\longrightarrow V_{\lambda }$ such that $:$

  1. (i) $\mathrm {crit}(j)=\bar {\delta }$ and $j(\bar {\delta })=\delta $ .

  2. (ii) $j(\bar {\alpha })=\alpha $ .

  3. (iii) $\bar {\lambda }$ is $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -reflecting.

It will then suffice to show that j can be lifted to an elementary embedding $j:V_{\bar {\lambda }}[G_{\bar {\lambda }}]\longrightarrow V_\lambda [G_\lambda ]$ , for then, since both $\lambda $ and $\bar {\lambda }$ are $\mathbb {P}$ -reflecting, we have that $V_\lambda [G_\lambda ]=V[G]_\lambda $ and $V_{\bar {\lambda }}[G_{\bar {\lambda }}]=V[G]_{\bar {\lambda }}$ .

The iterations $\mathbb {P}_{\bar {\lambda }}$ and $\mathbb {P}_{{\lambda }}$ factorize as follows:

  1. (i) $\mathbb {P}_{\bar {\lambda }}\cong \mathbb {P}_{\bar {\delta }}\ast \mathbb {Q}$ with $|\mathbb {Q}|\leq \bar {\lambda }$ .

  2. (ii) $\mathbb {P}_{{\lambda }}\cong \mathbb {P}_{{\delta }}\ast \mathbb {Q}^*$ with

    $$ \begin{align*} \Vdash_{\mathbb{P}_{\delta}} \text{"}\mathbb{Q}^* \text{ is weakly homogeneous and } \delta\text{-directed closed."} \end{align*} $$

Indeed, (i) is clear since $\bar {\lambda }$ is a $\beth $ -fixed point. For (ii), since $\mathbb {P}$ is weakly homogeneous and $\lambda $ is $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -reflecting, $\mathbb {P}_\lambda $ is weakly homogeneous in $V_\lambda $ , and therefore $\mathbb {P}_\delta $ forces that $\mathbb {Q}^\ast $ is weakly homogeneous. Thus, we only need to see that $\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}_{\delta }}$ $\mathbb {Q}^*$ is $\delta $ -directed closed.”

Recall from Proposition 5.2 that the class

$$ \begin{align*} C(\mathbb{P}):=\{\mu : \forall\eta\geq\mu,\, \Vdash_{\mathbb{P}_\eta}\text{"} \dot{\mathbb{Q}}_{\eta} \text{ is } \mu\text{-directed closed"}\} \end{align*} $$

is a club class. Thus, it will be sufficient to show that $\delta $ is a limit point of $C(\mathbb {P})$ , and therefore it belongs to $C(\mathbb {P})$ . So, let $\mu <\delta $ and notice that since $\mathbb {P}$ is a suitable iteration, the sentence $\varphi (\mu )$ asserting:

$$ \begin{align*} \exists \theta>\mu\, \forall\eta\geq\theta \; ( \; \Vdash_{\mathbb{P}_\eta}\text{"}\dot{\mathbb{Q}}_\eta \text{ is } \mu\text{-directed closed"})\end{align*} $$

holds in $\mathrm {V}$ . Since $\mathbb {P}$ is $\Delta _{m+1}$ -definable, $\varphi (\mu )$ is easily seen to be equivalent to the $\Sigma _{m+2}$ sentence

$$ \begin{align*} \exists \theta>\mu \, \forall\eta\geq \theta\, \forall \alpha >\eta \, (\alpha \in C^{(m)}\to \\[-36pt]\end{align*} $$
$$ \begin{align*} V_\alpha\vDash \text{"}\Vdash_{\mathbb{P}_\eta}`\,\dot{\mathbb{Q}}_\eta \text{ is } \mu\text{-directed closed}\, ' \text{"}). \end{align*} $$

Since $\delta $ is a $\Sigma _{n+2}$ -correct cardinal (by Lemma 2.3 and Proposition 4.2), and $m\leq n$ , there must be a witness for $\varphi (\mu )$ below $\delta $ . Arguing inductively, we define an $\omega $ -sequence of ordinals above $\mu $ with limit in $C(\mathbb {P})$ . This shows that $C(\mathbb {P})$ is unbounded in $\delta $ , as wanted.

Since $\delta \in C^{(n+2)}$ , and j is elementary with $j(\bar {\delta })=\delta $ , we have that $j(\mathbb {P}_{\bar {\delta }})=\mathbb {P}_\delta $ . Also, since $\bar {\delta }$ is the critical point of j, we have that $j\text {"}G_{\bar {\delta }}=G_{\bar {\delta }} \subseteq G_\delta $ , and so $j\restriction V_{\bar {\lambda }}$ can be lifted to an elementary embedding

$$ \begin{align*} j:V_{\bar{\lambda}}[G_{\bar{\delta}}]\longrightarrow V_{\lambda}[G_\delta]. \end{align*} $$

Let us denote by $G_{[\bar {\delta },\bar {\lambda })}$ and $G_{[{\delta },{\lambda })}$ the filters $G\cap \mathbb {Q}$ and $G\cap \mathbb {Q}^*$ , respectively. Notice that these filters are generic for $\mathbb {Q}$ and $\mathbb {Q}^*$ over $V_{\bar {\lambda }}[G_{\bar {\delta }}]$ and $V_{\lambda }[G_\delta ]$ , respectively. In order to lift the embedding j to the further generic extension $V_{\bar {\lambda }}[G_{\bar {\lambda }}]=V_{\bar {\lambda }}[G_{\bar {\delta }}][G_{[\bar {\delta },\bar {\lambda })}]$ , notice first that $j"G_{[\bar {\delta },\bar {\lambda })}$ is a directed subset of $\mathbb {Q}^\ast $ of cardinality $\leq \bar {\lambda }$ . Also, since $j\upharpoonright V_{\bar {\lambda }}\in V_\lambda [G_\delta ]$ , and $j"G_{[\bar {\delta },\bar {\lambda })}$ can be computed from $j\upharpoonright V_{\bar {\lambda }}$ and $G_{[\bar {\delta },\bar {\lambda })}$ , we have that $j"G_{[\bar {\delta },\bar {\lambda })}\in V_\lambda [G_\delta ]$ . Therefore, since $\mathbb {Q}^*$ is a $\delta $ -directed closed forcing notion in $V_{\lambda }[G_\delta ]$ , there is some condition $p\in \mathbb {Q}^*$ such that $p\leq q$ , for every $q\in j"G_{[\bar {\delta },\bar {\lambda })}$ . Thus, p is a master condition in $\mathbb {Q}^*$ for the embedding j and the generic filter $G_{[\bar {\delta },\bar {\lambda })}$ . So, if $H\subseteq \mathbb {Q}^*$ is a generic filter over $V_{\lambda }[G_\delta ]$ containing p, then j can be lifted to an elementary embedding

$$ \begin{align*} j: V_{\bar{\lambda}}[G_{\bar{\lambda}}]\longrightarrow V_{\lambda}[G_\delta\ast H]. \end{align*} $$

Claim 5.4.1. In $V[G]$ there exists some generic filter $H\subseteq \mathbb {Q}^*$ over $V_{\lambda }[G_\delta ]$ containing p such that $V_{\lambda }[G_\delta \ast H]=V_{\lambda }[G_\lambda ]$ .

Proof of claim By (ii) above, $\mathbb {Q}^*$ is a weakly homogeneous class forcing in $V_{\lambda }[G_\delta ]$ . Thus, the set of conditions $r\in \mathbb {Q}^*$ for which there is an automorphism $\pi $ of $\mathbb {Q}^*$ that is definable in $V_\lambda [G_\delta ]$ and such that $\pi (r)\leq p$ is dense. Pick such an r in $G_{[\delta ,\lambda )}$ and such an automorphism $\pi $ . Now, notice that the filter H generated by the set $\pi "G_{[\delta ,\lambda )}$ contains $\pi (r)$ and therefore it contains p. Since H is definable by means of $\pi $ and $G_{[\delta ,\lambda )}$ , and also $\pi $ is definable in $V_\lambda [G_\delta ]$ , we conclude that $V_{\lambda }[G_\delta \ast H]=V_{\lambda }[G_\lambda ]$ .

By taking $H\subseteq \mathbb {Q}^*$ as in the claim above, we thus obtain a lifting

$$ \begin{align*}j:V_{\bar{\lambda}}[G_{\bar{\lambda}}]\longrightarrow V_{\lambda}[G_\lambda],\end{align*} $$

as wanted.

Remark 5.5. Note that the above proof shows more than what is stated in Theorem 5.4. Specifically, what is proved is the following local result: every elementary embedding (in V) witnessing some partial degree of $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -supercompactness lifts to an elementary embedding (in $V^{\mathbb {P}}$ ) witnessing the same partial degree of $C^{(n)}$ -extendibility.

Corollary 5.6. Suppose $n\geq 1$ . Let $\mathbb {P}$ be an adequate $\Delta _2$ -definable and weakly homogeneous suitable iteration. Suppose there is a proper class of $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -reflecting cardinals. If $\delta $ is a $C^{(n+1)}$ -extendible cardinal, then

$$ \begin{align*} \Vdash_{\mathbb{P}}\text{"}\,\delta \text{ is } C^{(n)}\text{-extendible}\,.\text{"} \end{align*} $$

Proof Since $\mathbb {P}$ is adequate, $\Delta _2$ -definable, and there exists a proper class of $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -reflecting cardinals, Corollary 4.3 implies that $\delta $ is $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -supercompact. Now, Theorem 5.4 applies to get the desired result.

Let $\mathbb {P}$ be an adequate $\Delta _{m+1}$ -definable suitable iteration. Let us look next into the conditions under which, for some $n\geq 1$ , there exists a proper class of $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -reflecting cardinals (this was one of the assumptions of Theorem 5.4).

First, the class $C^{(n)}_{\mathbb {P}}$ is closed, unbounded, and $\Pi _{m+n}$ -definable (Proposition 3.9). Also, the class D of ordinals $\alpha $ such that $\mathbb {P}_\alpha =\mathbb {P}\cap V_\alpha $ is $\Pi _{m+1}$ -definable (cf. the proof of Proposition 3.17). Observe that D is a proper class by assumption, hence $\overline {D}$ (the closure of D) is a club proper class. Further, the following holds:

Lemma 5.7. The class K of $\mathbb {P}$ -reflecting cardinals is unbounded.

Proof We begin with the following auxiliary claim:

Claim 5.7.1. For each $\alpha \in \operatorname {\mathrm {ORD}}$ there is a $\mathbb {P}$ -name $\tau _\alpha $ such that

$$ \begin{align*} \Vdash_{\mathbb{P}} \text{"}\tau_\alpha=V[\dot{G}]_{\alpha}.\text{"} \end{align*} $$

Proof By induction on $\alpha $ . If $\alpha =0$ , then the result is clear. So, assume that $\langle \tau _\beta \mid \beta <\alpha \rangle $ has already been found, and let us find $\tau _\alpha $ . If $\alpha $ is a limit ordinal, then let $\tau _\alpha :=\bigcup _{\beta <\alpha }\tau _\beta $ . Clearly, $\tau _\alpha $ is as desired.

Now suppose that $\alpha $ is a successor ordinal; say, $\alpha =\bar {\alpha }+1$ . Let $\varphi \colon \delta \rightarrow \tau _{\bar {\alpha }}$ be a bijection, some cardinal $\delta $ . Thus, $\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}}\text {"}\check {\varphi }:\check {\delta }\to \tau _{\bar {\alpha }} \text { is onto.}\text {"}$ Since by the induction hypothesis, $\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}}\text {"}\tau _{\bar {\alpha }}=V[\dot {G}]_{\bar {\alpha }},\text {"}$ we have that $\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}}\text {"}\check {\varphi }:\check {\delta }\to V[\dot {G}]_{\bar {\alpha }} \text { is onto.}\text {"}$ As $\mathbb {P}$ is suitable we can find a cardinal $\theta $ such that $\tau _{\bar {\alpha }}$ is a $\mathbb {P}_\theta $ -name and, moreover,

$$ \begin{align*} \Vdash _{\mathbb{P}_\theta}\text{"}\dot{\mathbb{P}}_{[\theta,\operatorname{\mathrm{ORD}})} \text{ is } \delta^+\text{-closed}.\text{"} \end{align*} $$

As the remaining part $\mathbb {P}_{[\theta ,\operatorname {\mathrm {ORD}})}$ of the iteration does not add any new subsets of $\delta $ , hence no new elements of $V[\dot {G}]_\alpha $ , we have that

$$ \begin{align*} \Vdash _{\mathbb{P}}\text{"}V[\dot{G}]_\alpha =V[\dot{G}_\theta]_\alpha.\text{"} \end{align*} $$

So we can just take $\tau _\alpha $ to be a $\mathbb {P}_\theta $ -name for $V[\dot {G}_\theta ]_\alpha $ , where $\dot {G}_\theta $ is the standard $\mathbb {P}_\theta $ -name for the generic.

