Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-xbtfd Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-20T00:31:05.804Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

MODEL THEORY OF FIELDS WITH FINITE GROUP SCHEME ACTIONS

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  14 March 2022

DANIEL MAX HOFFMANN
Affiliation:
INSTYTUT MATEMATYKI UNIWERSYTET WARSZAWSKI WARSZAWA, POLAND and DEPARTMENT OF MATHEMATICS UNIVERSITY OF NOTRE DAME NOTRE DAME, IN, USA E-mail: [email protected] URL: https://sites.google.com/site/danielmaxhoffmann/home
PIOTR KOWALSKI*
Affiliation:
INSTYTUT MATEMATYCZNY UNIWERSYTET WROCŁAWSKI WROCŁAW, POLAND URL: http://www.math.uni.wroc.pl/~pkowa/
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

We study model theory of fields with actions of a fixed finite group scheme. We prove the existence and simplicity of a model companion of the theory of such actions, which generalizes our previous results about truncated iterative Hasse–Schmidt derivations [13] and about Galois actions [14]. As an application of our methods, we obtain a new model complete theory of actions of a finite group on fields of finite imperfection degree.

Type
Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2022. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Association for Symbolic Logic

1 Introduction

In this paper, we deal with model theory of actions of finite group schemes on fields. Our results here provide a generalization of both the results from [Reference Hoffmann and Kowalski13] (model theory of truncated iterative Hasse–Schmidt derivations on fields) and the results from [Reference Hoffmann and Kowalski14] (model theory of actions of finite groups on fields). We explain below the nature of this generalization.

Let us fix a field $\textbf {k}$ . By a finite group scheme over $\textbf {k}$ , we mean the dual object to a finite-dimensional Hopf algebra over $\textbf {k}$ (see Section 2). Let us fix such a finite group scheme $\mathfrak {g}$ . It is a classical result [Reference Waterhouse29, Section 6.7] that $\mathfrak {g}$ fits into the following short exact sequence:

$$ \begin{align*}1\longrightarrow \mathfrak{g}^{0}\longrightarrow \mathfrak{g}\longrightarrow \mathfrak{g}_{0}\longrightarrow 1,\end{align*} $$

where the finite group scheme $\mathfrak {g}^{0}$ is infinitesimal (that is, its underlying scheme is connected) and the finite group scheme $\mathfrak {g}_{0}$ is étale (that is, it becomes a constant finite group scheme after a finite Galois base extension). As explained in [Reference Hoffmann and Kowalski13], the actions of infinitesimal finite group schemes on fields correspond to truncated iterative Hasse–Schmidt derivations. It is also clear that the actions of constant finite group schemes on fields correspond to actions of finite groups, and the model theory of such actions was analyzed in [Reference Hoffmann and Kowalski14]. It should be clear now that the model theory of actions of finite group schemes, which is the topic of this paper, encompasses the situations from [Reference Hoffmann and Kowalski13, Reference Hoffmann and Kowalski14].

Before describing the main results of this paper, let us compare the structures we consider here with a certain kind of operators on fields. Moosa and Scanlon developed in [Reference Moosa and Scanlon22] a general theory of rings with iterative operators. They analyzed the model theory of fields with such operators in [Reference Moosa and Scanlon24] under two additional assumptions: the base field is of characteristic $0$ and the operators are free (every free operator is inter-definable in a natural way with a certain iterative operator as explained in [Reference Moosa and Scanlon24]). The results from [Reference Moosa and Scanlon24] were extended to an arbitrary characteristic case (still in the free context) in [Reference Beyarslan, Hoffmann, Kamensky and Kowalski1]. The actions of finite group schemes, which are the topic of this paper, are the same as iterative operators in the sense of Moosa–Scanlon for constant iterative systems (as we explain in Section 2), and they should be thought of as “very non-free” iterative operators.

We list here the main results of this paper.

  1. (1) The theory of actions of $\mathfrak {g}$ on fields has a model companion, which we denote by $\mathfrak {g}$ -DCF (Theorem 3.6).

  2. (2) The theory $\mathfrak {g}$ -DCF is simple (Theorem 4.12).

  3. (3) The theory of actions of a finite group G on fields of characteristic $p>0$ and of finite imperfection degree e has a model companion, which is bi-interpretable (after adding finitely many constants) with the theory $(\mathbb {G}_{\text {a}}[1]\times G_{{\mathbb {F}}_{p}})$ -DCF, where $\mathbb {G}_{\text {a}}[1]$ is the kernel of the Frobenius endomorphism on the additive group scheme over the prime field ${\mathbb {F}}_{p}$ (Theorem 5.6).

Coming back to the situation from [Reference Moosa and Scanlon24], we should mention that one can not expect a generalization of the above results to the case of general iterative operators considered in [Reference Moosa and Scanlon24], since the theory of such operators on fields may be not companionable as it is shown in [Reference Beyarslan, Hoffmann, Kamensky and Kowalski1, Reference Moosa and Scanlon24] (we comment more on this issue in Remark 4.13(5)).

This paper is organized as follows. In Section 2, we give the main definitions, provide some examples, and we also discuss the notion of a prolongation with respect to a fixed action of $\mathfrak {g}$ . In Section 3, we show the existence of a model companion of the theory of $\mathfrak {g}$ -actions on fields using the notion of a prolongation from Section 2. In Section 4, we analyze the model-theoretic properties of the theory obtained in Section 3. In particular, we show by the Galois-theoretic methods that this theory is simple. As an application of the results from Sections 3 and 4, we give in Section 5 a new example of a theory fitting to the set-up considered by the first author in [Reference Hoffmann11], that is we prove the existence of a model companion of the theory of actions of a finite group on fields of a fixed finite imperfection degree.

We would like to thank the referee for a useful report.

2 Finite group scheme actions: first-order set-up and prolongations

In this section, we describe our set-up of finite group scheme actions both in the algebraic as well as in the model-theoretic context. Then, we define the notion of a prolongation and collect some technical tools, which will be needed in the sequel.

We fix for the rest of this paper a base field $\textbf {k}$ .

2.1 Finite group scheme actions: definitions and examples

For the necessary background about affine group schemes, their actions, and Hopf algebras, we refer the reader to [Reference Waterhouse29]. All the group schemes considered in this paper will be affine, so we will skip the adjective “affine” from now on. Let us fix a finite group scheme $\mathfrak {g}$ over $\textbf {k}$ . Then $\mathfrak {g}=\operatorname {\mathrm{Spec}}(H)$ , where H is a finite dimensional Hopf algebra over $\textbf {k}$ . We denote the comultiplication in H by $\mu :H\to H\otimes _{\textbf {k}} H$ , and we denote the counit map in H by $\pi :H\to \textbf {k}$ . We also fix the number $e:=\dim _{\textbf {k}}(H)$ , which is called the order of the finite group scheme $\mathfrak {g}$ .

Definition 2.1. We say that R is a $\mathfrak {g}$ -ring, if R is a $\textbf {k}$ -algebra together with a group scheme action of $\mathfrak {g}$ on $\operatorname {\mathrm{Spec}}(R)$ .

Similarly, we define $\mathfrak {g}$ -fields, $\mathfrak {g}$ -morphisms, $\mathfrak {g}$ -extensions, etc.

Remark 2.2. Let R be a $\textbf {k}$ -algebra.

  1. (1) A $\mathfrak {g}$ -ring structure on R is the same as a $\textbf {k}$ -algebra map $\partial :R\to R\otimes _{\textbf {k}} H$ such that $\pi \circ \partial ={\mathrm{id}}_{R}$ (the counit condition) and the following diagram commutes (the coassociativity condition):

    If R is a $\mathfrak {g}$ -ring and we want to emphasize the group scheme action on R, then we say: “ $(R,\partial )$ is a $\mathfrak {g}$ -ring.”
  2. (2) A $\textbf {k}$ -algebra map $\partial :R\to R\otimes _{\textbf {k}} H$ satisfying only the counit condition (from Item $(1)$ above) was called an H-operator in [Reference Beyarslan, Hoffmann, Kamensky and Kowalski1]. This notion originated from [Reference Moosa and Scanlon23, Reference Moosa and Scanlon24] and should be thought of as a “free operator” in the sense that it is free from the coassociativity condition (or the iterativity condition) given by the multiplication in $\mathfrak {g}$ .

Example 2.3. We give below several examples of finite group schemes and we interpret their actions.

  1. (1) For a finite group G, we denote by $G_{\textbf {k}}$ the finite group scheme over $\textbf {k}$ corresponding to G, that is,

    $$ \begin{align*}G_{\textbf{k}}:=\operatorname{\mathrm{Spec}}(\mathrm{Func}(G,\textbf{k})),\end{align*} $$
    where the comultiplication in $\mathrm{Func}(G,\textbf {k})$ comes from the group operation in G. Then, $G_{\textbf {k}}$ -rings coincide with $\textbf {k}$ -algebras with actions of the group G by $\textbf {k}$ -algebra automorphisms.
  2. (2) Let us assume that $\mathrm{char}(\textbf {k})=p>0$ . A truncated group scheme (see [Reference Chase4]) over $\textbf {k}$ is a finite group scheme whose underlying scheme is isomorphic to

    $$ \begin{align*}\operatorname{\mathrm{Spec}}\left(\textbf{k}[X_{1},\ldots,X_{f}]/\left(X_{1}^{p^{m}},\ldots,X_{f}^{p^{m}}\right)\right)\end{align*} $$
    for some $f,m>0$ . If the base field $\textbf {k}$ is perfect, then each infinitesimal group scheme over $\textbf {k}$ is truncated (see e.g., [Reference Demazure and Gabriel9, Corollary 6.3, p. 347]). If $\mathfrak {g}$ is a truncated group scheme, then $(R,\partial )$ is a $\mathfrak {g}$ -ring if and only if $\partial $ is a $\mathfrak {g}$ -derivation on R in the sense of [Reference Hoffmann and Kowalski12, Definition 3.8] (see also [Reference Hoffmann and Kowalski12, Definition 3.9] for an interpretation in terms of m-truncated f-dimensional Hasse–Schmidt derivations on R over $\textbf {k}$ satisfying a “ $\mathfrak {g}$ -iterativity” rule).

    The simplest example of a truncated group scheme is the kernel of the Frobenius morphisms on the additive group scheme over $\textbf {k}$ and we denote this kernel by $\mathbb {G}_{\text {a}}[1]$ . Then, a $\mathbb {G}_{\text {a}}[1]$ -ring is the same as a $\textbf {k}$ -algebra R together with a $\textbf {k}$ -derivation d such that $d^{(p)}=0$ (the composition of d with itself p times).

  3. (3) Let us assume that $\mathfrak {g}=\mathfrak {g}_{1}\times \mathfrak {g}_{2}$ . Then, an action of $\mathfrak {g}$ on a $\textbf {k}$ -scheme X may be understood as an action of $\mathfrak {g}_{1}$ on X together an action of $\mathfrak {g}_{2}$ on X such that these two actions commute with each other.

    In the case when $\mathrm{char}(\textbf {k})=p>0$ and $\mathfrak {g}=\mathbb {G}_{\text {a}}[1]\times G_{\textbf {k}}$ for a finite group G, a $\mathfrak {g}$ -ring R is the same as a derivation d on R such that $d^{(p)}=0$ (see Item $(2)$ above) together with an action of G on R by $\textbf {k}$ -algebra differential automorphisms.

  4. (4) Assume that $\mathfrak {g}$ is a finite étale group scheme. Then, there is a finite Galois extension $\textbf {k}\subseteq \textbf {k}^{\prime }$ such that the group scheme

    $$ \begin{align*}\mathfrak{g}_{\textbf{k}^{\prime}}:=\mathfrak{g}\times {}_{\operatorname{\mathrm{Spec}}(\textbf{k})}\operatorname{\mathrm{Spec}}(\textbf{k}^{\prime})\end{align*} $$
    over $\textbf {k}^{\prime }$ is constant, that is, there is finite group G such that $\mathfrak {g}_{\textbf {k}^{\prime }}\cong G_{\textbf {k}^{\prime }}$ (see e.g., [Reference Waterhouse29, Section 6]).

    As an explicit non-constant example, let us take $\mathfrak {g}$ as the finite group scheme of third roots of unity over ${\mathbb {Q}}$ . That is,

    $$ \begin{align*}\mathfrak{g}=\operatorname{\mathrm{Spec}}({\mathbb{Q}}[\varepsilon]),\ \ \ \ {\mathbb{Q}}[\varepsilon]:={\mathbb{Q}}[X]/(X^{3}-1),\end{align*} $$
    and the counit and the comultiplication in ${\mathbb {Q}}[\varepsilon ]$ are given by:
    $$ \begin{align*}\pi(\varepsilon)=1,\ \ \ \ \ \mu(\varepsilon)=\varepsilon\otimes \varepsilon.\end{align*} $$
    We also have that:
    $$ \begin{align*}\mathfrak{g}_{{\mathbb{Q}}(\zeta)}\cong \left({\mathbb{Z}}/3{\mathbb{Z}}\right)_{{\mathbb{Q}}(\zeta)}\!,\end{align*} $$
    where $\zeta =\exp (2\pi i/3)$ is the third primitive root of unity in ${\mathbb {C}}$ .

    The following ${\mathbb {Q}}$ -algebra map:

    $$ \begin{align*}\partial:{\mathbb{Q}}(\sqrt[3]{2})\longrightarrow {\mathbb{Q}}(\sqrt[3]{2})\otimes_{{\mathbb{Q}}}{\mathbb{Q}}[\varepsilon],\ \ \ \ \ \partial(\sqrt[3]{2}):=\sqrt[3]{2}\otimes \varepsilon\end{align*} $$
    gives ${\mathbb {Q}}(\sqrt [3]{2})$ a $\mathfrak {g}$ -field structure. This action has an obvious functorial description on R-rational points (R is a ${\mathbb {Q}}$ -algebra): the group of third roots of unity in R naturally acts by the ring multiplication on the set of third roots of $2$ in R.

As mentioned in Section 1, we will provide now a comparison between the notion of a $\mathfrak {g}$ -ring considered in this paper and the notion of a $\underline {\mathcal {D}}$ -ring for a generalized Hasse–Schmidt system $\underline {\mathcal {D}}$ from [Reference Moosa and Scanlon22]. In short, the notion considered in [Reference Moosa and Scanlon22] is much more general than ours. A generalized Hasse–Schmidt system $\underline {\mathcal {D}}$ is an inverse system of schemes with scheme morphisms between them, which may be though of as “partial group scheme structures.” Such an idea is also considered in [Reference Kamensky17], where $\underline {\mathcal {D}}$ is replaced with a basically equivalent notion of a formal group scheme, which is a direct system of finite schemes together with some morphisms between them such that they become a group operation on the level of the formal limit. In our case, we consider just a constant system consisting of one finite group scheme $\mathfrak {g}$ (and the identity maps).

2.2 First-order set-up for finite group scheme actions

In this subsection, we will describe a first-order language $L_{\mathfrak {g}}$ and an $L_{\mathfrak {g}}$ -theory $\mathfrak {g}$ -DF such that models of $\mathfrak {g}$ -DF are exactly $\mathfrak {g}$ -fields. If we skip the “iterativity condition” (see Remark 2.2(2)), then we are exactly in the set-up from [Reference Beyarslan, Hoffmann, Kamensky and Kowalski1]. Let us recall this set-up briefly.

We fix $\{b_{0},\ldots ,b_{e-1}\}$ , which is a $\textbf {k}$ -basis of H such that $\pi (b_{0})=1$ and $\pi (b_{i})=0$ for $i>0$ . Then, for a $\textbf {k}$ -algebra R, any map $\partial :R\to R\otimes _{k}H$ can be identified with a sequence

$$ \begin{align*}\partial_{0},\partial_{1},\ldots,\partial_{e-1}:R\to R.\end{align*} $$

The map $\partial $ satisfies the counit condition (see Remark 2.2(1)) if and only if $\partial _{0}={\mathrm{id}}_{R}$ . To express the coassociativity condition, we need to use the structure constants for the comultiplication on H, which for $i,j,l<e$ are the elements $c^{i,j}_{l}\in \textbf {k}$ such that the following equality holds:

$$ \begin{align*}\mu(b_{l})=\sum\limits_{i,j<e}c^{i,j}_{l} b_{i}\otimes b_{j}\!.\end{align*} $$

Then, $(R,\partial )$ satisfies the coassociativity condition if and only if for any $r\in R$ , we have:

$$ \begin{align*}\partial_{i}\partial_{j}(r)=\sum_{l=0}^{e-1}c^{i,j}_{l}\partial_{l}(r).\end{align*} $$

Let $L_{\mathfrak {g}}$ be the language of rings expanded by $e-1$ unary function symbols and by extra constant symbols for the elements of $\textbf {k}$ . It is clear by what is written above, that there is an $L_{\mathfrak {g}}$ -theory, which we denote by $\mathfrak {g}$ -DF, whose models are exactly $\mathfrak {g}$ -fields. We are aiming towards showing that this theory has a model companion (Theorem 3.6) and that this model companion is simple (Corollary 4.12).

Example 2.4. We discuss here model-theoretic properties of $\mathfrak {g}$ -fields from Example 2.3.

  1. (1) If $\mathfrak {g}=G_{\textbf {k}}$ for a finite group G, then the theory $\mathfrak {g}$ -DF coincides with the theory of G-transformal fields from [Reference Hoffmann and Kowalski14]. It is proved in [Reference Hoffmann and Kowalski14] that the theory of G-transformal fields has a model companion (denoted G-TCF), which is supersimple of finite rank coinciding with the order of G.

  2. (2) If $\mathrm{char}(\textbf {k})=p>0$ and $\mathfrak {g}$ is a truncated group scheme, then the theory $\mathfrak {g}$ -DF was already introduced (with the same name in this truncated context) in [Reference Hoffmann and Kowalski13]. It is shown in [Reference Hoffmann and Kowalski13] that the theory $\mathfrak {g}$ -DF has a model companion (denoted $\mathfrak {g}$ -DCF), which is strictly stable.

  3. (3) If $\mathfrak {g}=\mathfrak {g}_{1}\times \mathfrak {g}_{2}$ , where $\mathfrak {g}_{1}$ is non-trivial truncated and $\mathfrak {g}_{2}$ is non-trivial, then, as for as we know, the model theory of $\mathfrak {g}$ -fields has not been considered before. If the finite group scheme $\mathfrak {g}_{2}$ is constant, then this theory fits to the set-up considered by the first author in [Reference Hoffmann11], which will be explained in Section 5.

  4. (4) If $\mathfrak {g}$ is a finite étale group scheme which is not constant, then, as far as we know, the iterativity rules (and the “Leibniz rules”) coming from such actions have not been studied yet. We consider the action from Example 2.3(4) and we use the notation from there. We have to fix a “good basis” $b_{0},b_{1},b_{2}$ first such that $\pi (b_{0})=1$ and $\pi (b_{1})=\pi (b_{2})=0$ . This choice is quite arbitrary, we have chosen the following:

    $$ \begin{align*}b_{0}:=\frac{1+\varepsilon+\varepsilon^{2}}{3},\ \ \ \ b_{1}:=\frac{\varepsilon-1}{3},\ \ \ \ b_{2}:=\frac{\varepsilon^{2}-1}{3}\!.\end{align*} $$
    1. (a) We have the following multiplication table:

      $$ \begin{align*} \begin{array}{r@{\,}c@{\,}lcr@{\,}c@{\,}l} b_0^2 &=& b_0, &\qquad& b_1^2 &=& \dfrac{-2b_1+b_2}{3},\\[8pt] b_0b_1 &=& 0, &\qquad& b_2^2 &=& \dfrac{b_1-2b_2}{3},\\[8pt] b_0b_2 &=& 0, &\qquad& b_1b_2 &=& \dfrac{-b_1-b_2}{3}. \end{array} \end{align*} $$
      Then, the multiplicative rule for $\mathfrak {g}$ -operators (with respect to this basis) is the following one:
      $$ \begin{align*}\partial_{1}(xy)=\frac{-2\partial_{1}(x)\partial_{1}(y)-\partial_{1}(x)\partial_{2}(y)-\partial_{2}(x)\partial_{1}(y)+\partial_{2}(x)\partial_{2}(y)}{3}\!,\end{align*} $$
      $$ \begin{align*}\partial_{2}(xy)=\frac{\partial_{1}(x)\partial_{1}(y)-\partial_{1}(x)\partial_{2}(y)-\partial_{2}(x)\partial_{1}(y)-2\partial_{2}(x)\partial_{2}(y)}{3}\!.\end{align*} $$
    2. (b) We have the following comultiplication table:

      $$ \begin{align*}\mu(b_{0})=b_{0}\otimes b_{0} + 2b_{1}\otimes b_{1} - b_{1}\otimes b_{2} - b_{2}\otimes b_{1} + 2b_{2}\otimes b_{2}\!,\end{align*} $$
      $$ \begin{align*}\mu(b_{1})=b_{0}\otimes b_{1} + b_{1}\otimes b_{0} + b_{1}\otimes b_{1} - b_{1}\otimes b_{2} - b_{2}\otimes b_{1}\!,\end{align*} $$
      $$ \begin{align*}\mu(b_{2})=b_{0}\otimes b_{2} + b_{2}\otimes b_{0} + b_{2}\otimes b_{2} - b_{1}\otimes b_{2} - b_{2}\otimes b_{1}\!,\end{align*} $$
      which gives the following $\mathfrak {g}$ -iterativity rules ( $\partial _{0}={\mathrm{id}}$ ):
      $$ \begin{align*} \begin{array}{r@{\,}c@{\,}l} \partial_1\circ \partial_1 &=& 2\partial_0+\partial_1,\\[3pt] \partial_2\circ \partial_2 &=& 2\partial_0+\partial_2,\\[3pt] \partial_1\circ \partial_2 &=& -\partial_0-\partial_1-\partial_2=\partial_2\circ \partial_1. \end{array} \end{align*} $$
    3. (c) It is interesting to see how the rules from Item (b) above transform into the rules for the usual action of ${\mathbb {Z}}/3{\mathbb {Z}}$ in the case when our $\mathfrak {g}$ -field contains the primitive third root of unity $\zeta $ in the constants of the action. In such a case, we set the following new basis:

      $$ \begin{align*}b_{0}^{\prime}:=b_{0}=\frac{1+\varepsilon+\varepsilon^{2}}{3},\ \ \ \ b_{1}^{\prime}=\frac{1+\zeta^{2}\varepsilon+\zeta\varepsilon^{2}}{3},\ \ \ \ b_{2}^{\prime}=\frac{1+\zeta\varepsilon+\zeta^{2}\varepsilon^{2}}{3}\!.\end{align*} $$
      It is easy to see that it is an “orthogonal basis,” that is $b_{i}^{\prime }b_{j}^{\prime }=\delta ^{i}_{j}$ (the Kronecker delta) and that the comultiplication on $b_{0}^{\prime },b_{1}^{\prime },b_{2}^{\prime }$ gives the constant group scheme coming from the group ${\mathbb {Z}}/3{\mathbb {Z}}$ . Then, we have the following transformation rules explaining how a $\mathfrak {g}$ -action given by $\partial _{1},\partial _{2}$ becomes an action of ${\mathbb {Z}}/3{\mathbb {Z}}$ given by $\partial _{1}^{\prime },\partial _{2}^{\prime }$ :
      $$ \begin{align*}\partial_{1}^{\prime}=\frac{\zeta^{2}\partial_{1}-\zeta\partial_{2}}{\zeta-\zeta^{2}},\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \partial_{2}^{\prime}=\frac{-\zeta\partial_{1}+\zeta^{2}\partial_{2}}{\zeta-\zeta^{2}}\!.\end{align*} $$

2.3 Prolongations with respect to finite group scheme actions

We fix in this subsection a $\mathfrak {g}$ -field $(K,\partial )$ . We will recall the notion of a prolongation from [Reference Moosa and Scanlon23], which is closely related to the Weil restriction of scalars. We need the following definition first.