We are now in conditions to show that the class K of $\mathbb {P}$ -reflecting cardinals is unbounded. To this aim fix any ordinal $\alpha $ and define inductively a sequence of ordinals $\langle \alpha _n :n<\omega \rangle $ in D, with $\alpha _0=\alpha $ and $\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}}\text {"}V[\dot {G}]_{\alpha _n}\subseteq V_{\alpha _{n+1}}[\dot {G}_{\alpha _{n+1}}],\text {"}$ as follows: Suppose that $\alpha _n$ has already been defined. By the above claim there is a $\mathbb {P}$ -name $\tau $ such that $\mathbb {P}$ forces “ $\tau =V[\dot {G}]_{\alpha _n}$ .” Let $\beta $ be an ordinal such that $p\in \mathbb {P}_\beta $ and $\mathbb {P}_\beta =\mathbb {P}\cap V_\beta $ . Then, $\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}}\text {"}\tau \in V_\beta [\dot {G}_\beta ]\text {"}$ and thus $\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}} \text {"}V[\dot {G}]_{\alpha _n}\subseteq V_{\alpha _{n+1}}[\dot {G}_{\alpha _{n+1}}],\text {"}$ where $\beta :=\alpha _{n+1}$ . Finally, let $\lambda $ be the supremum of the $\alpha _n$ ’s. In this case we have that $\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}} \text {"}V[\dot {G}]_\lambda \subseteq V_\lambda [\dot {G}_\lambda ],\text {"}$ and so $\lambda $ is $\mathbb {P}$ -reflecting.

Thus, K is a $\Pi _{m+2}$ -definable club proper class (see Propositions 3.3 and 3.14). For each $n\geq 1$ , set $\mathcal {K}_{n}:=C^{(n)}_{\mathbb {P}} \cap {K}\cap \overline {D}$ .

Proposition 5.8. Let $\mathbb {P}$ be an adequate $\Delta _{m+1}$ -definable suitable iteration. Then $\mathcal {K}_{n+1} \ ($ resp. $\mathcal {K}_1)$ is a $\Pi _{m+n+1}$ -definable $($ resp. $\Pi _{m+2})$ club class such that $\mathcal {K}_{n+1}\cap \mathrm {Reg} \ ($ resp. $\mathcal {K}_1\cap \mathrm {Reg})$ is contained in the class of $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -reflecting cardinals $($ resp. $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _{1}$ -reflecting cardinals).

Proof Clearly, $\mathcal {K}_{n+1}$ is a club class. Also, by the above discussion, $\mathcal {K}_{n+1}$ is $\Pi _{m+n+1}$ , and $\mathcal {K}_1$ is $\Pi _{m+2}$ . Let $\kappa \in \mathcal {K}_{n+1}\cap \mathrm {Reg}$ . To show that $\kappa $ is $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -reflecting it is enough to verify that $\kappa \in D$ .

Since $\kappa $ is an accumulation point of D, $\mathbb {P}\cap V_\kappa \subseteq \mathbb {P}_\kappa $ . Conversely, $\kappa $ is inaccessible, hence $\mathbb {P}_\kappa $ is the direct limit of the previous stages, and so $\mathbb {P}_\kappa \subseteq \mathbb {P}\cap V_\kappa $ . Hence $\kappa \in D$ . The proof for $\mathcal {K}_1$ is the same.

Recall that if $\kappa $ is a cardinal and $\alpha $ an ordinal,

  • $\kappa $ is $0$ -Mahlo if $\kappa $ is inaccessible;

  • $\kappa $ is $(\alpha +1)$ -Mahlo iff $\{\lambda <\kappa \mid \lambda \text { is } \alpha \text {-Mahlo}\}$ is stationary;

  • In case $\alpha>0$ is a limit ordinal, $\kappa $ is $\alpha $ -Mahlo iff $\kappa $ is $\beta $ -Mahlo for every $\beta <\alpha $ .

Definition 5.9. For $n<\omega $ and $\alpha \in \mathrm {ORD}$ , the class ${\mathrm {ORD}}$ is $\mathbf {\Gamma _n}$ - $(\alpha +1)$ -Mahlo if every $\mathbf {\Gamma _n}$ -definableFootnote 5 club proper class of ordinals contains an $\alpha $ -Mahlo cardinal.

Note that a cardinal is Mahlo if and only if it is $1$ -Mahlo, hence $\mathrm {ORD}$ is $\mathbf {\Gamma _n}$ -Mahlo if and only if $\mathrm {ORD}$ is $\mathbf {\Gamma _n}$ -1-Mahlo.

Definition 5.10. A proper class S of ordinals is $\boldsymbol {\Gamma }_{\mathbf {n}}$ -stationary if S intersects every $\boldsymbol {\Gamma }_{\mathbf {n}}$ -definable club proper class of ordinals.

Proposition 5.11. Let $\mathbb {P}$ be an adequate $\Delta _{m+1}$ -definable suitable iteration. If $\mathrm {ORD}$ is $\mathbf {\Pi _{m+n+1}}$ -Mahlo, then the class of $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -reflecting cardinals is $\mathbf {\Pi _{m+n+1}}$ -stationary, so it is a proper class.

Proof Let $\mathcal {C}$ be a $\mathbf {\Pi _{m+n+1}}$ club proper class of ordinals. By Proposition 5.8, $\mathcal {C}\cap \mathcal {K}_{n+1}$ is a $\mathbf {\Pi _{m+n+1}}$ club proper class such that $\mathcal {C}\cap \mathcal {K}_{n+1}\cap \mathrm {Reg}$ is contained in the class of $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -reflecting cardinals. Thus, the class of $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -reflecting cardinals is $\mathbf {\Pi _{m+n+1}}$ -stationary. To show the class is unbounded, given any cardinal $\kappa $ , let $\mathcal {C}:=C^{(n+m)}\setminus \kappa ^+$ . Then $\mathcal {C}$ is a $\mathbf {\Pi _{m+n+1}}$ -definable club proper class which, as before, contains a $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -reflecting cardinal.

Lemma 5.12. Let $\mathbb {P}$ be a $\Delta _{m+1}$ -definable suitable iteration. If $\mathrm {ORD}$ is $\mathbf {\Pi _{m+1}}$ -Mahlo, then $\mathbb {P}$ is adequate.

Proof Since $\mathbb {P}$ is $\Delta _{m+1}$ -definable, $\mathbb {P}^{V_\kappa }=\mathbb {P}\cap V_\kappa $ for every $\kappa \in C^{(m+1)}$ . Since $\mathrm {ORD}$ is $\mathbf {\Pi _{m+1}}$ -Mahlo, and direct limits are taken at inaccessible stages of the iteration, the class of inaccessible cardinals $\kappa $ such that $\mathbb {P}^{V_\kappa }=\mathbb {P}_\kappa $ is a proper class. Thus, $\mathbb {P}$ is adequate.

The following corollaries now follow immediately from Theorem 5.4, Corollary 5.6, Proposition 5.11, and Lemma 5.12:

Corollary 5.13. Let $m,n\geq 1$ and $m\leq n$ . Let $\mathbb {P}$ be $\Delta _{m+1}$ -definable weakly homogeneous suitable iteration. Suppose ${\mathrm {ORD}}$ is $\mathbf {\Pi _{m+n+1}}$ -Mahlo. If $\delta $ is a $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -supercompact cardinal, then

$$ \begin{align*} \Vdash_{\mathbb{P}} \text{"}\delta \text{ is } C^{(n)}\text{-extendible."} \end{align*} $$

Corollary 5.14. Let $n\geq 1$ and let $\mathbb {P}$ be $\Delta _2$ -definable weakly homogeneous suitable iteration. Suppose ${\mathrm {ORD}}$ is $\mathbf {\Pi _{n+2}}$ -Mahlo. If $\delta $ is a $C^{(n+1)}$ -extendible cardinal, then

$$ \begin{align*} \Vdash_{\mathbb{P}}\text{"}\,\delta \text{ is } C^{(n)}\text{-extendible}\,.\text{"} \end{align*} $$

6 Vopěnka’s principle and suitable iterations

Let us recall the following characterizations of Vopěnka’s Principle, as well as of its restriction to definable classes of structures of a given complexity, in terms of $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinals.

Theorem 6.1 [Reference Bagaria, Casacuberta, Mathias and Rosickỳ2].

The following are equivalent $:$

  1. (1) $\mathrm {VP}$ .

  2. (2) For every $n\geq 1$ there exists a $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinal.

Theorem 6.2 [Reference Bagaria1].

Let $n\geq 1$ . The following are equivalent $:$

  1. (1) $\mathrm {VP}(\mathbf {\Pi _{n+1}})$ , i.e., $\mathrm {VP}$ restricted to proper classes of structures that are ${\Pi _{n+1}}$ -definable with parameters.

  2. (2) There exists a proper class of $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinals.

For $n=0$ , the equivalence is between $\mathrm {VP} (\mathbf {\Pi _1})$ and the existence of a proper class of supercompact cardinal. The lightface version also holds. Namely, $\mathrm {VP}(\Pi _{n+1})$ is equivalent to the existence of a $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinal (see [Reference Bagaria1]).

Vopěnka’s Principle can be also characterized in terms of the existence of $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _n$ -supercompact cardinals (cf. Theorems 6.4 and 6.5). The following lemma will be useful for this purpose.

Lemma 6.3. Let $n\geq 1$ . Then $\mathrm {VP}(\mathbf {\Pi _n})$ implies that $\mathrm {ORD}$ is $\mathbf {\Sigma _{n+1}}$ - $(\kappa +1)$ -Mahlo, for every cardinal $\kappa $ .Footnote 6

Proof Let us prove the lemma for $n>1$ . The case $n=1$ is similar, using the fact that $\mathrm {VP}(\mathbf {\Pi _1})$ is equivalent to the existence of a proper class of supercompact cardinal, and that every supercompact cardinal belongs to $C^{(2)}$ . So, let $n>1$ and assume that $\mathrm {VP}(\mathbf {\Pi _{n}})$ holds.

Let $\mathcal {C}$ be a $\mathbf {\Sigma _{n+1}}$ -definable club proper class of ordinals and let $\varphi (x,\vec {a})$ be some $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -formula defining it. Let $\kappa $ be a cardinal and $\lambda $ be a $C^{(n-1)}$ -extendible cardinal with $\vec {a}\in V_\lambda $ and $\kappa <\lambda $ . Note that this $\lambda $ exists by virtue of Theorem 6.2. We claim that $\mathcal {C}\cap \lambda $ is unbounded in $\lambda $ . For if $\alpha <\lambda $ , then the sentence “ $\exists \beta>\alpha (\beta \in \mathcal {C})$ ” is $\Sigma _{n+1}$ (with $\vec {a}$ as parameters), hence it is true in $V_\lambda $ because $\lambda $ is $C^{(n-1)}$ -extendible and so it belongs to $C^{(n+1)}$ [Reference Bagaria1, Proposition 3.4]. Since $\mathcal {C}$ is closed, $\lambda \in \mathcal {C}$ . Since $\lambda $ is $\lambda $ -Mahlo, hence also $\kappa $ -Mahlo, the result follows.

Theorem 6.4. The following are equivalent $:$

  1. (1) $\mathrm {VP}$ holds.

  2. (2) For every $n\geq 1$ and every definable weakly homogeneous suitable iteration $\mathbb {P}$ , there is a proper class of $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _{n}$ -reflecting cardinals and there exists a proper class of $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _n$ -supercompact cardinal.

Proof $(1) \Rightarrow (2)$ : Let $n\geq 1$ and let $\mathbb {P}$ be $\Delta _{m+1}$ -definable weakly homogeneous suitable iteration, some $m\geq 1$ . By Lemma 5.12, $\mathbb {P}$ is adequate. By Lemma 6.3, ${\mathrm {ORD}}$ is $\mathbf {\Pi _{m+n+1}}$ -Mahlo and so Proposition 5.11 yields a proper class of $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -reflecting cardinals. Also, by Corollary 4.3 and Theorem 6.2 we infer that there is a proper class of $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _n$ -supercompact cardinal.

$(2)\Rightarrow (1)$ : Since (2) holds, by Corollary 4.3 there exists a proper class of $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinals, for every $n\geq 1$ , hence by Theorem 6.2, $\mathrm {VP}$ holds.

The following gives more precise information about the relationship between $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _n$ -supercompact cardinals and fragments of $\mathrm {VP}$ .

Theorem 6.5. Let $m,n\geq 1$ and let $\mathbb {P}$ be an ${\mathrm {ORD}}$ -length forcing iteration. Then,

  1. (1) Assume there is a proper class of $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -reflecting cardinals. If there is a $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -supercompact cardinal, then $\mathrm {VP}(\Pi _{n+1})$ holds $;$ and if there is a proper class of $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -supercompact cardinals, then $\mathrm {VP}(\mathbf {\Pi _{n+1}})$ holds.

  2. (2) If $\mathbb {P}$ is $\Delta _{m+1}$ -definable, some $m\geq 1$ , suitable, and weakly homogeneous, then $\mathrm {VP}(\mathbf {\Pi _{m+n+1}})$ implies the existence of a proper class of $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -reflecting cardinals and a proper class of $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -supercompact cardinals.

Proof Item (1) is a direct consequence of Corollary 4.3 and our remarks following Theorem 6.2. As for (2), Theorem 6.2 shows that $\mathrm {VP}(\mathbf {\Pi _{m+n+1}})$ is equivalent to the existence of a proper class of $C^{(m+n)}$ -extendible cardinals. Also, Lemma 6.3 shows that $\mathrm {VP}(\mathbf {\Pi _{m+n+1}})$ implies that ORD is $\mathbf {\Sigma _{m+n+2}}$ -Mahlo, hence Lemma 5.12 implies that $\mathbb {P}$ is adequate. Thus, by Proposition 5.11, there exists a proper class of $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -reflecting cardinals. By Corollary 4.3 there exists also a proper class of $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -supercompact cardinals.

We end this section by proving a level-by-level version of Brooke-Taylor’s result on the preservation of Vopěnka’s Principle under definable suitable iterations.

Theorem 6.6. Let $m,n\geq 1$ and $m\leq n$ . Let $\mathbb {P}$ be a $\Delta _{m+1}$ -definable weakly homogeneous suitable iteration. If $\mathrm {VP}(\mathbf {\Pi _{m+n+1}})$ holds, then

$$ \begin{align*} \Vdash_{\mathbb{P}}\text{"}\mathrm{VP}(\mathbf{\Pi_{n+1}}) \text{ holds."} \end{align*} $$

Proof By Theorem 6.5(2), there is a proper class of $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -reflecting cardinals, as well as a proper class of $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -supercompact cardinals. Also, by Lemma 5.12, $\mathbb {P}$ is adequate. Now the result follows combining Theorem 5.4 and the remarks just after Theorem 6.2.

Corollary 6.7 [Reference Brooke-Taylor8].

Let $\mathbb {P}$ be a definable weakly homogeneous suitable iteration. If $\mathrm {VP}$ holds in $\mathrm {V}$ , then $\mathrm {VP}$ holds in $V^{\mathbb {P}}$ .

Our version of Brooke-Taylor’s result differs from the original one in that we require the weak homogeneity of $\mathbb {P}$ . However, our proof shows more than Brooke-Taylor’s, for it shows that every relevant elementary embedding from the ground model lifts to an elementary embedding in the forcing extension (recall Remark 5.5). Even though weak homogeneity holds for a wide family of forcing notions, it puts some restrictions on the sort of statements that can be forced. One example is “ $\mathrm {V}=\mathrm {HOD}.$ ” In Section 9.1 we will address this problem and will prove Theorem 6.6 without the weak homogeneity assumption (Theorem 9.6). We are very grateful to Brooke-Taylor for his valuable comments on this matter.

7 $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinals and fitting iterations

While our main corollary from Section 5 (cf. Corollary 5.14) applies to a wide class of forcing iterations, it requires that the cardinal we begin with is $C^{(n+1)}$ -extendible. In this section we argue that this extra assumption can be avoided by restricting to a certain subclass of forcing iterations, which nevertheless are still general enough.

Definition 7.1. An $\mathrm {ORD}$ -length forcing iteration $\mathbb {P}$ is fitting if it is $\Delta _2$ -definable, suitable, and weakly homogeneous, and there is a $\Delta _2$ -definable $\mathbf {\Sigma _{2}}$ -stationary class $K_{\mathbb {P}}$ of regular $\mathbb {P}$ -reflecting cardinals $\kappa $ such that $\mathbb {P}\cap V_\kappa =\mathbb {P}_\kappa $ .

Remark 7.2. Note that every fitting iteration is adequate. Also notice that $K_{\mathbb {P}}\cap C^{(1)}$ is a $\Delta _2$ -definable proper class of inaccessible cardinals.

Theorem 7.3. Suppose that $\mathbb {P}$ is a fitting iteration. If $\delta $ is a supercompact cardinal in $C(\mathbb {P})$ , then $\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}}\text {"}\delta \text { is supercompact."}$ Footnote 7

Proof Let $\delta $ be a supercompact cardinal in $C(\mathbb {P})$ and suppose G is a $\mathbb {P}$ -generic filter over $\mathrm {V}$ . It will be sufficient to verify that for each $\lambda \in K_{\mathbb {P}}\cap C^{(1)}$ there are $\bar {\lambda }\in K_{\mathbb {P}}\cap C^{(1)}$ and $\bar {\delta }$ with $\bar {\delta }< \bar {\lambda }<\delta ,$ and an elementary embedding

$$ \begin{align*}j\colon V_{\bar{\lambda}}[G_{\bar{\lambda}}]\rightarrow V_\lambda[G_\lambda]\end{align*} $$

with $\mathrm {crit}(j)=\bar {\delta }$ and $j(\bar {\delta })=\delta $ . For since $\lambda $ and $\bar {\lambda }$ are $\mathbb {P}$ -reflecting we then have $V_{\bar {\lambda }}[G_{\bar {\lambda }}]=V[G]_{\bar {\lambda }}$ and $V_{\lambda }[G_{\lambda }]=V[G]_{\lambda }$ .

So let $\lambda $ be as above. Since $\delta $ is $\Sigma _1$ -supercompact, given $\mu \in C^{(1)}$ with $\mu>\lambda $ , there is $\bar {\mu }\in C^{(1)}$ and $\bar {\delta }<\bar {\lambda }<\bar {\mu }$ , and an elementary embedding $j:V_{\bar {\mu }}\rightarrow V_\mu $ with $\mathrm {crit}(j)=\bar {\delta }$ , $j(\bar {\delta })=\delta $ , and $j(\bar {\lambda })=\lambda $ .

Since $K_{\mathbb {P}}$ is $\Delta _2$ -definable, $V_\mu \models \lambda \in K_{\mathbb {P}}\cap C^{(1)}$ . Hence, by elementarity and $\Sigma _1$ -correctness of $\bar {\mu }$ , $\bar {\lambda }\in K_{\mathbb {P}}\cap C^{(1)}$ .

We only need to show how to lift $j\restriction V_{\bar {\lambda }}:V_{\bar {\lambda }}\rightarrow V_\lambda $ to an elementary embedding $V_{\bar {\lambda }}[G_{\bar {\lambda }}]\rightarrow V_\lambda [G_\lambda ].$ Since $\mathbb {P}$ is $\Delta _2$ -definable, $\mathbb {P}^{V_\lambda }=\mathbb {P}\cap V_\lambda =\mathbb {P}_\lambda $ , where the rightmost equality follows from $\lambda \in K_{\mathbb {P}}$ . Analogously, the same holds for $\mathbb {P}^{V_{\bar {\lambda }}}$ . Thus, we have:

  1. (i) $\mathbb {P}_{\bar {\lambda }}\cong \mathbb {P}_{\bar {\delta }}\ast \dot {\mathbb {Q}}$ , with $|\dot {\mathbb {Q}}|=\bar {\lambda }$ .

  2. (ii) $\mathbb {P}_\lambda \cong \mathbb {P}_{\delta }\ast \dot {\mathbb {Q}}^*$ and $\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}_{\delta }}\text {"}\dot {\mathbb {Q}}^* \text { is weakly homogeneous."}$

Since $\delta \in C(\mathbb {P})$ , $\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}_\delta }\text {"}\dot {\mathbb {Q}}^* \text { is } \delta \text {-directed closed."}$ We may now proceed as in the proof of Theorem 5.4 to get the desired elementary embedding $j:V_{\bar {\lambda }}[G_{\bar {\lambda }}]\rightarrow V_\lambda [G_\lambda ].$

Lemma 7.4. Suppose that $\mathbb {P}$ is a fitting iteration and $\delta $ is an extendible cardinal. Then, $\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}}\text {"}\delta \text { is extendible."}$

Proof Suppose G is a $\mathbb {P}$ -generic filter over $\mathrm {V}$ . It suffices to verify that for each $\lambda \in K_{\mathbb {P}}$ greater than $\delta $ , there is $\theta \in K_{\mathbb {P}}$ and an elementary embedding

$$ \begin{align*}j\colon V_\lambda[G_\lambda]\rightarrow V_\theta[G_\theta]\end{align*} $$

with $\mathrm {crit}(j)=\delta $ and $j(\delta )>\lambda $ . For since $\lambda $ and $\theta $ are $\mathbb {P}$ -reflecting we then have $V_{\lambda }[G_{\lambda }]=V[G]_{\lambda }$ and $V_{\theta }[G_{\theta }]=V[G]_{\theta }$ .

So let $\lambda $ be as above. Since $\delta $ is extendible, hence $C^{(1)+}$ -extendible, given $\mu \in C^{(1)}$ , $\mu>\lambda $ , there is $\eta \in C^{(1)}$ and an elementary embedding $j:V_\mu \rightarrow V_\eta $ with $\mathrm {crit}(j)=\delta $ and $j(\delta )>\mu $ . Since $K_{\mathbb {P}}$ is $\Delta _2$ -definable, $V_\mu \models \lambda \in K_{\mathbb {P}}$ , hence by elementarity and since $\eta \in C^{(1)}$ , $j(\lambda )\in K_{\mathbb {P}}$ .

Let $\theta :=j(\lambda )$ . We will show how to lift $j\restriction V_\lambda :V_\lambda \rightarrow V_\theta $ to an elementary embedding $V_\lambda [G_\lambda ]\rightarrow V_\theta [G_\theta ]$ . Since $\mathbb {P}$ is $\Delta _2$ -definable, $\mathbb {P}^{V_\lambda }=\mathbb {P}\cap V_\lambda =\mathbb {P}_\lambda $ , where the rightmost equality follows from $\lambda \in K_{\mathbb {P}}$ . Analogously, the same holds for $\mathbb {P}^{V_\theta }$ . Thus, we have:

  1. (i) $\mathbb {P}_\lambda \cong \mathbb {P}_\delta \ast \dot {\mathbb {Q}}$ , with $|\dot {\mathbb {Q}}|=\lambda $ .

  2. (ii) $\mathbb {P}_\theta \cong \mathbb {P}_{i(\delta )}\ast \dot {\mathbb {Q}}^*$ and $\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}_{i(\delta )}}\text {"}\dot {\mathbb {Q}}^* \text { is weakly homogeneous."}$

Claim 7.4.1. $\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}_{i(\delta )}}\text {"}\dot {\mathbb {Q}}^* \text { is } i(\delta )\text {-directed closed."}$

Proof of claim We first show that $\delta $ is an accumulation point of $C(\mathbb {P})$ , hence it belongs to $C(\mathbb {P})$ . So, fix an ordinal $\sigma _0<\delta $ . Since $\mathbb {P}$ is suitable the $\Sigma _3$ -formula $\varphi (\sigma _0)$

$$ \begin{align*} \exists \sigma \forall\rho\forall\alpha\forall X(\sigma_0<\sigma\leq \rho<\alpha\,\wedge \,\alpha\in \overline{K_{\mathbb{P}}^{(1)}}\,\wedge \\[-36pt]\end{align*} $$
$$ \begin{align*} X=V_\alpha\rightarrow X\models\ \Vdash_{\mathbb{P}_\rho}\text{"}\dot{\mathbb{Q}}_\rho \text{ is } \sigma_0\text{-directed closed"}) \end{align*} $$

holds. Since $\delta \in C^{(3)}$ and $\sigma _0<\delta $ , there is a witness $\sigma _0<\sigma _1<\delta $ for $\varphi (\sigma _0)$ . Arguing inductively we define a sequence $\langle \sigma _n\mid n<\omega \rangle $ of ordinals ${<}\delta $ such that $\sigma _{n+1}$ is a witness for $\varphi (\sigma _n)$ . Setting $\sigma _\omega :=\sup _{n<\omega }\sigma _n$ one can easily see that $\sigma _\omega \in C(\mathbb {P})\cap \delta $ .

Since $\delta \in C(\mathbb {P})$ , for each $\sigma \in [\delta ,\lambda )$ , $\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}_\delta }\text {"}\dot {\mathbb {P}}_{[\delta ,\sigma ]} \text { is }\delta \text {-directed closed."}$ Footnote 8 Since $\lambda $ is inaccessible, $^{<\delta }{V_\lambda }\subseteq V_\lambda $ , and therefore the same is true in $V_\lambda $ , namely $V_\lambda \models \text {"}\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}_\delta }\,\dot {\mathbb {Q}} \text { is } \delta \text {-directed closed."}$ By elementarity,

$$ \begin{align*} V_\theta \models \text{"}\Vdash _{\mathbb{P}_{i(\delta)}}\,\dot{\mathbb{Q}}^* \text{ is } i(\delta)\text{-directed closed."} \end{align*} $$

Since $\theta $ is inaccessible, $^{<i(\delta )}{V_\theta }\subseteq V_\theta $ , and therefore the quoted sentence displayed above also holds in V, as desired.

From this point on the argument for the lifting of $j\restriction V_\lambda $ to an elementary embedding $V_\lambda [G_\lambda ]\rightarrow V_\theta [G_\theta ]$ is essentially the same as in Theorem 5.4.

Theorem 7.5. Suppose that $\mathbb {P}$ is a fitting iteration such that $C(\mathbb {P})$ contains all supercompact cardinals, in case there are any. Then forcing with $\mathbb {P}$ preserves $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinals, for all $n<\omega $ .Footnote 9

Proof We prove the theorem by induction over n. The case $n=1$ is covered by Lemma 7.4. So, suppose that $n\geq 2$ and for each $0\leq k< n$ forcing with $\mathbb {P}$ preserves $C^{(k)}$ -extendible cardinals.