Definition 2.5. For a K-algebra R, we consider a “ $\partial $ -twisted” K-algebra structure on $R\otimes _{\textbf {k}} H$ , which is the K-algebra structure given by the following composition:

We denote the ring $ R\otimes _{\textbf {k}} H$ with the above $\partial $ -twisted K-algebra structure by $R\otimes _{\textbf {k}}^{\partial } H$ .

Remark 2.6. The functor $R\mapsto R\otimes _{\textbf {k}}^{\partial } H$ controls the $\mathfrak {g}$ -ring extensions of K. More precisely, a map

$$ \begin{align*}\partial^{\prime}:R\longrightarrow R\otimes_{\textbf{k}}^{\partial} H\end{align*} $$

is a K-algebra homomorphism if and only if $(R,\partial ^{\prime })$ is a $\mathfrak {g}$ -ring extension of $(K,\partial )$ .

By a K-variety, we always mean a reduced K-irreducible algebraic subvariety of $\mathbb {A}^{n}_{K}$ for some $n>0$ .

Definition 2.7. Let V be a K-variety.

  1. (1) A K-variety $\nabla (V)$ is called a $\partial $ -prolongation of V, if for each K-algebra R, there is a functorial bijection:

    $$ \begin{align*}\nabla(V)(R) \longleftrightarrow V\big(R\otimes_{\textbf{k}}^{\partial} H\big).\end{align*} $$
  2. (2) For any K-algebra R, the counit map $\mu :H\to \textbf {k}$ induces a natural K-algebra map $R\otimes _{\textbf {k}}^{\partial } H\to R$ , which yields the following functorial morphism:

    $$ \begin{align*}\pi_{V}:\nabla(V)\longrightarrow V.\end{align*} $$

From now on, we will regard the natural bijection from Definition 2.7(1) as the identity map.

Remark 2.8. We collect here several observations regarding the notion of a $\partial $ -prolongation.

  1. (1) As explained in [Reference Moosa and Scanlon23], $\partial $ -prolongations exist and they coincide with the Weil restriction to K of the base extension from K to $K{\kern-1pt}\otimes _{\textbf {k}}^{\partial } H$ .

  2. (2) On the level of rings, the $\partial $ -prolongation functor is a left-adjoint functor to the following functor:

    $$ \begin{align*}\mathrm{Alg}_{K}\ni R\mapsto R\otimes_{\textbf{k}}^{\partial} H\in \mathrm{Alg}_{K}\!.\end{align*} $$
  3. (3) It is good to point out that the notion of a $\partial $ -prolongation does not depend on the group scheme structure on $\mathfrak {g}$ . In particular, $\partial $ -prolongations also exist if $\partial $ is a “non-iterative” H-operator on K in the sense of Remark 2.2(2). However, we notice below that if $(K,\partial )$ is a $\mathfrak {g}$ -field (which is our assumption here), then the $\partial $ -prolongation functor still has some in-built iterativity properties (see Definition 2.13 and Remark 2.18).

Example 2.9. For finite group schemes considered in Example 2.3(1) and (2), the $\partial $ -prolongation functor has a natural description. Let V be a K-variety.

  1. (1) If $\mathfrak {g}=G_{\textbf {k}}$ for a finite group G, then G acts on K by field automorphisms. Let us recall that for any $\sigma \in \mathrm{Aut}(K)$ , we have the “ $\sigma $ -twisted” variety $V^{\sigma }$ defined as:

    $$ \begin{align*}V^{\sigma}:=V\times_{\operatorname{\mathrm{Spec}}(K)}(\operatorname{\mathrm{Spec}}(K),\operatorname{\mathrm{Spec}}(\sigma)).\end{align*} $$
    If $G=\{g_{1},\ldots ,g_{e}\}$ , then we have:
    $$ \begin{align*}\nabla(V)=V^{g_{1}}\times \cdots \times V^{g_{e}}\end{align*} $$
    (see [Reference Hoffmann and Kowalski14, Remark 2.7(4)]).
  2. (2) If $\mathrm{char}(\textbf {k})=p>0$ and $\mathfrak {g}$ is a finite truncated group scheme, then $\nabla (V)$ is a torsor of a higher tangent bundle of V. For a more explicit description, let us consider the simplest case when $\mathfrak {g}=\mathbb {G}_{\text {a}}[1]$ and $p=2$ . Then, we know that $\partial $ corresponds to a derivation d on K such that $d\circ d=0$ . If V is defined over the kernel of d, then $\nabla (V)$ coincides with the tangent bundle of V.

Definition 2.10. Let V be a K-variety and $(R,\partial ^{\prime })$ be a $\mathfrak {g}$ -ring extension of $(K,\partial )$ . By Remark 2.6, the map

$$ \begin{align*}\partial^{\prime}:R\longrightarrow R\otimes_{\textbf{k}}^{\partial} H\end{align*} $$

is a K-algebra homomorphism, hence it induces the following map, which is natural in V (but it is not a morphism!):

$$ \begin{align*}\partial^{\prime}_{V}:=V(\partial^{\prime}):V(R)\longrightarrow V\big(R\otimes_{\textbf{k}}^{\partial} H\big)=\nabla(V)(R).\end{align*} $$

It is easy to observe the following.

Remark 2.11. Let us assume that we are in the situation from Definition 2.10.

  1. (1) The following diagram is commutative:

  2. (2) Let as assume that $V\subseteq \mathbb {A}^{n}$ and let $\partial _{1},\ldots ,\partial _{e-1}$ (see Section 2.2) act coordinate-wise on $\mathbb {A}^{n}(R)=R^{n}$ . Then, the map $\partial _{V}^{\prime }:V(R)\to \nabla (V)(R)$ is given by:

    $$ \begin{align*}\partial_{V}^{\prime}(r)=\left(r,\partial_{1}^{\prime}(r),\ldots,\partial_{e-1}^{\prime}(r)\right)\!,\end{align*} $$
    and the map $\pi _{V}$ corresponds to the projection on the first (n-tuple) coordinate.

We will describe now a morphism $\nabla (V)\longrightarrow \nabla \left (\nabla (V)\right )$ , which reflects the “iterativity” of $\partial $ on the level of the $\partial $ -prolongation (it was mentioned in Remark 2.8(3)). We need a lemma first.

Lemma 2.12. The map

$$ \begin{align*}{\mathrm{id}}\otimes\mu: R\otimes_{\textbf{k}}^{\partial} H\longrightarrow \big(R\otimes_{\textbf{k}}^{\partial} H\big)\otimes_{\textbf{k}}^{\partial} H\end{align*} $$

is a morphism of K-algebras.

Proof Let $\iota :K\to R$ be the K-algebra structure map. By Remark 2.2(1), the following diagram commutes:

Since the ring homomorphism $(\iota \otimes {\mathrm{id}})\circ \partial $ gives the K-algebra structure of $R\otimes _{\textbf {k}}^{\partial }H$ and the ring homomorphism $(\iota \otimes {\mathrm{id}}\otimes {\mathrm{id}})\circ (\partial \otimes {\mathrm{id}})\circ \partial $ gives the K-algebra structure on $(R\otimes _{\textbf {k}}^{\partial }H)\otimes _{\textbf {k}}^{\partial } H$ , the result follows.

Definition 2.13. Let V be an affine K-scheme. We define the following scheme morphism (natural in V)

$$ \begin{align*}c_{V}:\nabla(V)\longrightarrow \nabla(\nabla(V))\end{align*} $$

using for any K-algebra R the following map (well-defined by Lemma 2.12):

$$ \begin{align*}c_{V}:=V\left({\mathrm{id}}\otimes\mu\right):V\big(R\otimes_{\textbf{k}}^{\partial} H\big)\longrightarrow V\big(\big(R\otimes_{\textbf{k}}^{\partial} H\big)\otimes_{\textbf{k}}^{\partial} H\big).\end{align*} $$

Remark 2.14.

  1. (1) In the set-up of Remark 2.11(2), the morphism $c_{V}$ above is given on rational points by the following formula:

    $$ \begin{align*}c_{V}(x_{0},\ldots,x_{e-1})=\left(\sum_{l=0}^{e-1}c^{i,j}_{l} x_{l}\right)_{i,j<e}\!.\end{align*} $$
  2. (2) In terms of the “constant” generalized Hasse–Schmidt system $\underline {\mathcal {D}}$ from [Reference Moosa and Scanlon22] (see the last paragraph of Section 2.1), the morphism $c_{V}$ above coincides with the morphism $\hat {\Delta }$ from [Reference Moosa and Scanlon23, Remark 2.18].

Lemma 2.15. We have the following:

$$ \begin{align*}\partial_{\nabla(V)}\circ \partial_{V} = c_{V} \circ \partial_{V}\!.\end{align*} $$

Proof By Definitions 2.10 and 2.13, we have:

$$ \begin{align*}\partial_{V}=V(\partial),\ \ \ \ \ c_{V}:=V\left({\mathrm{id}}\otimes\mu\right)\!.\end{align*} $$

Therefore, the statement we are showing follows from applying V (regarded as the functor of rational points) to the commutative diagram from Remark 2.2(1).

By the definition of $\nabla (V)$ , the morphisms $V\to \nabla (V)$ correspond to the K-algebra maps $K[V]\to K[V]\otimes _{\textbf {k}}^{\partial } H$ . The following result explains when such morphisms correspond to $\mathfrak {g}$ -ring structures on $K[V]$ extending $\partial $ on K (equivalently: $\mathfrak {g}$ -actions on V).

Lemma 2.16. Let us fix a morphism $\varphi :V\to \nabla (V)$ . Then, the following are equivalent.

  1. (1) The corresponding map $K[V]\to K[V]\otimes _{\textbf {k}}^{\partial } H$ makes $K[V]$ a $\mathfrak {g}$ -ring extension of K.

  2. (2) We have $\pi _{V}\circ \varphi ={\mathrm{id}}_{V}$ and the following diagram is commutative:

Proof It follows directly from the adjointness property defining the functor $\nabla $ and from Remark 2.2(1).

Example 2.17. By Lemma 2.16, we obtain that the morphism

$$ \begin{align*}c_{V}:\nabla(V)\longrightarrow \nabla(\nabla(V))\end{align*} $$

gives the ring $K[\nabla (V)]$ a canonical $\mathfrak {g}$ -ring structure $\widetilde {\partial }=(\widetilde {\partial }_{0},\ldots ,\widetilde {\partial }_{e-1})$ . This canonical structure is dual (or rather “adjoint”) to the one considered in [Reference Hoffmann and Kowalski12, Proposition 3.4].

Let us give an explicit description of this structure for $V=\mathbb {A}^{1}$ , so

$$ \begin{align*}K[\nabla(V)]=K[X_{0},\ldots,X_{e-1}]=:K[X_{<e}].\end{align*} $$

For any K-algebra R, we have (see Lemma 2.12):

$$ \begin{align*}\nabla(\mathbb{A}^{1})(R)=R\otimes^{\partial}_{\textbf{k}}H,\ \ \ \ \ \nabla(\nabla(\mathbb{A}^{1}))(R)=\big(R\otimes^{\partial}_{\textbf{k}}H\big)\otimes^{\partial}_{\textbf{k}}H,\end{align*} $$
$$ \begin{align*}c_{\mathbb{A}^{1}}={\mathrm{id}}\otimes \mu:R\otimes^{\partial}_{\textbf{k}}H\longrightarrow \big(R\otimes^{\partial}_{\textbf{k}}H\big)\otimes^{\partial}_{\textbf{k}}H.\end{align*} $$

Since for any $n>0$ , we have that $\nabla (\mathbb {A}^{n})=\mathbb {A}^{ne}$ , by Remark 2.14 we get the following interpretation (using the fixed basis $b_{0},\ldots ,b_{e-1}$ of H over $\textbf {k}$ ):

$$ \begin{align*} & c_{\mathbb{A}^{1}}:\nabla(\mathbb{A}^{1})(R)=R^{e}\longrightarrow \nabla(\nabla(\mathbb{A}^{1}))(R)=R^{e^{2}},\\ & c_{\mathbb{A}^{1}}(r_{0},\ldots,r_{e-1})=\left(\sum_{l=0}^{e-1}c^{i,j}_{l}r_{l}\right)_{i,j<e}\!.\end{align*} $$

We get the corresponding map on the coordinate rings:

$$ \begin{align*}c_{\mathbb{A}^{1}}^{*}:K\left[X_{i}^{(j)}\ |\ i,j<e\right]\longrightarrow K[X_{<e}],\ \ \ \ c_{\mathbb{A}^{1}}^{*}\left(X_{i}^{(j)}\right)=\sum_{l=0}^{e-1}c^{i,j}_{l}X_{l}\!.\end{align*} $$

The adjoint map to this last map above gives the canonical $\mathfrak {g}$ -ring structure on $K[\nabla (\mathbb {A}^{1})]$ :

$$ \begin{align*}\widetilde{\partial}=\left(c_{\mathbb{A}^{1}}^{*}\right)^{\dagger}:K[X_{<e}]\longrightarrow K[X_{<e}]\otimes^{\partial}_{\textbf{k}}H,\ \ \ \ \widetilde{\partial}(X_{j})=\sum_{j=0}^{e-1}\left(\sum_{l=0}^{e-1}c^{i,j}_{l}X_{l}\right)\otimes b_{j}\!.\end{align*} $$

In terms of the operators $\widetilde {\partial }_{0},\ldots ,\widetilde {\partial }_{e-1}$ , we get:

$$ \begin{align*}\widetilde{\partial}_{i}(X_{j})=\sum_{l=0}^{e-1}c^{i,j}_{l}X_{l}\!.\end{align*} $$

We consider below several explicit examples.

  1. (1) Let us assume that $\mathrm{char}(\textbf {k})=2$ and

    $$ \begin{align*}\mathfrak{g}=\mathbb{G}_{\mathrm{a}}[1]=\operatorname{\mathrm{Spec}}(\textbf{k}[v]),\ \ \ \ \mu(v)=v\otimes 1+ 1\otimes v,\ \ \ \ \ b_{0}=1,b_{1}=v;\end{align*} $$
    where $\textbf {k}[v]:=\textbf {k}[X]/(X^{2})$ . In this case, we have:
    $$ \begin{align*} \begin{array}{rcl} \widetilde{\partial}(X_0) &=& X_0\otimes b_0 + X_1\otimes b_1,\\[3pt] \widetilde{\partial}(X_1) &=& X_1\otimes b_0, \end{array} \end{align*} $$
    and we see that:
    $$ \begin{align*}\widetilde{\partial}_{1}(X_{0})=X_{1},\ \ \ \ \widetilde{\partial}_{1}(X_{1})=0.\end{align*} $$
  2. (2) We still assume that $\operatorname {\mathrm{char}}(\textbf {k})=2$ , the ring $\textbf {k}[v]$ is as above, and we take:

    $$ \begin{align*}\mathfrak{g}=\mathbb{G}_{\mathrm{{m}}}[1]=\operatorname{\mathrm{Spec}}(\textbf{k}[v]),\ \ \ \ \mu(v)=v\otimes 1+ 1\otimes v+v\otimes v,\ \ \ \ \ b_{0}=1,b_{1}=v.\end{align*} $$
    We obtain the following:
    $$ \begin{align*}\widetilde{\partial}_{1}(X_{0})=X_{1},\ \ \ \ \widetilde{\partial}_{1}(X_{1})=X_{1}\!.\end{align*} $$
  3. (3) If $G=\{g_{0},\ldots ,g_{e-1}\}$ is a finite group and $\mathfrak {g}=G_{\textbf {k}}$ , then we obtain a canonical G-action on $K[X_{<e}]$ such that for all $i,j,k<e$ , we have:

    $$ \begin{align*}g_{i}\cdot X_{j}=X_{k}\!,\end{align*} $$
    if and only if $g_{i}g_{j}=g_{k}$ .

Remark 2.18. We would like to say few words about an explicit construction of the $\partial $ -prolongation functor understood as the left-adjoint functor from Remark 2.8(2). If $R=K[\overline {X}]/I$ is an arbitrary K-algebra, then there is a “non-iterative H-operator $\overline {\partial }$ from $K[\overline {X}]$ to $K\{\overline {X}\}:=K[\overline {X},\overline {X}_{1},\ldots ,\overline {X}_{e-1}]$ ” defined by $\overline {\partial }_{i}(\overline {X}):=\overline {X}_{i}$ , and the $\partial $ -prolongation of R coincides with $K\{\overline {X}\}/(\overline {\partial }(I))$ .

In our “iterative” situation, the operator $\overline {\partial }$ extends to the $\mathfrak {g}$ -ring structure $\widetilde {\partial }$ as explained in Example 2.17. Then, we have that $\overline {\partial }(I)=\widetilde {\partial }(I)$ is an “ $\mathfrak {g}$ -ideal,” hence the quotient $K\{\overline {X}\}/(\overline {\partial }(I))$ gets a natural $\mathfrak {g}$ -ring structure, which coincides with the one described in Example 2.17.

3 Model companion

In this section, we prove the existence of a model companion of the theory of $\mathfrak {g}$ -fields for an arbitrary finite group scheme $\mathfrak {g}$ over the field $\textbf {k}$ . The proofs in this section follow the lines of the proofs from [Reference Hoffmann and Kowalski13, Reference Kowalski19], however, we made some improvements here in order to make these proofs simpler and “coordinate-free.”

For the next result, we need to introduce the notion of constants of a $\mathfrak {g}$ -ring (these are the same constants as in [Reference Beyarslan, Hoffmann, Kamensky and Kowalski1, Definition 2.2(3)]).

Definition 3.1. Let $(R,\partial )$ be a $\mathfrak {g}$ -ring. We denote by $R^{\mathfrak {g}}$ the ring of constants of $(R,\partial )$ , that is,

$$ \begin{align*}R^{\mathfrak{g}}:=\{x\in R\ |\ \partial(x)=x\}\!,\end{align*} $$

where $\partial $ is understood as a map $R\to R\otimes _{\textbf {k}}H$ and R is considered as a subring of $R\otimes _{\textbf {k}}H$ .

Remark 3.2. We note here several properties of the ring extension $R^{\mathfrak {g}}\subseteq R$ .

  1. (1) By [Reference Montgomery21, Theorem 4.2.1], the ring extension $R^{\mathfrak {g}}\subseteq R$ is integral (see also the proof of [Reference Mumford25, Section 12, Theorem 1]).

  2. (2) The extension $R^{\mathfrak {g}}\subseteq R$ need not be finite, that is R is not necessarily a finitely generated $R^{\mathfrak {g}}$ -module (by Item $(1)$ above, it is equivalent to saying that R is not necessarily a finitely generated $R^{\mathfrak {g}}$ -algebra). Finite generation fails in the simplest non-trivial case, that is for the constant group $\mathfrak {g}=({\mathbb {Z}}/2{\mathbb {Z}})_{\textbf {k}}$ as demonstrated in [Reference Montgomery20, Example 5.5] (a Noetherian domain R with an action of $G={\mathbb {Z}}/2{\mathbb {Z}}$ such that $R^{G}$ is not Noetherian and R is not a finite $R^{G}$ -module).

    Finite generation holds in the case when R is a finitely generated $\textbf {k}$ -algebra (it is quite easy to show knowing that the ring extension $R^{\mathfrak {g}}\subseteq R$ is integral, see e.g., [Reference Serre27, Lemma 10, p. 49]), but this is not a good assumption for us.

  3. (3) We will show in Section 4 (Theorem 4.4) that if K is a field, then the field extension $K^{\mathfrak {g}}\subseteq K$ is finite and of degree bounded by e, as in the case of group actions. It is hard to believe that this result is new, but we were unable to find it in the literature. The closest result we could find is [Reference Montgomery21, Theorem 8.3.7], but there is an extra assumption there saying that the extension $K^{\mathfrak {g}}\subseteq K$ should be Hopf Galois (see [Reference Montgomery21, Definition 8.1.1]) and, as [Reference Montgomery21, Example 8.1.3] shows, the field extension $K^{\mathfrak {g}}\subseteq K$ need not be Hopf Galois in general.

Lemma 3.3. Suppose that R is a $\mathfrak {g}$ -ring and $R\to S,R\to T$ are homomorphisms of $\mathfrak {g}$ -rings. Then, we have the following.

  1. (1) There is a unique $\mathfrak {g}$ -ring structure on $S\otimes _{R}T$ such that the natural maps $S\to S\otimes _{R}T,T\to S\otimes _{R}T$ are homomorphisms of $\mathfrak {g}$ -rings.

  2. (2) If R is a domain, then the $\mathfrak {g}$ -ring structure on R extends uniquely to its field of fractions, which we denote by $\mathrm{Frac}(R)$ .

Proof Item $(1)$ is an instance of the following very general fact: if a group G in a category acts on the objects X and Y, then there is a unique G-action on $X\times Y$ such that the projection maps $X\times Y\to X,X\times Y\to Y$ commute with the action of G.

For Item $(2)$ , we notice first that by Remark 3.2(1) the extension of domains $R^{\mathfrak {g}}\subseteq R$ is integral, which implies that:

$$ \begin{align*}\mathrm{Frac}\left(R^{\mathfrak{g}}\right)[R]=\mathrm{Frac}(R).\end{align*} $$

Since tensor products commute with localizations, we get that:

$$ \begin{align*}\mathrm{Frac}\left(R^{\mathfrak{g}}\right)\otimes_{R^{\mathfrak{g}}}R\cong_{R}\mathrm{Frac}(R).\end{align*} $$

Therefore, using Item $(1)$ , we obtain that there is an $\mathfrak {g}$ -action on $\mathrm{Frac}(R)$ extending uniquely the trivial action on $\mathrm{Frac}\left (R^{\mathfrak {g}}\right )$ and the given action on R.

Remark 3.4. It is rather clear that Lemma 3.3(1) holds for actions of arbitrary (that is, not necessarily finite) group schemes. As the referee pointed out to us, Lemma 3.3(2) fails for example when we consider the action of the additive group scheme on itself by translations.

For the rest of this section we fix a $\mathfrak {g}$ -field K and a K-variety V. The following lemma is an extended version of [Reference Kowalski19, Lemma 1.1(ii)].

Proposition 3.5. Assume that W is a K-variety such that $W\subseteq \nabla (V)$ and $c_{V}(W)\subseteq \nabla (W)$ . Then, we have the following.

  1. (1) There is a $\mathfrak {g}$ -field structure $\partial ^{\prime }$ on $K(W)$ such that $K\subseteq K(W)$ is a $\mathfrak {g}$ -field extension.

  2. (2) Let $b:W\to V$ denote the composition of the inclusion $W\subseteq \nabla (V)$ and the projection morphism $\pi _{V}:\nabla (V)\to V$ . We regard b as an element of $V(K(W))$ . Then, we have:

    $$ \begin{align*}\partial^{\prime}_{V}(b)\in W(K(W)),\end{align*} $$
    where $\partial ^{\prime }$ comes from Item $(1)$ above.

Proof For the proof of Item $(1)$ , we consider the morphism:

$$ \begin{align*}\varphi:=c_{V}|_{W}:W\longrightarrow \nabla(W).\end{align*} $$

By Example 2.17, the morphism $\varphi $ satisfies the second condition from Lemma 2.16, hence $K\subseteq K[W]$ has a natural structure of a $\mathfrak {g}$ -ring extension. By Lemma 3.3, the $\mathfrak {g}$ -ring structure on $K[W]$ extends to a $\mathfrak {g}$ -field structure, which we denote by $\partial ^{\prime }$ , on $K(W)$ .

For Item $(2)$ , we notice first that the rational point $\partial ^{\prime }_{V}(b)\in \nabla (V)(K(W))$ corresponds to the following morphism:

$$ \begin{align*}\nabla(b)\circ \varphi:W\longrightarrow \nabla(V).\end{align*} $$

It is enough to show that this morphism coincides with the inclusion $W\subseteq \nabla (V)$ , which follows from the commutativity of the following diagram:

and the facts that $\nabla (\pi _{V})=\pi _{\nabla (V)}$ and $\pi _{\nabla (V)}\circ c_{V}={\mathrm{id}}_{\nabla (V)}$ (since $c_{V}$ satisfies the counit condition from Remark 2.2(1)).