We argue similarly as in the proof of Lemma 7.4. So, let $\delta $ be a $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinal and suppose G is a $\mathbb {P}$ -generic filter over $\mathrm {V}$ . Let $\lambda \in K^{(1)}_{\mathbb {P}}$ be greater than $\delta $ , and let $\mu \in C^{(n)}$ be greater than $\lambda $ . Then, there is $\eta \in C^{(n)}$ and an elementary embedding

$$ \begin{align*}j:V_\mu\rightarrow V_\eta\end{align*} $$

with $\mathrm {crit}(j)=\delta $ , $j(\delta )>\mu $ , and $j(\delta )\in C^{(n)}$ . Actually, $j(\delta )$ is $C^{(n-2)}$ -extendible. Since $n\geq 2$ and $K_{\mathbb {P}}$ is $\Delta _{2}$ -definable, $V_\mu \models \lambda \in K_{\mathbb {P}}$ . Hence, by elementarity and since $\eta \in C^{(n)}$ , $j(\lambda )\in K_{\mathbb {P}}$ .

Arguing exactly as in the proof of Theorem 7.4, we can lift $j\upharpoonright V_\lambda $ to an elementary embedding $V[G]_\lambda \rightarrow V[G]_\theta $ , where $\theta :=j(\lambda )$ .

It only remains to show that $j(\delta )\in C^{(n)}$ . Suppose first $n=2$ . Since $j(\delta )$ is supercompact and every supercompact belongs to $C^{(2)}$ , it is enough to show that $j(\delta )$ is supercompact in $V[G]$ . By our assumption, $j(\delta )\in C(\mathbb {P})$ , hence $j(\delta )$ is supercompact in $V[G]$ (cf. Theorem 7.3).

For $1\leq n-2$ and $j(\delta )$ being $C^{(n-2)}$ -extendible, our induction hypothesis implies that $i(\delta )$ is $C^{(n-2)}$ -extendible in $V[G]$ . In particular, $V[G]_{j(\delta )}\prec _{\Sigma _n} V[G]$ . Thus, $\delta $ is $C^{(n)}$ -extendible in $V[G]$ .

In the next section we provide several applications of this theorem.

8 Some applications

8.1 Forcing the GCH and related combinatorial principles

Let $\mathbb {P}=\langle \mathbb {P}_\alpha; \dot {\mathbb {Q}}_\alpha :\alpha \in \mathrm {ORD}\rangle $ be the standard Jensen’s proper class iteration for forcing the global GCH. Namely, $\mathbb {P}$ is the direct limit of the iteration with Easton support where $\mathbb {P}_0$ is the trivial forcing and for each ordinal $\alpha $ , if $\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}_\alpha }\text {"}\alpha \text { is an uncountable cardinal,"}$ then $\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}_\alpha }\text {"}\dot {\mathbb {Q}}_{\alpha } = \mathrm {Add},\text {"}$ and $\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}_\alpha }\text {"}\dot {\mathbb {Q}}_\alpha \text { is trivial"}$ otherwise.

Lemma 8.1. Assume $\mathrm {ORD}$ is $\mathbf {\Sigma _2}$ - $2$ -Mahlo. Then $\mathbb {P}$ is fitting and $C(\mathbb {P})$ contains all supercompact cardinals, in case there are any.

Proof Clearly, $\mathbb {P}$ is a suitable and weakly homogeneous iteration. Also, $\mathbb {P}$ is $\Delta _2$ -definable, as “ $p\in \mathbb {P}$ ” if and only if $V_\alpha \models \text {"}p\in \mathbb {P},\text {"}$ for (some) every $\alpha \in C^{(1)}$ such that $p\in V_\alpha $ .

Let $K_{\mathbb {P}}$ denote the class of all Mahlo cardinals. Clearly, $K_{\mathbb {P}}$ is $\Delta _2$ -definable. Also, since $\mathrm {ORD}$ is $\mathbf {\Sigma }_2$ - $2$ -Mahlo, $K_{\mathbb {P}}$ is a $\mathbf {\Sigma _2}$ -stationary proper class. Let $\kappa \in K_{\mathbb {P}}$ . Thus, $\kappa $ is regular and, clearly, $\mathbb {P}\cap V_\kappa =\mathbb {P}_\kappa $ .

Claim 8.1.1. $\kappa $ is $\mathbb {P}$ -reflecting.

Proof of claim Clearly, $\kappa $ is inaccessible and $\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}_\kappa } \text {"}\dot {\mathbb {Q}} \text { is } \kappa \text {-distributive,"}$ where $\mathbb {P}\cong \mathbb {P}_\kappa \ast \dot {\mathbb {Q}}$ . Also, $\mathbb {P}_\kappa \subseteq V_\kappa $ . Let $\lambda <\kappa $ be forced by $\mathbb {P}_\kappa $ to be a cardinal. For every inaccessible cardinal $\theta <\kappa $ , $\theta \in C(\mathbb {P})$ , hence

$$ \begin{align*} \Vdash _{\mathbb{P}_\theta}\text{"}\dot{\mathbb{Q}}_{[\theta,\kappa)} \text{ is } \theta\text{-distributive"} \end{align*} $$

and $\mathbb {P}_\theta =\mathbb {P}\cap V_\theta $ . Since $\kappa $ is Mahlo and $\{\theta <\kappa \mid \mathbb {P}_\theta =\mathbb {P}\cap V_\theta \}$ is unbounded, $\mathbb {P}_\kappa $ is $\kappa $ -cc. Also, standard arguments show that $\mathbb {P}_\kappa $ forces “ $|\dot {\mathcal {P}}(\lambda )|<\check {\kappa }$ .” Altogether, $\mathbb {P}$ forces $\kappa $ to be inaccessible. Finally, we appeal to Proposition 3.4 to get that $\kappa $ is $\mathbb {P}$ -reflecting, as wanted.

The claim about $C(\mathbb {P})$ containing all supercompacts is obvious.

In [Reference Tsaprounis28, Section 5], Tsaprounis shows that $\mathbb {P}$ preserves $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinals. The following theorem gives an improvement of his result:

Theorem 8.2.

  1. (1) If $\mathrm {ORD}$ is $\mathbf {\Sigma _2}$ - $2$ -Mahlo, and $\delta $ is supercompact then

    $$ \begin{align*} \Vdash _{\mathbb{P}}\text{"}\delta \text{ is supercompact."} \end{align*} $$
  2. (2) If for some $n\geq 1$ , $\delta $ is $C^{(n)}$ -extendible then

    $$ \begin{align*} \Vdash _{\mathbb{P}}\text{"}\delta \text{ is } C^{(n)}\text{-extendible."} \end{align*} $$

InFootnote 10 particular, if there is a proper class of supercompact cardinals $($ equivalently, if $\mathrm {VP}(\mathbf {\Pi _1})$ holds), then forcing with $\mathbb {P}$ preserves $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinals, for all $n<\omega $ .

Proof This follows from Theorem 7.5 and Lemma 8.1. The particular case can be proved using Lemma 6.3.

Recall that a class function E from the class $\mathrm {Reg}$ of infinite regular cardinals to the class of cardinals is an Easton function if it satisfies König’s theorem (i.e., $\mathrm {cf}(E(\kappa ))>\kappa $ , for all $\kappa \in \mathrm {Reg}$ ) and is increasingly monotone. Let $\mathbb {P}_E$ be the direct limit of the iteration $\langle \mathbb {P}_\alpha , \dot {\mathbb {Q}}_\alpha :\,\alpha \in \mathrm {ORD}\rangle $ with Easton support where $\mathbb {P}_0$ is the trivial forcing and for each ordinal $\alpha $ , if $\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}_\alpha }\text {"}\alpha \text { is a regular cardinal,"}$ then $\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}_\alpha }\text {"}\dot {\mathbb {Q}}_\alpha =\mathrm {Add}(\alpha ,E(\alpha )),\text {"}$ and $\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}_\alpha }\text {"}\dot {\mathbb {Q}}_\alpha \text { is trivial"}$ otherwise. Standard arguments [Reference Jech16, Section 15] show that if the GCH holds in the ground model, then $\mathbb {P}_E$ preserves all cardinals and cofinalities and forces that $2^\kappa =E(\kappa )$ , for each $\kappa \in \mathrm {Reg}$ .

Lemma 8.3. Let E be a $\Delta _2$ -definable Easton function and assume that $\mathrm {ORD}$ is $\mathbf {\Sigma _2}$ - $2$ -Mahlo. Then $\mathbb {P}_E$ is fitting and $C(\mathbb {P})$ contains all supercompact cardinals, in case there are any.

Proof Arguing as in Lemma 8.1, $\mathbb {P}_E$ is a $\Delta _2$ -definable, weakly homogeneous suitable iteration. Set $\mathbb {P}:=\mathbb {P}_E$ and let

$$ \begin{align*} K_{\mathbb{P}}:=\{\kappa\mid \kappa \text{ is Mahlo and } E[\kappa]\subseteq \kappa\}. \end{align*} $$

Clearly, every $\kappa \in K_{\mathbb {P}}$ is regular and witnesses $\mathbb {P}\cap V_\kappa =\mathbb {P}_\kappa $ . The argument for the verification that each $\kappa \in K_{\mathbb {P}}$ is $\mathbb {P}$ -reflecting is analogous to the one given in Lemma 8.1. The claim about $C(\mathbb {P})$ is obvious. Also, since E is $\Delta _2$ -definable, so is $K_{\mathbb {P}}$ . Moreover, $K_{\mathbb {P}}$ is $\mathbf {\Sigma _2}$ -stationary, for if $\mathcal {C}$ is a $\mathbf {\Sigma _2}$ -definable club class of ordinals, then $\mathcal {C}_E:=\{\alpha \in \mathcal {C}\mid E[\alpha ]\subseteq \alpha \}$ is a $\mathbf {\Sigma _2}$ -definable proper club class, and since $\mathrm {ORD}$ is $\mathbf {\Sigma _2}$ - $2$ -Mahlo, $K_{\mathbb {P}}\cap \mathcal {C}\neq \varnothing $ .

Similarly as in Theorem 8.2, we now obtain the following:

Theorem 8.4. Assume the $\mathrm {GCH}$ holds and let E be a $\Delta _2$ -definable Easton function.Footnote 11 Then the following hold $:$

  1. (1) If $\mathrm {ORD}$ is $\mathbf {\Sigma _2}$ - $2$ -Mahlo and $\delta $ is supercompact then

    $$ \begin{align*} \Vdash _{\mathbb{P}_E}\text{"}\delta \text{is supercompact."} \end{align*} $$
  2. (2) If $n\geq 1$ and $\delta $ is $C^{(n)}$ -extendible then

    $$ \begin{align*} \Vdash _{\mathbb{P}_E}\text{"}\delta \text{ is } C^{(n)}\text{-extendible."} \end{align*} $$

In particular, if the $\mathrm {GCH}$ holds and there is a proper class of supercompact cardinals $($ equivalently, $\mathrm {VP}(\mathbf {\Pi _1})$ holds), then forcing with $\mathbb {P}_E$ preserves $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinals, for all $n<\omega $ .

Corollary 8.5. Let E be a $\Delta _2$ -definable Easton function and assume the $\mathrm {GCH}$ holds. Then the following are true $:$

  1. (1) If $\mathrm {VP}(\mathbf {\Pi _{1}})$ holds, then $\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}_E}\text {"}\mathrm {VP}(\mathbf {\Pi _{1}}).\text {"}$

  2. (2) If $\mathrm {VP}({\Pi _{n+1}})$ holds, then $\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}_E}\text {"}\mathrm {VP}({\Pi _{n+1}}).\text {"}$ Also, if $\mathrm {VP}(\mathbf {\Pi _{n+1}})$ holds then $\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}_E}\text {"}\mathrm {VP}(\mathbf {\Pi _{n+1}}).\text {"}$

The next corollary shows that $\mathrm {VP}$ is also consistent with any possible behaviour of the power-set function given by an arbitrary definable Easton function.

Corollary 8.6. If $\mathrm {VP}$ holds, then in some class forcing extension, for every definable Easton function E there is a further class forcing extension that preserves $\mathrm {VP}$ and where $2^\kappa =E(\kappa )$ , for every $\kappa \in \mathrm {Reg}$ .

Proof First force with the standard Jensen’s iteration for forcing the GCH and call the resulting generic extension V. By Corollary 6.7, $V\models \mathrm {VP}$ . Then, given a V-definable Easton function E, force over V with $\mathbb {P}_E$ . Once again by Corollary 6.7, $V^{\mathbb {P}_E}\models \mathrm {VP}$ . Finally, since $V\models \mathrm {GCH}$ , it follows that $\mathbb {P}_E$ forces $2^\kappa =E(\kappa )$ , for every $\kappa \in \mathrm {Reg}$ .