We can formulate now:

Geometric axioms for $\mathfrak {g}$ -DCF

For each positive integer n, suppose that $V \subseteq \mathbb {A}^{n}$ and $W \subseteq \nabla (V)$ are K-varieties. If $c_{V}(W)\subseteq \nabla (W)$ , then there is $a\in V(K)$ such that $\partial _{V}(a)\in W(K)$ .

It is standard to see that these axioms are first-order, see e.g., the discussion in [Reference Hoffmann and Kowalski14, Remark 2.7].

Theorem 3.6. The $\mathfrak {g}$ -field $(K,\partial )$ is existentially closed if and only if $(K,\partial )$ satisfies the geometric axioms above.

Proof For the left-to-right implication, let us assume that the $\mathfrak {g}$ -field K is existentially closed and take $V,W$ as in the assumptions of the geometric axioms for $\mathfrak {g}$ -DCF. As in the statement of Proposition 3.5, we regard the projection morphism $W\to V$ as a rational point $b\in V(K(W))$ . By Proposition 3.5, $(K,\partial )\subseteq (K(W),\partial ^{\prime })$ is a $\mathfrak {g}$ -field extension and $\partial ^{\prime }_{V}(b)\in W(K(W))$ . By Lemma 2.11 and our assumption saying that the $\mathfrak {g}$ -field $(K,\partial )$ is existentially closed, we obtain that there is $a\in V(K)$ such that $\partial _{V}(a)\in W(K)$ .

For the right-to-left implication, let us assume that $(K,\partial )$ satisfies the geometric axioms for $\mathfrak {g}$ -DCF. We take a $\mathfrak {g}$ -field extension $(K,\partial )\subseteq (L,\partial ^{\prime })$ and a quantifier-free $L_{\mathfrak {g}}$ -formula $\phi (x)$ over K having a realisation v in $(L,\partial ^{\prime })$ . By the usual trick of introducing extra variables (to get rid of any negations of equalities), we can assume that for

$$ \begin{align*}V:=\mathrm{locus}_{K}(v),\ \ \ \ \ \ W:=\mathrm{locus}_{K}(\partial_{V}^{\prime}(v)),\end{align*} $$

the formula $\phi (x)$ is implied by the formula saying that “ $x\in V$ and $\partial _{V}(x)\in W$ ” (the latter is clearly a first-order formula by Remark 2.11(2)). By Lemma 2.15, we get that $c_{V}(W)\subseteq \nabla (W)$ , thus by the geometric axioms for $\mathfrak {g}$ -DCF, the formula $\phi (x)$ has a realisation in $(K,\partial )$ .

Example 3.7. The geometric axioms for $\mathfrak {g}$ -DCF generalize both the axiomatizations given in [Reference Hoffmann and Kowalski13, Reference Hoffmann and Kowalski14]. We explain below how the axioms for $\mathfrak {g}$ -DCF specialize to these two cases.

  1. (1) In [Reference Hoffmann and Kowalski13], the case of a truncated (see Example 2.3(2)) finite group scheme $\mathfrak {g}$ is considered. The axioms for the theory of existentially closed $\mathfrak {g}$ -fields from [Reference Hoffmann and Kowalski13, Section 5.2] have basically the same form as the axioms above. However, the idea that similar axioms as in [Reference Hoffmann and Kowalski13, Section 5.2] may work for an arbitrary finite group scheme $\mathfrak {g}$ only came to us at the final moments of writing the article [Reference Hoffmann and Kowalski14] (see [Reference Hoffmann and Kowalski14, Remark 5.1]).

  2. (2) In [Reference Hoffmann and Kowalski14], we studied model theory of actions of finite groups on fields, which correspond to actions of finite constant group schemes (see Example 2.4(1)). The geometric version of the corresponding axioms is given in [Reference Hoffmann and Kowalski14, Remark 2.7(2)(b)] and the comparison to axioms from Item $(1)$ above (so, also to the axioms from Theorem 3.6) is discussed in [Reference Hoffmann and Kowalski14, Remark 2.7(4)].

4 Fields of constants and simplicity

The main result of this section is Theorem 4.12, which says that the theory $\mathfrak {g}$ -DCF (see Theorem 3.6) is simple. This result follows from a Galois-theoretic analysis of the field of constants of an existentially closed $\mathfrak {g}$ -field: we show that this field is pseudo-algebraically closed and bounded. We also show that any $\mathfrak {g}$ -field is a finite extension of its field of constants (as a pure field).

Our first aim is to show the finite generation result mentioned above. The next lemma holds in any category in which quotients of group actions exist (as in the case of standard group actions). We recall that quotients exist in the category of finite group schemes (see e.g., [Reference Waterhouse29, Section 16.3]).

Lemma 4.1. Assume that K is a $\mathfrak {g}$ -field and $\mathfrak {n}$ is a normal subgroup scheme of $\mathfrak {g}$ . Then, we have the following.

  1. (1) K is an $\mathfrak {n}$ -field and $K^{\mathfrak {n}}$ is a $\mathfrak {g}/\mathfrak {n}$ -field.

  2. (2) The following two subfields of invariants coincide:

    $$ \begin{align*}\left(K^{\mathfrak{n}}\right)^{\mathfrak{g}/\mathfrak{n}}=K^{\mathfrak{g}}\!.\end{align*} $$

Thanks to Lemma 4.1, we can reduce the proof of our first aim to the case of a reasonably simple finite group scheme $\mathfrak {g}$ . The next two results deal with some particular cases of such group schemes. We recall that e is the order of $\mathfrak {g}$ , that is $e=\dim _{\textbf {k}}(H)$ , where $\mathfrak {g}=\operatorname {\mathrm{Spec}}(H)$ .

Lemma 4.2. Assume that K is a $\mathfrak {g}$ -field, $\mathrm{char}(\textbf {k})=p>0$ and $\mathfrak {g}=\ker (\operatorname {\mathrm{Fr}}_{\mathfrak {g}})$ . Then, we have:

$$ \begin{align*}\left[K:K^{\mathfrak{g}}\right]\leqslant e.\end{align*} $$

Proof The proof of [Reference Hoffmann and Kowalski13, Corollary 3.21] works in the case considered here as well (our e here plays the role of $pe$ from [Reference Hoffmann and Kowalski13]).

Lemma 4.3. Assume that K is a $\mathfrak {g}$ -field and $\mathfrak {g}$ is étale. Then we have:

$$ \begin{align*}\left[K:K^{\mathfrak{g}}\right]\leqslant e.\end{align*} $$

Proof Let $\textbf {k}\subseteq \textbf {l}$ be a finite Galois extension such that $\mathfrak {g}_{\textbf {l}}\cong G_{\textbf {l}}$ , where G is a finite group of order e (see Example 2.3(4)). Since K is a $\mathfrak {g}$ -field, $K{\kern-1pt}\otimes _{\textbf {k}}\textbf {l}$ becomes a $\mathfrak {g}_{\textbf {l}}$ -ring, which means that the group G acts on $K{\kern-1pt}\otimes _{\textbf {k}}\textbf {l}$ by $\textbf {l}$ -algebra automorphisms. By [Reference Beyarslan, Hoffmann, Kamensky and Kowalski1, Theorem 4.4], it is enough to show that $K{\kern-1pt}\otimes _{\textbf {k}}\textbf {l}$ can be generated by e elements as a $(K{\kern-1pt}\otimes _{\textbf {k}}\textbf {l})^{G}$ -module.

Since the extension $\textbf {k}\subseteq \textbf {l}$ is finite separable, the ring $K{\kern-1pt}\otimes _{\textbf {k}}\textbf {l}$ is a reduced Artinian K-algebra, so it is semisimple. By [Reference Montgomery20, Theorem 2.19] and the comments about the finite number of generators after its proof (since a commutative semisimple ring is necessarily self-injective), our inequality follows.

We are ready now to show our main finite generation result. As already pointed out in Remark 3.2(3), we doubt whether this result is new, but we could not find any reference to it.

Theorem 4.4. Assume that K is a $\mathfrak {g}$ -field. Then we have:

$$ \begin{align*}\left[K:K^{\mathfrak{g}}\right]\leqslant e.\end{align*} $$

Proof By the short exact sequence of finite group schemes from Section 1 (see [Reference Waterhouse29, Section 6.7]) and Lemma 4.1, we can assume that $\mathfrak {g}$ is connected or $\mathfrak {g}$ is étale. The étale case holds by Lemma 4.3. For the connected case, by Lemma 4.1 again we can assume that $\ker (\operatorname {\mathrm{Fr}}_{\mathfrak {g}})=\mathfrak {g}$ (see [Reference Hoffmann and Kowalski13, Remark 2.3]), and then the proof is concluded by Lemma 4.2.

We recall (the reader may consult e.g., [Reference Fried and Jarden10, Section 11]) that a field M is pseudo-algebraically closed, abbreviated PAC, if each absolutely irreducible variety over M has an M-rational point.

Proposition 4.5. If K is an existentially closed $\mathfrak {g}$ -field, then $K^{\mathfrak {g}}$ is PAC.

Proof By [Reference Fried and Jarden10, Proposition 11.3.5], we need to show that $K^{\mathfrak {g}}$ is existentially closed in each regular field extension $K^{\mathfrak {g}}\subseteq L$ . We can assume that K and L are algebraically disjoint over $K^{\mathfrak {g}}$ . Let us define:

$$ \begin{align*}M:=K{\kern-1pt}\otimes_{K^{\mathfrak{g}}} L.\end{align*} $$

By Lemma 3.3(1), there is a $\mathfrak {g}$ -ring structure $\partial ^{\prime }$ on M such that $L\subseteq R^{\partial ^{\prime }}$ . Since the field extension $K^{\mathfrak {g}}\subseteq L$ is regular and the field extension $K^{\mathfrak {g}}\subseteq K$ is finite algebraic (by Theorem 4.4), the ring M is a field. Then we have the following:

  • $(K,\partial )\subseteq (M,\partial ^{\prime })$ is a $\mathfrak {g}$ -field extension;

  • the $\mathfrak {g}$ -field $(K,\partial )$ is existentially closed;

  • $L\subseteq M^{\partial ^{\prime }}$ .

The conditions above imply that for any quantifier-free formula $\varphi (x)$ over $K^{\mathfrak {g}}$ in the language of fields, $\varphi (K^{\mathfrak {g}})\neq \emptyset $ if and only if $\varphi (L)\neq \emptyset $ . Therefore, $K^{\mathfrak {g}}$ is existentially closed in L, what we needed to show.

Corollary 4.6. If K is an existentially closed $\mathfrak {g}$ -field, then K is PAC.

Proof Since an algebraic extension of a PAC field is a PAC field (see [Reference Fried and Jarden10, Corollary 11.2.5]), it is enough to use Proposition 4.5 and Theorem 4.4.

For the boundedness part, we would like to single out first the following Galois-theoretic result, which appeared in some form in [Reference Sjögren28], [Reference Hoffmann and Kowalski14, Lemma 3.7], and [Reference Beyarslan and Kowalski3, Lemma 2.8]. We recall that for a field M, $\operatorname {\mathrm{Gal}}(M)$ denotes the absolute Galois group of M (consider as a topological profinite group), that is,

$$ \begin{align*}\operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(M):=\operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}\left(M^{\mathrm{sep}}/M\right)\end{align*} $$

For the necessary background about Frattini covers, we refer the reader to [Reference Fried and Jarden10, Chapter 22].

Proposition 4.7. Suppose that $M\subseteq N$ is a finite Galois field extension. Then the following conditions are equivalent.

  1. (1) The restriction map

    $$ \begin{align*}\mathrm{res}:\operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(M)\longrightarrow \operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(N/M)\end{align*} $$
    is a Frattini cover.
  2. (2) For any separable field extension $M\subseteq M^{\prime }$ , $M^{\prime }$ is not linearly disjoint from N over M.

Proof We will use [Reference Beyarslan and Kowalski3, Lemma 2.8], which says that for any closed subgroup $\mathcal {H}\leqslant \operatorname {\mathrm{Gal}}(M)$ and for

$$ \begin{align*}M^{\prime}:=\left(M^{\operatorname{\mathrm{alg}}}\right)^{\mathcal{H}}\!,\end{align*} $$

the following conditions are equivalent:

  1. (A) $\mathrm{res}(\mathcal {H})=\operatorname {\mathrm{Gal}}(N/M)$ ,

  2. (B) the restriction map

    $$ \begin{align*}\operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(NM^{\prime}/M^{\prime})\longrightarrow \operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(N/M)\end{align*} $$
    is an isomorphism.