8.2 A remark on Woodin’s HOD Conjecture

The HOD Dichotomy theorem of Woodin states that if there exists an extendible cardinal, then either $\mathrm {V}$ is close to HOD or is far from it. Specifically, if $\kappa $ is an extendible cardinal, then either (1): for every singular cardinal $\lambda>\delta $ , $\lambda $ is singular in HOD and $(\lambda ^+)^{\mathrm {HOD}}=\lambda ^+$ , or (2): every regular cardinal $\lambda>\kappa $ is $\omega $ -strongly measurable in HOD (see [Reference Woodin29]). Woodin’s HOD Hypothesis asserts that there is a proper class of regular cardinals that are not $\omega $ -strongly measurable in HOD, and therefore that the first option of the HOD Dichotomy is the true one. Woodin’s HOD Conjecture asserts that the HOD Hypothesis is provable in the theory ZFC + “There exists an extendible cardinal.” Our arguments may be used to show that if the HOD Conjecture holds, and therefore it is provable in ZFC + “There exists an extendible cardinal” that above the first extendible cardinal every singular cardinal $\lambda $ is singular in HOD and $(\lambda ^+)^{\mathrm {HOD}}=\lambda ^+$ , there may still be no agreement at all between V and HOD about successors of regular cardinals. Moreover, many singular cardinals in $\mathrm {HOD}$ need not be cardinals in $\mathrm {V}$ . Let us give some examples.

Let $\mathbb {P}$ be the direct limit of the iteration $\langle \mathbb {P}_\alpha; \dot {\mathbb {Q}_\alpha }:\,\alpha \in \mathrm {ORD}\rangle $ with Easton support, where $\mathbb {P}_0$ is the trivial forcing and for each ordinal $\alpha $ , if $\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}_\alpha }\text {"}\alpha \text { is regular"}$ then $\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}_{\alpha }}\text {"}\boldsymbol {\dot {\mathbb {Q}}}_{\alpha } = \dot {\mathrm {Coll}}(\alpha ,\alpha ^+),\text {"}$ and $\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}_{\alpha }}\text {"}\dot {\mathbb {Q}_{\alpha }} \text { is trivial"}$ otherwise. Arguing essentially as in Lemma 8.1 we obtain the following:

Lemma 8.7. Assume $\mathrm {ORD}$ is $\mathbf {\Sigma }_2$ - $2$ -Mahlo. Then, $\mathbb {P}$ is fitting and $C(\mathbb {P})$ contains all supercompact cardinals, in case there are any.

Theorem 8.8.

  1. (1) If $\mathrm {ORD}$ is $\mathbf {\Sigma }_2$ - $2$ -Mahlo, and $\delta $ is supercompact then

    $$ \begin{align*}\Vdash _{\mathbb{P}} \text{"}\delta \text{ is supercompact."}\end{align*} $$
  2. (2) If $n\geq 1$ and $\delta $ is $C^{(n)}$ -extendible, then

    $$ \begin{align*} \Vdash_{\mathbb{P}} \text{"}\delta \text{ is } C^{(n)}\text{-extendible."} \end{align*} $$

Moreover, $\mathbb {P}$ forces $"\forall \lambda \in \mathrm {Reg}\,((\lambda ^+)^{\mathrm {HOD}}<\lambda ^+)$ .”

Proof For the preservation of $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinals we combine Lemma 8.7 and Theorem 7.5. To prove the claim about successors of regular cardinals, note that if $\lambda $ is a regular cardinal in $V^{\mathbb {P}}$ , then it was also a regular cardinal at stage $\lambda $ of the iteration, hence its successor was collapsed at stage $\lambda +1$ . Thus, on the one hand, $(\lambda ^+)^V<(\lambda ^+)^{V^{\mathbb {P}}}.$ On the other hand, $\mathbb {P}$ is weakly homogeneous and ordinal definable, hence $\mathrm {HOD}^{{V}^{\mathbb {P}}}\subseteq HOD^V$ (see, e.g., [Reference Jech16] for details). Hence, in $V^{\mathbb {P}}$ , $(\lambda ^+)^{\mathrm {HOD}}<\lambda ^+$ , as wanted.

Corollary 8.9. Forcing with $\mathbb {P}$ preserves $\mathrm {VP}$ and forces $(\lambda ^+)^{\mathrm {HOD}}<\lambda ^+$ for every regular cardinal $\lambda $ .

Theorem 8.8 yields the parallel of the main theorem from [Reference Dobrinen and Friedman11], at the level of $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinals.

Suppose now that K is a function on the class of infinite cardinals such that $K(\lambda )> \lambda $ , and K is increasingly monotone, for every $\lambda $ . Let $\mathbb {P}_K$ be the direct limit of an iteration $\langle \mathbb {P}_\alpha; \dot {\mathbb {Q}}_\alpha :\,\alpha \in \mathrm {ORD}\rangle $ with Easton support, where $\mathbb {P}_0$ is the trivial forcing and for each ordinal $\alpha $ , if $\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}_\alpha }\text {"}\alpha \text { is regular"}$ then $\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}_\alpha }{"}\dot {\mathbb {Q}}_\alpha =\dot {\mathrm {Coll}}(\alpha ,K(\alpha )),\text {"}$ and $\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}_\alpha }\text {"}\dot {\mathbb {Q}}_\alpha \text { is trivial"}$ otherwise. Notice that for each $\alpha $ such that $\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}_\alpha }\text {"}\alpha \text { is regular,"}$ the remaining part of the iteration after stage $\alpha $ is $\alpha $ -closed, hence it preserves $\alpha $ . Also note that if K is $\Delta _m$ -definable ( $m\geq 1$ ), then $\mathbb {P}_K$ is also $\Delta _m$ -definable. Clearly, $\mathbb {P}_K$ is suitable and weakly homogeneous.

Lemma 8.10. Assume $\mathrm {ORD}$ is $\mathbf {\Sigma }_2$ - $2$ -Mahlo. Let K be a $\Delta _2$ -definable class function as above. Then, $\mathbb {P}_K$ is a fitting iteration and $C(\mathbb {P})$ contains all supercompact cardinals, in case there are any.

Proof Let $K_{\mathbb {P}}:=\{\kappa \mid \kappa \text { is Mahlo and } K[\kappa ]\subseteq \kappa \}$ . The proof that $K_{\mathbb {P}}$ is a witness for the fittingness of $\mathbb {P}$ is similar to those given in Lemmas 8.3 and 8.7. The claim about $C(\mathbb {P})$ is obvious.

Theorem 8.11. Let K be a $\Delta _2$ -definable class function as above.

  1. (1) If $\mathrm {ORD}$ is $\mathbf {\Sigma _2}$ - $2$ -Mahlo, and $\delta $ is supercompact then

    $$ \begin{align*} \Vdash _{\mathbb{P}_K} \text{"}\delta \text{ is supercompact."} \end{align*} $$
  2. (2) If $\delta $ is $C^{(n)}$ -extendible, for some $n\geq 1$ , then

    $$ \begin{align*} \Vdash _{\mathbb{P}_K} \text{"}\delta \text{ is } C^{(n)}\text{-extendible."} \end{align*} $$

Moreover, $\mathbb {P}_K$ forces

$$ \begin{align*} (\lambda^+)^{\mathrm{HOD}}\leq K(\lambda)<\lambda^+ \end{align*} $$

for all infinite regular cardinals $\lambda $ .

Proof The preservation of $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinals, $n<\omega $ , follows from Lemma 8.10 and Theorem 7.5.

If G is $\mathbb {P}_K$ -generic over $\mathrm {V}$ and $\lambda $ is regular in $V[G]$ , then it is also regular at the $\lambda $ -stage of the iteration. Hence, $\mathbb {Q}_\lambda =\mathrm {Coll}(\lambda ,K(\lambda ))$ , and therefore $K(\lambda )<\lambda ^+$ holds in $V[G]$ . The other inequality (i.e., $(\lambda ^+)^{\mathrm {HOD}}\leq K(\lambda )$ ) follows from the fact that $\mathbb {P}_K$ is weakly homogeneous and ordinal definable, and thus that $\mathrm {HOD}^{V[G]}\subseteq \mathrm {HOD}^V$ .

The theorem above implies that many kinds of disagreement between successors of regulars in $\mathrm {HOD}$ and in $\mathrm {V}$ may be forced while preserving $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinals. It also implies that one can destroy many singular cardinals in $\mathrm {HOD}$ while preserving $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinals. For example, let K be such that $K(\lambda )$ is the least singular cardinal in $\mathrm {HOD}$ greater than $\lambda $ , i.e., $K(\lambda )=(\lambda ^{+\omega })^{\mathrm {HOD}}$ . It is easily seen that K, and therefore also $\mathbb {P}_K$ as defined above, are $\Delta _2$ -definable. Then we have the following.

Corollary 8.12. For each $n\geq 1$ , $\mathbb {P}_K$ preserves $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinals and forces $\text {"}\forall \lambda \in \mathrm {Reg}\,((\lambda ^{+\omega })^{\mathrm {HOD}}<\lambda ^+).\text {"}$

8.3 On diamonds

Other combinatorial statements that we can force while preserving $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinals are the diamond principles $\diamondsuit _S$ . Namely, given a stationary set $S\subseteq \kappa $ , a sequence $\langle A_\alpha :\,\alpha \in S\rangle $ is a $\diamondsuit _S$ -sequence if $A_\alpha \subseteq \alpha $ and for every $A\subseteq \kappa $ the set $\{\alpha \in S:\, A\cap \alpha =A_\alpha \}$ is stationary. We say that $\diamondsuit _S$ holds if there is a $\diamondsuit _S$ -sequence.

It is well-known that $\mathrm {Add}(\kappa ^+,1)$ automatically forces $\diamondsuit _{S}$ , for every stationary $S\subseteq \kappa ^+$ in $V^{\mathrm {Add}(\kappa ^+,1)}$ . Thus, from Theorem 8.2, we obtain:

Corollary 8.13.

  1. (1) If $\mathrm {ORD}$ is $\mathbf {\Sigma _2}$ - $2$ -Mahlo and $\delta $ is a supercompact cardinal, then there is a generic extension where $\delta $ is still supercompact and $\diamondsuit _{S}$ holds for every cardinal $\kappa $ and every stationary $S\subseteq \kappa ^+$ .

  2. (2) If $n\geq 1$ and $\delta $ is a $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinal, there is a generic extension where $\delta $ is $C^{(n)}$ -extendible and $\diamondsuit _{S}$ holds for every cardinal $\kappa $ and every stationary $S\subseteq \kappa ^+$ .

Hence, if $\mathrm {VP}$ holds in $\mathrm {V}$ , there is a generic extension where $\mathrm {VP}$ holds together with $\diamondsuit _{S}$ , for every $\kappa $ and every stationary $S\subseteq \kappa ^+$ .

Another relevant diamond principle is the so-called $\diamondsuit ^+_{\kappa ^+}$ -principle.

A sequence $\langle \mathcal {A}_\alpha :\,\alpha \in \kappa ^+\rangle $ is a $\diamondsuit ^+_{\kappa ^+}$ -sequence if $\mathcal {A}_\alpha \in [\mathcal {P}(\alpha )]^{\leq \kappa }$ and for every $A\subseteq \kappa ^+$ there is a club $C\subseteq \kappa ^+$ such that

$$ \begin{align*}C\subseteq\{\alpha\in \kappa^+\mid \, A\cap \alpha\in \mathcal{A}_\alpha\,\wedge\, C\cap \alpha\in \mathcal{A}_\alpha\}.\end{align*} $$

We say that $\diamondsuit ^+_{\kappa ^+}$ holds if there is a $\diamondsuit ^+_{\kappa ^+}$ -sequence.

In [Reference Cummings, Foreman and Magidor10, Theorem 12.2] it is shown that, assuming $2^\kappa =\kappa ^+$ and $2^{\kappa ^+}=\kappa ^{++}$ , there is a $\kappa ^+$ -closed and $\kappa ^{++}$ -cc forcing notion that forces $\diamondsuit ^+_{\kappa ^+}$ . The forcing is an iteration $\mathbb {D}^+_{\kappa ^{++}}=\langle \mathbb {P}_\alpha ,\dot {\mathbb {Q}}_\beta : \beta <\alpha \leq \kappa ^{++}\rangle $ with supports of size $\leq \kappa $ , where $\mathbb {P}_0$ is the natural forcing notion that introduces a sequence $\vec {\mathcal {A}}$ of the right form whereas the rest of the iterates forces the club sets $C\subseteq \kappa ^+$ witnessing that $\vec {\mathcal {A}}$ is a $\diamondsuit ^+_{\kappa ^+}$ -sequence.

Arguing as in Lemma 8.1 one has the following:

Lemma 8.14. Assume the $\mathrm {GCH}$ holds and that $\mathrm {ORD}$ is $\mathbf {\Sigma _2}$ - $2$ -Mahlo. Let $\mathbb {D}$ be the standard Easton support iteration of the forcings $\mathbb {D}^{+}_{\kappa ^{++}}$ , for $\kappa $ a cardinal. Then $\mathbb {D}$ is fitting and $C(\mathbb {P})$ contains all supercompact cardinals, in case there are any.

Theorem 8.15. Assume the $\mathrm {GCH}$ holds.

  1. (1) If $\mathrm {ORD}$ is $\mathbf {\Sigma _2}$ - $2$ -Mahlo and $\delta $ is a supercompact cardinal, then forcing with $\mathbb {D}$ preserves the supercompactness of $\delta $ and yields a generic extension where $\diamondsuit ^+_{\kappa ^+}$ holds, for every cardinal $\kappa $ .

  2. (2) If $n\geq 1$ and $\delta $ is a $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinal, then forcing with $\mathbb {D}$ preserves the $C^{(n)}$ -extendibility of $\delta $ and yields a generic extension where $\diamondsuit ^+_{\kappa ^+}$ holds, for every cardinal $\kappa $ .

Hence, if $\mathrm {VP}$ and the $\mathrm {GCH}$ hold in $\mathrm {V}$ , then $\mathrm {VP}$ also holds in $V^{\mathbb {D}}$ , together with $\diamondsuit _{\kappa ^+}^+$ , for every cardinal $\kappa $ .

The claim of the theorem above referring to $\mathrm {VP}$ was first proved by Brooke-Taylor in [Reference Brooke-Taylor8, Corollary 26]

8.4 On weak square sequences

A classical result due to Solovay is that Jensen’s square principle $\square _\lambda $ must fail for every cardinal $\lambda $ greater than or equal to the first strongly compact cardinal [Reference Solovay25]. This result was subsequently refined by Jensen, who proved that $\square _\lambda $ fails for any subcompact cardinal $\lambda $ , a much weaker notion than supercompactness. Further sharper results are due to Brooke-Taylor and Friedman [Reference Brooke-Taylor and Friedman9] and to Bagaria and Magidor [Reference Bagaria and Magidor5]. In our context, namely with the existence of extendible cardinals, and therefore with the failure of $\square _\lambda $ for a tail of $\lambda $ ’s, we shall consider $\square _{\lambda ,\mu }$ -principles, a weak form of the square principle introduced by Schimmerling in [Reference Schimmerling24].

Following up on Solovay’s work, Shelah proved that if $\kappa $ is supercompact and $\mathrm {cof}(\lambda )<\kappa <\lambda $ , then $\square _{\lambda ,\lambda }$ (also known as $\square ^*_\lambda $ ) fails [Reference Cummings, Foreman and Magidor10, Section 2]. Also, Burke and Kanamori showed that if $\kappa $ is $\lambda ^+$ -strongly compact, then $\square _{\lambda ,<\mathrm {cof}(\lambda )}$ fails [Reference Cummings, Foreman and Magidor10].Footnote 12 The remaining cases, namely $\square _{\lambda ,\mu }$ with $\kappa \leq \mathrm {cof}(\lambda )\leq \mu \leq \lambda $ turned out to be consistent with the existence of a supercompact cardinal $\kappa $ [Reference Cummings, Foreman and Magidor10, Section 9]. Specifically, in [Reference Cummings, Foreman and Magidor10, Theorem 9.2], the authors define, for each $\kappa \leq \mathrm {cof}(\lambda )<\lambda $ , a forcing notion $\mathbb {S}_\lambda $ which forces $\square _{\lambda , \mathrm {cof}(\lambda )}$ and is $\mathrm {cof}(\lambda )$ -directed closed and $\lambda $ -strategically closed. Thus, if $\kappa $ is Laver-indestructible, then forcing with $\mathbb {S}_\lambda $ preserves the supercompactness of $\kappa $ . In this section we shall extend this result to $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinals.

Let K be the class function with $\text {dom}\,(K)=\mathrm {Card}\setminus \aleph _1$ , such that $K(\lambda ):= \text {"The first singular cardinal of cofinality } \lambda ^+.\text {"}$ Observe that K is $\Delta _2$ -definable. Now let $\mathbb {P}_K$ be denote the direct limit of $\langle \mathbb {P}_\alpha ;\dot {\mathbb {Q}}_\alpha :\,\alpha \in \mathrm {ORD}\rangle $ , the iteration with Easton support where $\mathbb {P}_0$ is the trivial forcing and for every $\alpha $ , if $\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}_\alpha }\text {"}\alpha \in \dot {\mathrm {Card}}\setminus \dot {\aleph }_1,\text {"}$ then $\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}_\alpha }\text {"}\dot {\mathbb {Q}}_\alpha =\dot {\mathbb {S}}_{K(\alpha )},\text {"}$ and otherwise.

Remark 8.16. For every $\alpha $ , if $\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}_\alpha } \text {"}\alpha \in \dot {\mathrm {Card}}\setminus \dot {\aleph }_1,\text {"}$ then $\mathbb {P}_{[\alpha ,\mathrm {ORD})}$ is $\alpha ^+$ -directed closed and $K(\alpha )$ -strategically closed.

We now prove that $\mathbb {P}_K$ forces class many instances of $\square _{K(\lambda ),\lambda ^+}$ .

Lemma 8.17. $\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}}\text {"}\forall \lambda \geq \dot {\aleph }_1\,(\square _{K(\lambda ),\lambda ^+} \text { holds}).\text {"}$

Proof Suppose $\lambda $ is an uncountable cardinal in $V^{\mathbb {P}}$ . Then, by the above remark, $\lambda $ is also an uncountable cardinal in $V^{\mathbb {P}_\lambda }$ , hence $\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}_\lambda }\text {"}\dot {\mathbb {Q}}_\lambda =\dot {\mathbb {S}}_{K(\lambda )}.\text {"}$ Thus, $\square _{K(\lambda ),\lambda ^+}$ holds in $V^{\mathbb {P}_{\lambda +1}}$ . Again, by the above remark, $\mathbb {P}_{[\lambda +1,\mathrm {ORD})}$ is distributive enough to preserve $\square _{K(\lambda ),\lambda ^+}$ .

Arguing as in Lemma 8.3 we can show that $\mathbb {P}_K$ is a fitting iteration. Precisely, we have the following:

Lemma 8.18. Assume $\mathrm {ORD}$ is $\mathbf {\Sigma _2}$ - $2$ -Mahlo. Then $\mathbb {P}_K$ is fitting and $C(\mathbb {P})$ contains all supercompact cardinals, in case there are any.

Theorem 8.19.

  1. (1) If $\mathrm {ORD}$ is $\mathbf {\Sigma _2}$ - $2$ -Mahlo, then $\mathbb {P}_K$ preserves supercompact cardinals.

  2. (2) For each $n\geq 1$ , forcing with $\mathbb {P}_K$ preserves $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinals.

Moreover, in any generic extension by $\mathbb {P}_K$ the following holds $:$ for every uncountable cardinal $\lambda $ , if $K(\lambda )$ is the first singular cardinal of cofinality $\lambda ^+$ , then $\square _{K(\lambda ),\lambda ^+}$ holds.

Corollary 8.20. If $\mathrm {VP}$ holds, then there is a class forcing iteration that preserves $\mathrm {VP}$ and forces $\square _{\lambda ,\mathrm {cof}(\lambda )}$ , for a proper class of singular cardinals $\lambda $ .

9 General class forcing iterations

In this section we follow up the discussion at the end of Section 6 about nonweakly homogeneous suitable iterations. One prominent example is the iteration $\mathbb {P}$ that forces $\mathrm {V}=\mathrm {HOD}$ by coding the universe into the power-set function pattern. This iteration is suitable but not weakly homogenous. One may also want to consider class forcing iterations $\mathbb {P}$ over some model M such that $\mathbb {P}$ is not definable in M. To deal with such general class forcing notions we shall work within the theory $\mathrm {ZFC}_{\mathbb {P}}$ , namely ZFC with the axiom schemata of Separation and Replacement allowing for formulas in the language of set theory with the additional predicate symbol $\mathbb {P}$ .

Definition 9.1 ( $\mathbb {P}$ - $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinal).

For $n\geq 1$ , we say that a cardinal $\delta $ is $\mathbb {P}$ - $C^{(n)}$ -extendible if for every cardinal $\lambda \in C^{(n)}_{\mathbb {P}}$ , $\lambda>\delta $ , there is an ordinal $\theta $ and an elementary embedding

$$ \begin{align*}j: \langle V_\lambda,\in, \mathbb{P}\cap V_\lambda\rangle\rightarrow \langle V_\theta,\in, \mathbb{P}\cap V_\theta\rangle\end{align*} $$

with $\mathrm {crit}(j)=\delta $ , $j(\delta )>\lambda $ , and $j(\delta )\in C^{(n)}$ . If, moreover, we can pick $\theta \in C^{(n)}_{\mathbb {P}}$ , then we say that $\delta $ is $\mathbb {P}$ - $C^{(n)+}$ -extendible.

Similarly, we may also consider the notion of $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _n$ -supercompactness, for a general class $\mathbb {P}$ which is not necessarily definable.

Definition 9.2 ( $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _n$ -supercompactness).

If $n\geq 1$ , then a cardinal $\delta $ is $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _n$ -supercompact if for every $\lambda \in C^{(n)}_{\mathbb {P}}$ greater than $\delta $ , and every $a\in V_\lambda $ there exist $\bar {\delta }<\bar {\lambda }<\delta $ and $\bar {a}\in V_{\bar {\lambda }}$ , and there exists an elementary embedding $j: V_{\bar {\lambda }}\longrightarrow V_\lambda $ such that:

  • $\mathrm {crit}(j)=\bar {\delta }$ and $j(\bar {\delta })=\delta $ .

  • $j(\bar {a})=a$ .

  • $\bar {\lambda }\in C^{(n)}_{\mathbb {P}}$ .

The same arguments as in the proof of Theorem 2.4 yield the following equivalence.

Theorem 9.3. For every $n\geq 1$ , every class $\mathbb {P}$ , and every cardinal $\kappa $ , the following are equivalent $:$

  1. (1) $\kappa $ is $\mathbb {P}$ - $C^{(n)}$ -extendible.

  2. (2) $\kappa $ is $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -supercompact.

  3. (3) $\kappa $ is $\mathbb {P}$ - $C^{(n)+}$ -extendible.Footnote 13

We will say that a cardinal $\delta $ is $\mathbb {P}$ - $C^{(n)}$ -extendible with $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _n$ -reflecting target if in Definition 9.1 we may moreover require that $j(\delta )$ is $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _n$ -reflecting (cf. Definition 3.15). Likewise, one defines the notion of $\mathbb {P}$ - $C^{(n)+}$ -extendible with $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _n$ -reflecting target. Arguing as usual one can check that both notions are equivalent.

Clearly, any $\mathbb {P}$ - $C^{(n)+}$ -extendible with $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _n$ -reflecting target is $C^{(n)}$ -extendible. Moreover, if the predicate $\mathbb {P}$ is definable with low complexity and satisfies some minor requirements, then, as the next proposition shows, a cardinal is $\mathbb {P}$ - $C^{(n)+}$ -extendible with $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _n$ -reflecting target if and only if is $C^{(n)}$ -extendible.

Proposition 9.4. Let $n,m\geq 1$ with $m\leq n$ . Let $\mathbb {P}$ be a $\Delta _{m+1}$ -definable $\operatorname {\mathrm {ORD}}$ -length forcing iteration and assume that

$$ \begin{align*} \{\kappa\mid \mathbb{P}\cap V_\kappa=\mathbb{P}_\kappa\,\wedge\,\kappa \text{ is } \mathbb{P}\text{-reflecting}\} \end{align*} $$

is a proper class containing all $C^{(n-2)}$ -extendible cardinals.Footnote 14 Then, every $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinal belonging to $C^{(m+n+1)}$ is $\mathbb {P}$ - $C^{(n)+}$ -extendible with $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _n$ -reflecting target.

In particular, if $\mathbb {P}$ is $\Delta _2$ -definable, a cardinal is $C^{(n)}$ -extendible if and only if it is $\mathbb {P}$ - $C^{(n)+}$ -extendible with $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _n$ -reflecting target.

Proof Let $\delta $ be a $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinal in $C^{(m+n+1)}$ .

Claim 9.4.1. $\delta $ is $\mathbb {P}$ - $C^{(n)}$ -extendible.

Proof of claim Let $\mu>\lambda >\delta $ be with $\lambda \in C^{(n)}_{\mathbb {P}}$ and $\mu \in C^{(n)}$ . Since $\delta $ is actually $C^{(n)+}$ -extendible (cf. Remark 2.5) we may pick $\eta \in C^{(n)}$ together with an elementary embedding $j\colon V_\mu \rightarrow V_{\eta }$ with $\mathrm {crit}(j)=\delta $ , $j(\delta )>\mu $ , and $j(\delta )\in C^{(n)}$ . Observe that $V_{j(\lambda )}\prec _{\Sigma _n} V_\eta \prec _{\Sigma _n} V$ , hence

$$ \begin{align*}j(\langle V_\lambda,\in,\mathbb{P}^{V_\lambda}\rangle)=\langle V_{j(\lambda)},\in, \mathbb{P}^{V_{j(\lambda)}}\rangle=\langle V_{j(\lambda)},\in, \mathbb{P}\cap V_{j(\lambda)}\rangle,\end{align*} $$

where the right-most equality follows from $\Delta _{m+1}$ -definability of $\mathbb {P}$ and $m\leq n$ . Altogether, $j\upharpoonright \langle V_\lambda ,\in ,\mathbb {P}\cap V_\lambda \rangle $ yields the desired embedding.