It is easy to see that Condition (B) above is equivalent to saying that $M^{\prime }$ is linearly disjoint from N over M. Since the restriction map

$$ \begin{align*}\mathrm{res}:\operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(M)\longrightarrow \operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(N/M)\end{align*} $$

is a Frattini cover if and only if for each proper closed subgroup $\mathcal {H}$ as above, we have $\mathrm{res}(\mathcal {H})\neq \operatorname {\mathrm{Gal}}(N/M)$ , the result follows.

Our next aim is to show that if K is an existentially closed $\mathfrak {g}$ -field, then $K^{\mathfrak {g}}$ is bounded, that is the absolute Galois group $\operatorname {\mathrm{Gal}}(K^{\mathfrak {g}})$ is small. As in the case of actions of finite groups, we will achieve this aim by identifying $\operatorname {\mathrm{Gal}}(K^{\mathfrak {g}})$ with the universal Frattini cover of a certain finite group. Similarly as in the group case, the whole strength of the existential closedness assumption is not necessary here, we will only need the property expressed in the following definition.

Definition 4.8. A $\mathfrak {g}$ -field K is $\mathfrak {g}$ -closed, if there are no non-trivial $\mathfrak {g}$ -field extensions $K\subset L$ such that the pure field extension $K\subset L$ is algebraic.

The following result is crucial for our proof of the simplicity of the theory $\mathfrak {g}$ -DCF.

Theorem 4.9. Assume that a $\mathfrak {g}$ -field K is $\mathfrak {g}$ -closed and $C=K^{\mathfrak {g}}$ . Let $C\subseteq K^{\mathrm{nc}}$ be the normal closure of the field extension $C\subseteq K$ . Then, the restriction map:

$$ \begin{align*}\operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(C)\longrightarrow \operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(K^{\mathrm{nc}}/C)\end{align*} $$

is a Frattini cover.

Proof Let us define:

$$ \begin{align*}C^{\mathrm{ins}}:=\left(K^{\mathrm{nc}}\right)^{\operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(K^{\mathrm{nc}}/C)}\!.\end{align*} $$

By [Reference Isaacs16, Theorem 19.18], the extension $C\subseteq C^{\mathrm{ins}}$ is purely inseparable, the extension $C^{\mathrm{ins}}\subseteq K^{\mathrm{nc}}$ is Galois, and the following diagram commutes:

Therefore, by Proposition 4.7, it is enough to show that for any proper Galois field extension $C^{\mathrm{ins}}\subset C^{\mathrm{ins}^{\prime }}$ , we have that $K^{\mathrm{nc}}$ is not linearly disjoint from $C^{\mathrm{ins}^{\prime }}$ over $C^{\mathrm{ins}}$ . Let us assume that there is a proper Galois field extension $C^{\mathrm{ins}}\subset C^{\mathrm{ins}^{\prime }}$ such that $K^{\mathrm{nc}}$ is linearly disjoint from $C^{\mathrm{ins}^{\prime }}$ over $C^{\mathrm{ins}}$ . We aim to reach a contradiction. Let $C\subseteq C^{\prime }$ be the maximal separable subextension of the extension $C\subset C^{\mathrm{ins}^{\prime }}$ . The situation is summarized in the following commutative diagram, where all the arrows are inclusions of fields:

We have the following:

$$ \begin{align*}[C^{\mathrm{ins}^{\prime}}:C^{\mathrm{ins}}]=[C^{\mathrm{ins}^{\prime}}:C]_{\mathrm{sep}}=[C^{\prime}:C],\end{align*} $$
$$ \begin{align*}[C^{\mathrm{ins}}:C]=[C^{\mathrm{ins}^{\prime}}:C]_{\mathrm{ins}}=[C^{\mathrm{ins}^{\prime}}:C^{\prime}].\end{align*} $$

Therefore, $C\subset C^{\prime }$ is a proper Galois extension and we have:

$$ \begin{align*}\operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(C^{\prime}/C)\cong \operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}( C^{\mathrm{ins}^{\prime}}/C^{\mathrm{ins}}),\ \ \ \ K^{\mathrm{nc}}\cap C^{\prime}= C.\end{align*} $$

Since the extension $C\subset C^{\prime }$ is Galois and $K\cap C^{\prime }= C$ , we obtain that K is linearly disjoint from $C^{\prime }$ over C. Hence, we have:

$$ \begin{align*}KC^{\prime}\cong K{\kern-1pt}\otimes_{C}C^{\prime}\!,\end{align*} $$

and by Lemma 3.3, the field extension $K\subset KC^{\prime }$ has a $\mathfrak {g}$ -field extension structure. Since the field extension $K\subset KC^{\prime }$ is proper algebraic, we get a contradiction with the assumption that K is $\mathfrak {g}$ -closed.

One could wonder whether the field extension $C\subseteq K$ appearing in the statement of Theorem 4.9 is a Galois extension (as it is the case when we consider the actions of groups) or perhaps it is only a normal extension or it is only a separable extension. The example below shows that “anything may happen,” hence we really need to consider the fields $K^{\mathrm{nc}}$ and $C^{\mathrm{ins}}$ in the proof of Theorem 4.9.

Example 4.10.

  1. (1) If $\mathrm{char}(\textbf {k})=p>0$ , $\mathfrak {g}=\mathbb {G}_{\text {a}}[1]$ , and K is a $\mathfrak {g}$ -field such that the $\mathfrak {g}$ -action is non-trivial, then the extension $K^{\mathfrak {g}}\subset K$ is purely inseparable and non-trivial (see [Reference Hoffmann and Kowalski13, Definition 3.5 and Lemma 3.16]).

  2. (2) To see that the field extension $K^{\mathfrak {g}}\subseteq K$ need not be normal (even in the case when $\mathfrak {g}$ is étale), one can consider the $\mathfrak {g}$ -field ${\mathbb {Q}}(\sqrt [3]{2})$ from the end of Example 2.3(4), where $\mathfrak {g}$ is the group scheme of the third roots of unity over ${\mathbb {Q}}$ . Then, we have:

    $$ \begin{align*}\left({\mathbb{Q}}(\sqrt[3]{2})\right)^{\mathfrak{g}}={\mathbb{Q}}\!,\end{align*} $$
    and the field extension ${\mathbb {Q}}\subset {\mathbb {Q}}(\sqrt [3]{2})$ is clearly not normal.

Corollary 4.11. If K is an existentially closed $\mathfrak {g}$ -field, then the field $K^{\mathfrak {g}}$ is PAC and bounded.

Proof The PAC part is exactly Proposition 4.5.

We proceed to show the boundedness part. Since an existentially closed $\mathfrak {g}$ -field is $\mathfrak {g}$ -closed, we can apply Theorem 4.9 and obtain that the restriction map

$$ \begin{align*}\operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(K^{\mathfrak{g}})\longrightarrow \operatorname{\mathrm{Gal}}(K^{\mathrm{nc}}/K^{\mathfrak{g}})\end{align*} $$

is a Frattini cover. Since a Frattini cover of a topologically finitely generated profinite group (in our case, it just the finite group $\operatorname {\mathrm{Gal}}(K^{\mathrm{nc}}/K^{\mathfrak {g}})$ ) is finitely generated again (see [Reference Fried and Jarden10, Corollary 22.5.3]), we get that the profinite group $\operatorname {\mathrm{Gal}}(K^{\mathfrak {g}})$ is topologically finitely generated. By [Reference Ribes and Zalesskii26, Proposition 2.5.1(a)], the profinite group $\operatorname {\mathrm{Gal}}(K^{\mathfrak {g}})$ is small, therefore the field $K^{\mathfrak {g}}$ is bounded.

Theorem 4.12. The theory $\mathfrak {g}-\mathrm{DCF}$ is simple.

Proof For any model $(K,\mathfrak {g})$ of $\mathfrak {g}$ -DCF, by Theorem 4.4, the theory of $(K,\mathfrak {g})$ is bi-interpretable with the theory of the pure field $K^{\mathfrak {g}}$ (the description of this bi-interpretation given in [Reference Hoffmann and Kowalski14, Remark 2.3] works here as well). By Corollary 4.11, the field $K^{\mathfrak {g}}$ is PAC and bounded. Therefore, by [Reference Kim18, Fact 2.6.7], the theory of the field $K^{\mathfrak {g}}$ is simple.

Remark 4.13. We describe here some special cases and comment on possible improvements and generalizations.

  1. (1) If the group scheme $\mathfrak {g}$ is infinitesimal (see Example 2.3(2)), then the theory $\mathfrak {g}$ -DCF is stable and it coincides with one of the theories considered in [Reference Hoffmann and Kowalski13].

  2. (2) If the group scheme $\mathfrak {g}=G_{\textbf {k}}$ is constant (G is a finite group), then we have

    $$ \begin{align*}\mathfrak{g}-\mathrm{DCF}=G-\mathrm{TCF}\!,\end{align*} $$
    where G-TCF is the theory considered in [Reference Hoffmann and Kowalski14]. In particular, this theory is supersimple of finite rank e coinciding with the order of G.
  3. (3) Suppose that the group scheme $\mathfrak {g}$ is neither infinitesimal nor étale. It means that $\mathfrak {g}\neq \mathfrak {g}^{0}$ and $\mathfrak {g}\neq \mathfrak {g}_{0}$ , where $\mathfrak {g}^{0}$ and $\mathfrak {g}_{0}$ come from the exact sequence considered in the beginning of Section 1. In this case, using [Reference Kim18, Fact 2.6.7] again, the theory $\mathfrak {g}$ -DCF is strictly simple (that is, simple, not stable, and not supersimple), since the PAC field $K^{\mathfrak {g}}$ is neither separably closed nor perfect.

  4. (4) We consider in Section 5 finite group schemes $\mathfrak {g}$ of some special kind, which are of the type described in Item $(3)$ above. For such finite group schemes, the theory $\mathfrak {g}-\mathrm{DCF}$ considered in a certain expanded language has a finer description, which is obtained using the results from [Reference Hoffmann11] (see Corollary 5.8).

  5. (5) As we pointed out in Section 2, the $\mathfrak {g}$ -rings considered in this paper are a very special case of the rings with iterative operators considered in [Reference Moosa and Scanlon23]. One may wonder whether our main results (Theorems 3.6 and 4.12) could be generalized to the context considered in [Reference Moosa and Scanlon23]. Unfortunately, it looks impossible at this moment, since, for example, actions of locally finite groups on rings constitute still quite a special case of the situation from [Reference Moosa and Scanlon23]. But the theory of actions of such groups on fields need not be companionable, as a recent work of Beyarslan and the second author shows [Reference Beyarslan and Kowalski3]. More precisely, the case of Abelian torsion groups is considered in [Reference Beyarslan and Kowalski3] and a rather unexpected algebraic condition on such groups is given in [Reference Beyarslan and Kowalski3, Theorem 1.1], which is equivalent to the companionability the theory mentioned above. For the general case of locally finite groups, it is even unclear what should be conjecturally taken for this algebraic condition.

5 Group actions on fields of finite imperfection degree

In this section, we use the results from the previous sections to show the existence and to describe some properties of a model complete theory of actions of a fixed finite group on fields of finite imperfection degree. Let us describe first the general setting of the model-theoretic dynamics from [Reference Hoffmann11], which will be used here. We start from an L-theory T having a model companion $T^{\operatorname {\mathrm{mc}}}$ and we assume that $T^{\operatorname {\mathrm{mc}}}$ has elimination of quantifiers. For a fixed group G, we expand the language L to the language $L_{G}$ by adding unary function symbols for elements of G. Then, $T_{G}$ is the obvious $L_{G}$ -theory of G-actions by automorphisms on models of T, and it is an interesting question whether a model companion of $T_{G}$ exists (if it exists, it is denoted by $T_{G}^{\operatorname {\mathrm{mc}}}$ ). In the case of $G={\mathbb {Z}}$ , the above question is about the existence of an axiomatization of the theory of generic automorphism of models of T (see [Reference Chatzidakis and Pillay7]). It is well-known (see e.g., [Reference Chatzidakis and Hrushovski6]) that if T is the theory of fields, then the theory $T_{{\mathbb {Z}}}^{\operatorname {\mathrm{mc}}}$ (=ACFA) exists. In [Reference Chatzidakis5], Chatzidakis shows the existence of the theory $T_{{\mathbb {Z}}}^{\operatorname {\mathrm{mc}}}$ , where T is the theory of separably closed fields of a fixed imperfection degree in the language of fields expanded by symbols for p-basis and $\lambda $ -functions.

If G is a finite group and T is the theory of fields, then the theory $T_{G}^{\operatorname {\mathrm{mc}}}$ exists (see [Reference Hoffmann and Kowalski14, Reference Sjögren28]); this theory was denoted by G-TCF in [Reference Hoffmann and Kowalski14]. It is a good moment now to warn the reader that the theory $T_{G}^{\operatorname {\mathrm{mc}}}$ usually does not imply the theory $T^{\operatorname {\mathrm{mc}}}$ : for example the models of G-TCF are not algebraically (or even separably) closed for a non-trivial finite group G (see [Reference Hoffmann and Kowalski14]). The main aim of this section is to show a variant of Chatzidakis’ existence result from [Reference Chatzidakis5] for a finite group G replacing the infinite cyclic group, which also gives one more example of the class of theories satisfying the conditions from [Reference Hoffmann11]. To achieve this aim, we do not follow the methods from [Reference Chatzidakis5], but we provide a new argument using Theorem 3.6.

We start with describing our version of the general set-up from [Reference Hoffmann11]. Let us fix a positive integer e (it will not play the role of the number e from the previous sections!) and a prime number p. For the notion of a p-basis, the reader may consult [Reference Chatzidakis5, Section 1.5]. The imperfection degree of a field K of characteristic p is the cardinality of its p-basis. We define the language L as the language of fields with the extra constant symbols $b=\{b_{1},\ldots ,b_{e}\}$ and the extra unary function symbols $\lambda =\{\lambda _{i}\;|\;i\in [p]^{e}\}$ , where $[p]:=\{0,\ldots ,p-1\}$ . We set as T the L-theory $\mathrm{SF}_{p,e}$ , which is such that its models $(K;b,\lambda )$ satisfy the following:

  • K is a field of characteristic p;

  • the set $\{b_{1},\ldots ,b_{e}\}$ is a p-basis of K;

  • for each $x\in K$ , we have:

    $$ \begin{align*}x=\sum\limits_{i\in[p]^{e}}\lambda_{i}(x)^{p}b^{i}\!.\end{align*} $$

It is well-known that the model companion $T^{\operatorname {\mathrm{mc}}}$ is the theory of separably closed fields which are models of $\mathrm{SF}_{p,e}$ ; this theory is denoted by $\mathrm{SCF}_{p,e}$ . The theory $\mathrm{SCF}_{p,e}$ is strictly stable and has quantifier elimination (Theorem 2.3 in [Reference Delon and Bouscaren8]), so we are in the general situation from [Reference Hoffmann11].

We describe now how to add dynamics to the theory T. Let G be a finite group of order $e^{\prime }$ . As explained above, $L_{G}$ denotes the language L expanded by unary function symbols $\{\sigma _{g}\;|\;g\in G\}$ and $T_{G}=(\mathrm{SF}_{p,e})_{G}$ is the theory of group actions of G on models of $\mathrm{SF}_{p,e}$ by L-automorphisms. To show the existence of the theory $T_{G}^{\operatorname {\mathrm{mc}}}$ , we will use the theory $\mathfrak {g}-\mathrm{DCF}$ (see Theorem 3.6) for $\textbf {k}={\mathbb {F}}_{p}$ and the following finite group scheme:

$$ \begin{align*}\mathfrak{g}:=\mathbb{G}_{\mathrm{a}}^{e}[1]\times G_{{\mathbb{F}}_{p}}\!.\end{align*} $$

For the rest of this section, $\mathfrak {g}$ denotes the finite group scheme defined above, so we diverge again from the notation of the previous sections, since e is not anymore the order of $\mathfrak {g}$ (which is now $p^{e}+e^{\prime }$ ).

By Example 2.3(3), a $\mathfrak {g}$ -field $(K,\partial )$ is the same as a field K of characteristic p with derivations $D_{1},\ldots ,D_{e}$ and with an action of the group G by field automorphisms on K such that the following conditions hold:

  • the derivations $D_{1},\ldots ,D_{e}$ commute with each other;

  • for each $i\leqslant e$ , we have $D_{i}^{(p)}=0$ (the composition of $D_{i}$ with itself p times);

  • the action of G commutes with the derivations $D_{1},\ldots ,D_{e}$ .

Let us define:

$$ \begin{align*}C_{K}:=K^{\mathbb{G}_{\mathrm{a}}^{e}[1]}=\ker\left(D_{1}\right)\cap \ldots \cap \ker\left(D_{e}\right)\!.\end{align*} $$

We clearly have $K^{p}\subseteq C_{K}$ and the next result shows that there is a $\mathfrak {g}$ -field extension of K where the equality holds, which will be crucial in the proof of Theorem 5.6 (our aim here).

Lemma 5.1. For any $\mathfrak {g}$ -field K, there is a $\mathfrak {g}$ -field extension $K\subseteq M$ such that $C_{M}=M^{p}$ .

Proof If $C_{K}=K^{p}$ , then there is nothing to do, so let us take $t\in C_{K}\setminus K^{p}$ . Then, we have:

$$ \begin{align*}G\cdot t\subset C_{K}\setminus K^{p}\!.\end{align*} $$

We take a p-basis $\{t_{1}=t,\ldots ,t_{k}\}$ of $K^{p}(G\cdot t)$ over $K^{p}$ and we define:

$$ \begin{align*}K_{1}:=K\left(t_{1}^{1/p},\ldots,t_{k}^{1/p}\right)\!.\end{align*} $$

By setting for any $i\leqslant e$ and $j\leqslant k$ :

$$ \begin{align*}D_{i}\left(t_{j}^{1/p}\right):=0,\end{align*} $$

$K_{1}$ becomes a $\mathbb {G}_{\text {a}}^{e}[1]$ -field extension of K. For any $g\in G$ and any $j\leqslant k$ , we define:

$$ \begin{align*}g\cdot t_{j}^{1/p}:=(g\cdot t_{j})^{1/p}\!,\end{align*} $$

which gives a unique extension of the G-action from K to $K_{1}$ . This makes $K_{1}$ a $\mathfrak {g}$ -field extension of K and by repeating this process, we can define M as the union of a tower of $\mathfrak {g}$ -field extensions of K.

For a $\mathfrak {g}$ -field K, it will be crucial to find a p-basis of K in the subfield of G-invariants $K^{G}$ , which is allowed by the next result.

Lemma 5.2. Suppose that the group G acts on a field K of characteristic p and of imperfection degree e. Then, there is a p-basis of K in $K^{G}$ .

Proof Let us denote $K_{0}:=K^{G}$ and consider the following commutative diagram of field extensions:

By applying the Frobenius map, we have $[K:K_{0}]=[K^{p}:K_{0}^{p}]$ . Therefore, we obtain:

$$ \begin{align*}[K:K^{p}]=[K_{0}:K_{0}^{p}],\end{align*} $$

so the imperfection degree of $K_{0}$ is e as well. Since the field extension $K_{0}^{p}\subseteq K_{0}$ is purely inseparable and the extension $K_{0}^{p}\subseteq K^{p}$ is Galois (because the extension $K_{0}\subseteq K$ is Galois), we obtain that $K_{0}$ is linearly disjoint from $K^{p}$ over $K_{0}^{p}$ . The linear disjointness and the fact that the imperfection degree of $K_{0}$ is finite and coincides with the imperfection degree of $K_{0}$ imply that any p-basis of $K_{0}$ is a p-basis of K as well.

Proposition 5.3. If K is a model of $\mathfrak {g}-\mathrm{DCF}$ , then $C_{K}=K^{p}$ and the imperfection degree of K is e.

Proof Since K is an existentially closed $\mathfrak {g}$ -field, Lemma 5.1 implies that $C_{K}=K^{p}$ . By [Reference Hoffmann and Kowalski14, Corollary 3.21], we get that $[K:C_{K}]\leqslant p^{e}$ . Therefore (by the existential closedness again), it is enough to find a $\mathfrak {g}$ -field extension $K\subseteq N$ such that the imperfection degree of N is e.

Let us consider the field of rational functions ${\mathbb {F}}_{p}(X_{1},\ldots ,X_{e})$ with the standard $\mathbb {G}_{\text {a}}^{e}[1]$ -field structure given by $D_{i}(X_{j})=\delta ^{j}_{i}$ (the Kronecker delta) and with the trivial action of G. Then, ${\mathbb {F}}_{p}(X_{1},\ldots ,X_{e})$ becomes a $\mathfrak {g}$ -field of imperfection degree e and such that:

$$ \begin{align*}C_{{\mathbb{F}}_{p}(X_{1},\ldots,X_{e})}={\mathbb{F}}_{p}\left(X_{1}^{p},\ldots,X_{e}^{p}\right)=\left({\mathbb{F}}_{p}(X_{1},\ldots,X_{e})\right)^{p}\!.\end{align*} $$

We consider now the following field:

$$ \begin{align*}M:=\mathrm{Frac}\left(K{\kern-1pt}\otimes_{{\mathbb{F}}_{p}}{\mathbb{F}}_{p}(X_{1},\ldots,X_{e})\right)\!.\end{align*} $$

By Lemma 3.3 (both of the items), M is a $\mathfrak {g}$ -field and it is naturally a $\mathfrak {g}$ -field extension of K and ${\mathbb {F}}_{p}(X_{1},\ldots ,X_{e})$ . Let N be a $\mathfrak {g}$ -field extension of M provided by Lemma 5.1, so $N^{p}=C_{N}$ . By [Reference Hoffmann and Kowalski14, Lemma 3.22], the field extension ${\mathbb {F}}_{p}(X_{1},\ldots ,X_{e})\subseteq N$ is separable, hence the imperfection degree of N is at least e. Since $N^{p}=C_{N}$ , we obtain (using [Reference Hoffmann and Kowalski14, Corollary 3.21] again) that the imperfection degree of N is exactly e.

For our main bi-interpretability result, we need to consider the theory $\mathfrak {g}$ -DCF in an expanded language. We set the following.

  1. (1) Let $L_{\mathfrak {g},b}$ be the language $L_{\mathfrak {g}}$ (see Section 2.2) expanded by the constant symbols $b_{1},\ldots ,b_{e}$ .

  2. (2) Let $\mathfrak {g}-\mathrm{DF}_{b}$ be the $L_{\mathfrak {g},b}$ -theory of $\mathfrak {g}$ -fields such that:

    1. (a) $\{b_{1},\ldots ,b_{e}\}$ is a p-basis;

    2. (b) $\{b_{1},\ldots ,b_{e}\}$ is contained in the invariants of the action of G;

    3. (c) for all $i,j\leqslant e$ , we have:

      $$ \begin{align*}D_{i}(b_{j})=\delta^{j}_{i}\ \ \ \ \ \ \text{(the Kronecker delta).}\end{align*} $$
  3. (3) We define the $L_{\mathfrak {g},b}$ -theory $\mathfrak {g}-\mathrm{DCF}_{b}$ as the theory $\mathfrak {g}-\mathrm{DCF}$ with the same extra conditions on the fixed p-basis and the G-invariants as in Item $(2)$ above.

The next lemma shows that the theory $\mathfrak {g}-\mathrm{DF}_{b}$ has the expected properties.

Lemma 5.4. We have the following.

  1. (1) If K is a model of $\mathfrak {g}-\mathrm{DF}_{b}$ , then the imperfection degree of K is e and $C_{K}=K^{p}$ .

  2. (2) The theory $\mathfrak {g}-\mathrm{DF}_{b}$ is bi-interpretable with the theory $T_{G}=(\mathrm{SF}_{p,e})_{G}$ .