By Theorem 9.3, $\delta $ is actually $\mathbb {P}$ - $C^{(n)+}$ -extendible, so we concentrate on proving the other assertion. Let $\lambda \in C^{(n)}_{\mathbb {P}}$ with $\lambda>\delta $ , together with an elementary embedding

$$ \begin{align*}j\colon \langle V_\lambda,\in,\mathbb{P}\cap V_\lambda\rangle\rightarrow \langle V_\theta,\in,\mathbb{P}\cap V_\theta\rangle,\end{align*} $$

with $\mathrm {crit}(j)=\delta $ , $\theta \in C^{(n)}_{\mathbb {P}}$ , $j(\delta )>\lambda $ , and $j(\delta )\in C^{(n)}$ . Note that $j(\delta )$ is $C^{(n-2)}$ -extendible hence $\mathbb {P}$ -reflecting and a witness for $\mathbb {P}\cap V_{j(\delta )}=\mathbb {P}_{j(\delta )}$ .

Claim 9.4.2. $j(\delta )\in C^{(n)}_{\mathbb {P}}$ .

Proof of Claim Since $\mathbb {P}$ is $\Delta _{m+1}$ -definable, $C^{(n)}_{\mathbb {P}}$ is a $\Pi _{n+m}$ -definable club class (cf. Proposition 3.9). In particular, as $\delta \in C^{(n+m+1)}$ , $\delta $ is an accumulation point of $C^{(n)}_{\mathbb {P}}$ and thus a member of $C^{(n)}_{\mathbb {P}}$ .

Since $\mathbb {P}$ is $\Delta _{m+1}$ , $m\leq n$ and $\delta ,\lambda \in C^{(n)}_{\mathbb {P}}$ , $\langle V_\delta ,\in , \mathbb {P}^{V_\delta }\rangle \prec _{\Sigma _n}\langle V_\lambda ,\in ,\mathbb {P}^{V_\lambda }\rangle $ . By elementarity, $\langle V_{j(\delta )},\in , \mathbb {P}^{V_{j(\delta )}}\rangle \prec _{\Sigma _n}\langle V_\theta ,\in ,\mathbb {P}^{V_\theta }\rangle $ and so, since $\theta \in C^{(n)}_{\mathbb {P}}$ , $\langle V_{j(\delta )},\in , \mathbb {P}^{V_{j(\delta )}}\rangle \prec _{\Sigma _n}\langle V,\in ,\mathbb {P}\rangle $ . Once again, since $\mathbb {P}$ is $\Delta _{m+1}$ -definable, $m\leq n$ and $j(\delta )\in C^{(n)}$ , $\mathbb {P}^{V_{j(\delta )}}=\mathbb {P}\cap V_{j(\delta )}$ , hence $j(\delta )\in C^{(n)}_{\mathbb {P}}$ .

The above claims combined give the proof of the proposition.

The main result of the section is the following:

Theorem 9.5. Let $\mathbb {P}$ be a $($ not necessarily definable) suitable iteration. Assume that there is a proper class of $\mathbb {P}$ -reflecting cardinals $\lambda $ such that $\mathbb {P}_\lambda =\mathbb {P}\cap V_\lambda $ .Footnote 15 For each $n\geq 1$ , if $\delta $ is $\mathbb {P}$ - $C^{(n)}$ -extendible with $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _n$ -reflecting target then

$$ \begin{align*} \Vdash _{\mathbb{P}}\text{"}\delta \text{ is } C^{(n)}\text{-extendible."} \end{align*} $$

Actually for $n=1$ the above is true by just assuming that $\delta $ is $\mathbb {P}$ - $C^{(1)}$ -extendible.

Proof Let $\lambda>\delta $ be $\mathbb {P}$ -reflecting and such that $\mathbb {P}_\lambda =\mathbb {P}\cap V_\lambda $ . It will be sufficient to prove that if $G_\lambda $ is $\mathbb {P}_\lambda $ -generic over $\mathrm {V}$ , then in the generic extension $V[G_\lambda ]$ , the set D of conditions $r\in \mathbb {P}_{[\lambda ,Ord)}$ that force the existence of an elementary embedding

$$ \begin{align*}j:V[G_\lambda][\dot{G}_{[\lambda, Ord)}]_\lambda\to V[G_\lambda][\dot{G}_{[\lambda, Ord)}]_\theta,\end{align*} $$

some $\theta $ , with $\mathrm {crit}(j)=\delta $ , $j(\delta )>\lambda $ , and $j(\delta )\in C^{(n)}$ , is dense in $\mathbb {P}_{[\lambda ,Ord)}$ .

In $V[G_\lambda ]$ , let r be a condition in $\mathbb {P}_{[\lambda ,Ord)}$ . Back in $\mathrm {V}$ , let $\mu \in C^{(n)}_{\mathbb {P}}$ be greater than $\lambda $ and such that

$$ \begin{align*} \Vdash_{\mathbb{P}_\mu}\text{"}\mathbb{P}_{[\mu,Ord)} \text{ is } |\mathbb{P}_\lambda|^+\text{-directed closed."} \end{align*} $$

Since $\delta $ is $\mathbb {P}$ - $C^{(n)+}$ -extendible with $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _n$ -reflecting target, in the ground model $\mathrm {V}$ there exists an elementary embedding

$$ \begin{align*} j: \langle V_\mu, \in ,\mathbb{P}\cap V_\mu\rangle\rightarrow \langle V_\theta, \in ,\mathbb{P}\cap V_\theta\rangle \end{align*} $$

with $\mathrm {crit}(j)=\delta $ such that $j(\delta )>\mu $ , $\theta \in C^{(n)}_{\mathbb {P}}$ , and $ j(\delta )$ being $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _n$ -reflecting.

For each $q\in \mathbb {P}_\lambda $ there is an ordinal $\alpha <\delta $ such that $\text {supp}\,(q)\cap \delta \subseteq \alpha $ . Hence, $\text {supp}\,(j(q))\cap j(\delta )\subseteq \alpha $ , and so $j(q)$ is a $\mathbb {P}_{j(\lambda )}$ -condition such that

Since $\mu <j(\delta )$ we have that $\text {supp}\,(j(q))\cap [\lambda ,\mu ) =\varnothing $ . So, by our choice of the ordinal $\mu $ , in $V[G_\lambda ]$ we can take $r^*\in \mathbb {P}_{[\mu , Ord)}$ such that

$$ \begin{align*}\Vdash_{\mathbb{P}_{[\lambda ,\mu)}}\text{"}r^*\leq j(q)\upharpoonright [\mu, j(\lambda))\text{"}\end{align*} $$

for all $q\in G_\lambda $ . Then, the condition $r\wedge r^\ast $ such that

$$ \begin{align*}(r\wedge r^*)(\beta):=\left\{\begin{array}{ccc} r(\beta)& \text{if}& \beta\in [\lambda,\mu),\\ r^*(\beta)& \text{if}& \beta\in[\mu, j(\lambda)) \end{array}\right.\end{align*} $$

is well-defined and works as a master condition for j and the forcing $\mathbb {P}_{j(\lambda )}/G_\lambda $ , because

$$ \begin{align*} r\wedge r^*\Vdash_{\mathbb{P}_{j(\lambda)}/G_\lambda} j\text{"}G_\lambda\subseteq \dot{G}_{j(\lambda)}. \end{align*} $$

Thus, for any $\mathbb {P}_{j(\lambda )}$ -generic filter $G_{j(\lambda )}$ over $\mathrm {V}$ extending $G_\lambda $ and containing $r\wedge r^\ast $ , the elementary embedding

$$ \begin{align*} j\restriction V_\lambda : \langle V_\lambda, \in , \mathbb{P}\cap V_\lambda \rangle \to \langle V_{j(\lambda)}, \in , \mathbb{P}\cap V_{j(\lambda)} \rangle \end{align*} $$

lifts to an elementary embedding

$$ \begin{align*} j^\ast: \langle V_\lambda[G_\lambda], \in , \mathbb{P}\cap V_\lambda[G_\lambda] \rangle \to \langle V_{j(\lambda)}[G_{j(\lambda)}], \in , \mathbb{P}\cap V_{j(\lambda)}[G_{j(\lambda)}] \rangle. \end{align*} $$

Now, since $\lambda $ is $\mathbb {P}$ -reflecting, $\mathbb {P}$ forces that $V_\lambda [\dot {G}_\lambda ]=V[\dot {G}]_\lambda $ . Hence, by the choice of $\mu $ , the same is forced by $\mathbb {P}_\mu $ . By the elementarity of j, the structure $\langle V_\theta , \in ,\mathbb {P}\cap V_\theta \rangle $ thinks that the forcing $\mathbb {P}\cap V_\theta $ forces $V_{j(\lambda )}[\dot {G}_{j(\lambda )}]=V[\dot {G}]_{j(\lambda )}$ . So, since $\theta \in C^{(n)}_{\mathbb {P}}$ , $\mathbb {P}$ forces the same. Also, since $j(\delta )$ is $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _n$ -reflecting in $\mathrm {V}$ and $V_{j(\delta )}\models \mathrm {ZFC}$ , Lemma 3.16 yields

$$ \begin{align*} \Vdash _{\mathbb{P}}\text{"}j^*(\delta)\in\dot{C}^{(n)}.\text{"} \end{align*} $$

We have thus found a condition below r, namely $r\wedge r^\ast $ , forcing the existence of an elementary embedding

$$ \begin{align*} j^\ast: \langle V[\dot{G}]_\lambda, \in , \mathbb{P}\cap V[\dot{G}] _\lambda\rangle \to \langle V[\dot{G}]_{j(\lambda)}, \in , \mathbb{P}\cap V[\dot{G}]_{j(\lambda)} \rangle \end{align*} $$

with $\mathrm {crit}(j^\ast )=\delta $ , $j^\ast (\delta )>\lambda $ , and $j^\ast (\delta )\in C^{(n)}$ , as wanted.

9.1 $\mathrm {VP}$ and non-homogeneous suitable iterations

We now use Theorem 9.5 to prove Theorem 6.6 without the homogeneity assumption on $\mathbb {P}$ , hence yielding the desired refinement of Brooke-Taylor’s main theorem of [Reference Brooke-Taylor8].

Theorem 9.6. Let $n,m\geq 1$ with $m\leq n$ . Let $\mathbb {P}$ be a $\Delta _{m+1}$ -definable suitable iteration. If $\mathrm {VP}(\mathbf {\Pi _{m+n+1})}$ holds then $V^{\mathbb {P}}\models \mathrm {VP}(\mathbf {\Pi _{n+1}})$ .

In particular, if $\mathrm {VP}$ holds and $\mathbb {P}$ is a definable suitable iteration, then

$$ \begin{align*} V^{\mathbb{P}}\models \mathrm{VP}. \end{align*} $$

Proof By Theorem 6.2, $\mathrm {VP}(\mathbf {\Pi _{m+n+1})}$ yields the existence of a proper class of $C^{(m+n)}$ -extendible cardinals. Also, by Theorem 6.5, it entails the existence of a proper class of $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -reflecting cardinals, hence a proper class of $\mathbb {P}$ -reflecting cardinals $\lambda $ such that $\mathbb {P}_\lambda =\mathbb {P}\cap V_\lambda $ . In particular, the assumptions of Theorem 9.6 are met.

Claim 9.6.1. For each $n\geq 2$ , every $C^{(m+n)}$ -extendible is $\mathbb {P}$ - $C^{(n)}$ -extendible with $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _n$ -reflecting target.

Proof of claim If $\delta $ is $C^{(m+n)}$ -extendible then it is $C^{(n)}$ -extendible and $\Sigma _{m+n+2}$ -correct. Thus, Claim 9.4.2 implies that $\delta $ is $\mathbb {P}$ - $C^{(n)}$ -extendible.

Let $\lambda \in C^{(n)}_{\mathbb {P}}$ be with $\lambda>\theta $ . By $\mathbb {P}$ - $C^{(n)+}$ -extendibility of $\delta $ , there is $\theta \in C^{(n)}_{\mathbb {P}}$ and an elementary embedding

$$ \begin{align*} j: \langle V_\lambda,\in,\mathbb{P}\cap V_\lambda\rangle\rightarrow \langle V_\theta,\in,\mathbb{P}\cap V_\theta\rangle, \end{align*} $$

with $\mathrm {crit}(j)=\delta $ , $j(\delta )>\lambda $ , and $j(\delta )\in C^{(n)}$ .

Subclaim 9.6.1.1. $j(\delta )$ is $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _n$ -reflecting.

Proof of subclaim Since $\delta $ is $C^{(n+m)}$ -extendible, hence $C^{(n)}$ -extendible and $\delta \in C^{(n+m+1)}$ , Claim 9.4.2 yields $j(\delta )\in C^{(n)}_{\mathbb {P}}$ . Let us now check that $\mathbb {P}_{j(\delta )}=\mathbb {P}\cap V_{j(\delta )}$ and that $j(\delta )$ is $\mathbb {P}$ -reflecting.

For each $\alpha <j(\delta )$ the formula

$$ \begin{align*} \exists \beta\,\exists X\,(\beta>\alpha\,\wedge\, X=V_\beta\,\wedge\, \mathbb{P}_\alpha\subseteq V_\beta) \end{align*} $$

is $\Sigma _{m+1}$ , with parameter $\alpha $ . Since $j(\delta )\in C^{(n+m)}$ , for each $\alpha <j(\delta )$ there is $\alpha <\beta <j(\delta )$ witnessing the above. Combining this with the $\Delta _{m+1}$ -definability of $\mathbb {P}$ and with $1\leq m\leq n$ it follows that

$$ \begin{align*} \mathbb{P}_{j(\delta)}=\mathbb{P}\cap V_{j(\delta)}=\mathbb{P}^{V_{j(\delta)}}. \end{align*} $$

Let us now prove that $j(\delta )$ is $\mathbb {P}$ -reflecting by showing that all the assumptions of Proposition 3.4 are met. First, $j(\delta )$ is inaccessible (actually, Mahlo) and by the above displayed expression $\mathbb {P}$ is a forcing iteration such that $\mathbb {P}_{j(\delta )}\subseteq V_{j(\delta )}$ . Second, thanks to the Mahloness of $j(\delta )$ , the iteration $\mathbb {P}_{j(\delta )}$ is $j(\delta )$ -cc and so it is not hard to show that $\mathbb {P}_{j(\delta )}$ preserves the inaccessibility of $j(\delta )$ . Finally, we claim that $j(\delta )\in C(\mathbb {P})$ , and so that $\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}_{j(\delta )}}\text {"}\mathbb {P}_{[j(\delta ),\operatorname {\mathrm {ORD}})} \text { is } j(\delta )\text {-distributive."}$

Indeed, arguing as in the proof of Theorem 5.4 and using that the cardinal $j(\delta )$ is $\Sigma _{m+n}$ -correct, hence $\Sigma _{m+2}$ -correct, one infers that $j(\delta )$ is an accumulation point of $C(\mathbb {P})$ , hence $j(\delta )\in C(\mathbb {P})$ .Footnote 16

This shows that $\delta $ is $\mathbb {P}$ - $C^{(n)}$ -extendible with $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _n$ -reflecting target.

For simplicity let us assume that $n\geq 2$ , as the argument for $n=1$ is the same. The above claim alongside the previous comments implies the existence of a proper class of $\mathbb {P}$ - $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinals with $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _n$ -reflecting target, hence Theorem 9.5 yields the existence of a proper class of $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinals in $V^{\mathbb {P}}$ and so $V^{\mathbb {P}}\models \mathrm {VP}(\mathbf {\Pi _{n+1}})$ .

9.2 On $\mathrm {V=HOD}$ and the Ground Axiom

The first forcing iteration producing a generic extension where $\mathrm {V}=\mathrm {HOD}$ holds was defined by McAloon [Reference McAloon22]. The idea is to code the universe into the power-set function pattern so that all sets become definable using ordinals as parameters. For more sophisticated codings see [Reference Brooke-Taylor7].

For the purposes of the current section we may also assume that the GCH holds, for otherwise we can force it while preserving $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinals (cf. Theorem 8.4).

Let $\mathbb {P}$ be the class forcing notion from [Reference Reitz23, Theorem 3.3]. It is easy to see that $\mathbb {P}$ is $\Delta _2$ -definable and that the class of $\mathbb {P}$ -reflecting cardinals $\kappa $ such that $ \mathbb {P}\cap V_\kappa =\mathbb {P}_\kappa $ contains all Mahlo cardinals, if there are any. Moreover, if there is a $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinal, there are class many Mahlo cardinals, hence the above class is proper, and every $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinal is also $\mathbb {P}$ - $C^{(n)}$ -extendible with $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _n$ -reflecting target (see Proposition 9.4). Thus $\mathbb {P}$ fulfils the assumptions of Theorem 9.5. As the GCH holds, $\mathbb {P}$ yields a cardinal-preserving generic extension in which the Continuum Coding Axiom (CCA) holds, hence where $\mathrm {V}=\mathrm {HOD}$ holds [Reference Reitz23, Theorem 3.3]. Altogether, we obtain the following, which extends [Reference Reitz23, Theorem 3.9].

Corollary 9.7. Forcing with $\mathbb {P}$ produces a generic extension of $\mathrm {CCA}+\neg \mathrm {GCH}$ and preserves $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinals, for $n\geq 1$ . In particular, $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinals are consistent with $\mathrm {V=HOD}$ .

Likewise, the following extends [Reference Hamkins, Reitz and Woodin14, Corollary 4]:

Corollary 9.8. There is a class iteration forcing “ $\text {V}\neq \text {HOD}+\text {GA}$ ” and preserving $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinals, for $n\geq 1$ .

Proof Let $\mathbb {P}$ be the forcing iteration of Corollary 9.7 and let $\dot {\mathbb {Q}}$ be a $\mathbb {P}$ -name for the iteration with Easton support that forces with $\mathrm {Add}(\kappa ,1)$ at each regular cardinal $\kappa $ such that $2^{<\kappa }=\kappa $ . Set $\mathbb {R}:=\mathbb {P}\ast \dot {\mathbb {Q}}$ . By the argument in [Reference Hamkins, Reitz and Woodin14, Theorem 3], $V^{\mathbb {R}}\models \text {"V}\neq \text {HOD}+\text {GA."}$ Since $\mathbb {R}$ is $\Delta _2$ -definable and the class of $\mathbb {R}$ -reflecting cardinals $\kappa $ such that $ \mathbb {R}\cap V_\kappa =\mathbb {R}_\kappa $ contains all Mahlo cardinals, every $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinal is $\mathbb {P}$ - $C^{(n)}$ -extendible with $\mathbb {P}$ - $\Sigma _n$ -reflecting target. As $\mathbb {R}$ satisfies the hypotheses of Theorem 9.5, the result follows.

Acknowledgments

The authors are grateful to the anonymous referee for his valuable suggestions on previous versions of the manuscript. This gratitude is extended to Hiroshi Sakai for his very efficient task as editor. The research work of both authors was supported by the Spanish Government under grant MTM2017-86777-P, and by the Generalitat de Catalunya (Catalan Government) under grant SGR 270-2017. The research of the second author has also been supported by MECD Grant FPU15/00026.

Footnotes

1 Magidor’s original characterization does not require that $\lambda $ and $\bar {\lambda }$ are in $C^{(1)}$ , or that for every $a\in V_\lambda $ there is $\bar {a}\in V_{\bar {\lambda }}$ with $j(\bar {a})=a$ .

2 We are interested in the case $\mathbb {P}$ is a class-forcing iteration, but the definition as well as the next proposition make sense and hold also for any predicate $\mathbb {P}$ .

3 See Remark 3.5.

4 Recall that an Easton support iteration is a forcing iteration where direct limits are taken at inaccessible stages and inverse limits elsewhere.

5 That is, $\Gamma _n$ -definable with parameters (see Notation 3.8).

6 The lightface version of the statement also holds.

7 For the definition of $C(\mathbb {P})$ , see Proposition 5.2.

8 Here $\dot {\mathbb {P}}_{[\delta ,\sigma ]}$ is a $\mathbb {P}_\delta $ -name for the iteration $\mathbb {Q}$ up to $\sigma $ .

9 By convention, a cardinal is $C^{(0)}$ -extendible iff it is supercompact (cf. page 20).

10 An ad hoc argument for Jensen’s iteration can be composed to show that it preserves supercompact cardinals without the assumption, used in Lemma 8.1, of $\mathrm {ORD}$ being $\mathbf {\Sigma _2}$ - $2$ -Mahlo. Nevertheless, the arguments given in the lemma also apply to other class forcing iterations considered in the subsections below.

11 The GCH assumption is superfluous if we are only interested in preserving $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinals, $n\geq 1$ , for in that case we may first force the GCH while preserving $C^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinals (cf. Theorem 8.2).

12 Note that this is interesting only for $\mathrm {cof}(\lambda )\geq \kappa $ .

13 See Remark 2.5.

14 By convention, a $C^{(-1)}$ -extendible cardinal is a Mahlo cardinal.

15 In particular, $\mathbb {P}$ is adequate (cf. Definition 3.10).

16 Note that here we have used that $n\geq 2$ .

References

Bagaria, J., C (n)-cardinals . Archive for Mathematical Logic , vol. 51 (2012), no. 3, pp. 213240.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bagaria, J., Casacuberta, C., Mathias, A. R. D., and Rosickỳ, J.. Definable orthogonality classes in accessible categories are small . Journal of the European Mathematical Society , vol. 17 (2015), no. 3, pp. 549589.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bagaria, J., Gitman, V., and Schindler, R., Generic Vopěnka’s principle, remarkable cardinals, and the weak proper forcing Axiom . Archive for Mathematical Logic , vol. 56 (2017), nos. 1–2, pp. 120.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bagaria, J., Hamkins, J. D., Tsaprounis, K., and Usuba, T., Superstrong and other large cardinals are never Laver indestructible . Archive for Mathematical Logic , vol. 55 (2016), nos. 1–2, pp. 1935.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bagaria, J. and Magidor, M., On ${\omega}_1$ -strongly compact cardinals, this Journal, vol. 79 (2014), no. 1, pp. 266–278.Google Scholar
Boney, W., Model theoretic characterizations of large cardinals. Israel Journal of Mathematics , vol. 236 (2020), pp. 133181.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brooke-Taylor, A. D., Large cardinals and definable well-orders on the universe, this Journal, vol. 74 (2009), no. 2, pp. 641–654.Google Scholar
Brooke-Taylor, A. D., Indestructibility of Vopěnka’s principle . Archive for Mathematical Logic , vol. 50 (2011), no. 5, pp. 515529.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brooke-Taylor, A. D. and Friedman, S.-D., Subcompact cardinals, squares, and stationary reflection . Israel Journal of Mathematics , vol. 197 (2013), no. 1, pp. 453473.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cummings, J., Foreman, M., and Magidor, M., Squares, scales and stationary reflection . Journal of Mathematical Logic , vol. 1 (2001), no. 1, pp. 3598.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dobrinen, N. and Friedman, S.-D., Homogeneous iteration and measure one covering relative to HOD . Archive for Mathematical Logic , vol. 47 (2008), no. 7, pp. 711718.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Friedman, S.-D., Fine Structure and Class Forcing , Walter de Gruyter, Berlin, 2000.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gitik, M. and Shelah, S., On certain indestructibility of strong cardinals and a question of Hajnal . Archive for Mathematical Logic , vol. 28 (1989), no. 1, pp. 3542.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hamkins, J., Reitz, J., and Woodin, W. H., The ground axiom is consistent with V $\,\ne\,$ HOD . Proceedings of the American Mathematical Society , vol. 136 (2008), no. 8, pp. 29432949.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hamkins, J. D., The lottery preparation . Annals of Pure and Applied Logic , vol. 101 (2000), nos. 2–3, pp. 103146.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jech, T., Set Theory: The Third Millennium Edition, Revised and Expanded , Springer Monographs in Mathematics, vol. 14, Springer, Berlin, 2002.Google Scholar
Jensen, R. B., Measurable cardinals and the GCH , Axiomatic Set Theory (T. J. Jech, editor), Proceedings of Symposia in Pure Mathematics, vol. 13, American Mathematical Society, Providence, RI, 1974, pp. 175178.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kanamori, A., The Higher Infinite , Springer Monographs in Mathematics, Springer, Berlin, 2003.Google Scholar
Laver, R., Making the supercompactness of $\kappa$ indestructible under $\kappa$ -directed closed forcing . Israel Journal of Mathematics , vol. 29 (1978), no. 4, pp. 385388.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lücke, P., Njegomir, A., Holy, P., Krapf, R., and Schlicht, P., Class forcing, the forcing theorem and Boolean completions, this Journal, vol. 81 (2016), no. 4, pp. 1500–1530.Google Scholar
Magidor, M., On the role of supercompact and extendible cardinals in logic . Israel Journal of Mathematics , vol. 10 (1971), no. 2, pp. 147157.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McAloon, K., Consistency results about ordinal definability . Annals of Mathematical Logic , vol. 2 (1971), no. 4, pp. 449467.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reitz, J., The ground Axiom , Ph.D. thesis, The Graduate Center of the City University of New York, 2006.Google Scholar
Schimmerling, E., Combinatorial principles in the core model for one Woodin cardinal . Annals of Pure and Applied Logic , vol. 74 (1995), no. 2, pp. 153201.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Solovay, R. M., Strongly compact cardinals and the GCH , Proceedings of the Tarski Symposium , (L. Henkin, J. Addison, C. C. Chang, W. Craig, D. Scott, and R. Vaught, editors) Proceedings of Symposia in Pure Mathematics, vol. 25, American Mathematical Society, Providence, RI, 1974, pp. 365372.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tsaprounis, K., Large cardinals and resurrection axioms , Ph.D. thesis, Universitat de Barcelona, 2012.Google Scholar
Tsaprounis, K., On extendible cardinals and the GCH . Archive for Mathematical Logic , vol. 52 (2013), nos. 5–6, pp. 593602.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tsaprounis, K., On ${C}^{(n)}$ -extendible cardinals, this Journal, vol. 83 (2018), pp. 1112–1131.Google Scholar
Woodin, W. H., Suitable extender models I . Journal of Mathematical Logic , vol. 10 (2010), no. 01n02, pp. 101339.CrossRefGoogle Scholar