Proof For the proof of Item $(1)$ , the statement about the imperfection degree of K is clear from the axiomatization of the theory $\mathfrak {g}-\mathrm{DF}_{b}$ . To show that $C_{K}=K^{p}$ , we consider for each $i\leqslant e$ the following subfield of K:

$$ \begin{align*}C_{i}:=\ker(D_{1})\cap \cdots \cap \ker(D_{i}).\end{align*} $$

Then, we have the following tower of fields:

$$ \begin{align*}K^{p}\subseteq C_{K}=C_{e}\varsubsetneq C_{e-1} \varsubsetneq \cdots \varsubsetneq C_{1} \varsubsetneq K,\end{align*} $$

where the properness of the inclusions is witnessed by $b_{i}\in C_{i-1}\setminus C_{i}$ (we set $C_{0}:=K$ ). Therefore, we get:

$$ \begin{align*}p^{e}=[K:K^{p}]\geqslant [K:C_{K}]\geqslant p^{e}\!,\end{align*} $$

which implies that $C_{K}=K^{p}$ .

For the proof of Item $(2)$ , if $(K;b,D_{1},\ldots D_{e},\sigma _{g})_{g\in G}$ is a model of $\mathfrak {g}-\mathrm{DF}_{b}$ , then $(K;b,\sigma _{g})_{g\in G}$ obviously interprets a model of $T_{G}$ , since $\lambda $ -functions are definable in a field with a p-basis. If $(K;b,\lambda ,\sigma _{g})_{g\in G}$ is a model of $T_{G}$ , then we forget about the $\lambda $ -functions and define the derivations by the following formula (as in the proof of Proposition 5.3):

$$ \begin{align*}D_{j}(b_{i})=\delta^{j}_{i}\!.\end{align*} $$

Then, it is standard that $(K;b,D_{1},\ldots D_{e},\sigma _{g})_{g\in G}$ is a model of $\mathfrak {g}-\mathrm{DF}_{b}$ . It is also clear that the two interpretations above are mutually inversive.

The next result is crucial for the proof of Theorem 5.6.

Proposition 5.5. The theory $\mathfrak {g}-\mathrm{DCF}_{b}$ is a model companion of the theory $\mathfrak {g}-\mathrm{DF}_{b}$ .

Proof Clearly, any model of $\mathfrak {g}-\mathrm{DCF}_{b}$ is a model of $\mathfrak {g}-\mathrm{DF}_{b}$ . We need to show that each model of $\mathfrak {g}-\mathrm{DF}_{b}$ embeds into a model of $\mathfrak {g}-\mathrm{DCF}_{b}$ and that the theory $\mathfrak {g}-\mathrm{DCF}_{b}$ is model complete.

It is easy to see the model completeness part, since the theory $\mathfrak {g}-\mathrm{DCF}_{b}$ is an expansion by constants of the model complete (by Theorem 3.6) theory $\mathfrak {g}-\mathrm{DCF}$ .

Let $(K;b,\partial )$ be a model of the theory $\mathfrak {g}-\mathrm{DF}_{b}$ . By Theorem 3.6, the $\mathfrak {g}$ -field $(K,\partial )$ has a $\mathfrak {g}$ -field extension $(K^{\prime },\partial ^{\prime })$ which is a model of the theory $\mathfrak {g}-\mathrm{DCF}$ . By Lemma 5.4, we have $C_{K}=K^{p}$ . Therefore, by [Reference Hoffmann and Kowalski14, Lemma 3.22], the field extension $K\subseteq K^{\prime }$ is separable. Since b is a p-basis of K and the extension $K\subseteq K^{\prime }$ is separable, b is p-independent in $K^{\prime }$ . By Proposition 5.3, the imperfection invariant of $K^{\prime }$ is e, so b is a p-basis of $K^{\prime }$ as well. Hence $(K^{\prime };b,\partial ^{\prime })$ is a model of $\mathfrak {g}-\mathrm{DCF}_{b}$ and $(K^{\prime };b,\partial ^{\prime })$ is also an extension of $(K;b,\partial )$ , which finishes the proof.

Before stating the main result of this section, we advice the reader to recall our notational set-up regarding the theories $T,T_{G},T^{\operatorname {\mathrm{mc}}},T^{\operatorname {\mathrm{mc}}}_{G}$ from the beginning of this section.

Theorem 5.6. The theory $T_{G}^{\operatorname {\mathrm{mc}}}$ exists and it is bi-interpretable with the theory $\mathfrak {g}-\mathrm{DCF}_{b}$ . In particular, the theory $T_{G}^{\operatorname {\mathrm{mc}}}$ is strictly simple.

Proof The existence part follows from the bi-interpretability part, which is clear by Lemma 5.4(2) and Proposition 5.5. The “in particular” part follows from Remark 4.13 and the bi-interpretability part above.

Remark 5.7. As we have pointed out before, the theory $T_{G}^{\operatorname {\mathrm{mc}}}$ need not imply the theory $T^{\operatorname {\mathrm{mc}}}$ and indeed: if G is non-trivial, then the underlying fields of models of $T_{G}^{\operatorname {\mathrm{mc}}}$ are not separably closed, since the are no non-trivial actions of a finite group on a separably closed field of positive characteristic (the Artin–Schreier theorem).

We can apply now the techniques from [Reference Hoffmann11] to obtain several model-theoretic properties of the theory $T_{G}^{\operatorname {\mathrm{mc}}}$ . We assume that $\mathfrak {C}$ is a sufficiently saturated model of $T_{G}^{\operatorname {\mathrm{mc}}}$ and that $\mathfrak {C}$ is embedded in a sufficiently saturated model $\mathfrak {D}$ of $T^{\operatorname {\mathrm{mc}}}=\mathrm{SCF}_{p,e}$ . In other words, $\mathfrak {C}$ is an existentially closed field with a p-basis, $\lambda $ -functions and a group action of G, and $\mathfrak {D}$ is an existentially closed field with a p-basis and $\lambda $ -functions. We will consider the model-theoretic algebraic closure inside $\mathfrak {C}$ , denoted by $\operatorname {\mathrm{acl}}_{G}(\,\cdot \,)$ , and the model-theoretic algebraic closure inside $\mathfrak {D}$ , denoted by $\operatorname {\mathrm{acl}}_{\operatorname {\mathrm{sep}}}(\,\cdot \,)$ . By [Reference Hrushovski15, Fact 2.7], if $A\subseteq \mathfrak {D}$ then $\operatorname {\mathrm{acl}}_{\operatorname {\mathrm{sep}}}(A)$ coincides with the field theoretic algebraic closure in $\mathfrak {D}$ of the subfield generated by the p-basis and the values of the $\lambda $ -functions on the elements of A.

Corollary 5.8. Let $A,B,C$ be small subsets of $\mathfrak {C}$ such that $C\subseteq A\cap B$ .

  1. (1) By [Reference Hoffmann11, Corollary 4.12], we have:

    $$ \begin{align*}\operatorname{\mathrm{acl}}_{G}(A)=\operatorname{\mathrm{acl}}_{\operatorname{\mathrm{sep}}}(G\cdot A) \cap\mathfrak{C}\!.\end{align*} $$
  2. (2) By [Reference Hoffmann11, Corollary 4.28], we have:

    i.e., the forking independence in $T_{G}^{\operatorname {\mathrm{mc}}}$ is given by the G-action and the forking independence in $T^{\operatorname {\mathrm{mc}}}=\mathrm{SCF}_{p,e}$ .
  3. (3) By [Reference Hoffmann11, Remark 4.13], $T_{G}^{\operatorname {\mathrm{mc}}}$ has “almost quantifier elimination” (similarly as ACFA).

  4. (4) By [Reference Hoffmann11, Remark 4.36], $T_{G}^{\operatorname {\mathrm{mc}}}$ has geometric elimination of imaginaries.

It was shown in [Reference Beyarslan and Kowalski2] that the theory of actions of a fixed virtually free group on fields has a model companion. An analogous result holds in the case of actions of a finite group (Theorem 5.6) or the infinite cyclic group [Reference Chatzidakis5] on fields of finite imperfection degree. The following natural question arises.

Question 5.9. Does the theory of actions of a fixed virtually free group on fields of finite imperfection degree have a model companion? More generally, what is the class of groups such that the model companion above exists?

Let us point out that the “more generally” part of Question 5.9 is wide open even in the case of group actions on arbitrary fields.

Acknowledgments

Hoffmann is supported by the Polish National Agency for Academic Exchange. Kowalski is supported by the Narodowe Centrum Nauki grant no. 2018/31/B/ST1/00357 and by the Tübitak 1001 grant no. 119F397.

References

Beyarslan, Ö., Hoffmann, D. M., Kamensky, M., and Kowalski, P., Model theory of fields with free operators in positive characteristic . Transactions of the American Mathematical Society , vol. 372 (2019), no. 8, pp. 59916016.10.1090/tran/7896CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beyarslan, Ö. and Kowalski, P., Model theory of fields with virtually free group actions . Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society , vol. 118 (2019), no. 2, pp. 221256.Google Scholar
Beyarslan, Ö. and Kowalski, P., Model theory of Galois actions of torsion abelian groups, submitted. Preprint, 2020, https://arxiv.org/pdf/2003.02329.pdf.Google Scholar
Chase, S. U., Infinitesimal group scheme actions on finite field extensions . American Journal of Mathematics , vol. 98 (1976), no. 2, pp. 441480.10.2307/2373897CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chatzidakis, Z., Generic automorphisms of separably closed fields . Illinois Journal of Mathematics , vol. 45 (2002), no. 3, pp. 693733.Google Scholar
Chatzidakis, Z. and Hrushovski, E., Model theory of difference fields . Transactions of the American Mathematical Society , vol. 351 (2000), no. 8, pp. 29973071.Google Scholar
Chatzidakis, Z. and Pillay, A., Generic structures and simple theories . Annals of Pure and Applied Logic , vol. 95 (1998), pp. 7192.Google Scholar
Delon, F., Separably closed fields , Model Theory, Algebra, and Geometry: An Introduction to E. Hrushovski’s Proof of the Geometric Mordell–Lang Conjecture (Bouscaren, E., editor), Lecture Notes in Mathematics, vol. 1696, Springer, Berlin, 1998, pp. 143176.Google Scholar
Demazure, M. and Gabriel, P., Groupes Algébriques, Vol. 1, Géométrie Algébrique, Généralités, Groupes Commutatifs , Masson, Paris, 1970.Google Scholar
Fried, M. D. and Jarden, M., Field arithmetic , Ergebnisse der Mathematik und ihrer Grenzgebiete, 3. Folge/A Series of Modern Surveys in Mathematics, Springer, Berlin, 2008.Google Scholar
Hoffmann, D. M., Model theoretic dynamics in Galois fashion . Annals of Pure and Applied Logic , vol. 170 (2019), no. 7, pp. 755804.10.1016/j.apal.2019.02.002CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hoffmann, D. M. and Kowalski, P., Integrating Hasse–Schmidt derivations . Journal of Pure and Applied Algebra , vol. 219 (2015), no. 4, pp. 875896.10.1016/j.jpaa.2014.05.024CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hoffmann, D. M. and Kowalski, P., Existentially closed fields with $\ G$ -derivations . Journal of London Mathematical Society , vol. 93 (2016), no. 3, pp. 590618.10.1112/jlms/jdw009CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hoffmann, D. M. and Kowalski, P., Existentially closed fields with finite group actions . Journal of Mathematical Logic , vol. 18 (2018), no. 1, p. 1850003.Google Scholar
Hrushovski, E., The Mordell–Lang conjecture for function fields . Journal of the American Mathematical Society , vol. 9 (1996), no. 3, pp. 667690.Google Scholar
Isaacs, I. M., Algebra. A Graduate Course . Graduate Studies in Mathematics, vol. 100, American Mathematical Society, Providence, 1994.Google Scholar
Kamensky, M., Tannakian formalism over fields with operators . International Mathematics Research Notices , vol. 24 (2013), pp. 55715622.Google Scholar
Kim, B., Simplicity Theory , Oxford Logic Guides, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2013.Google Scholar
Kowalski, P., Geometric axioms for existentially closed Hasse fields . Annals of Pure and Applied Logic , vol. 135 (2005), pp. 286302.Google Scholar
Montgomery, S., Fixed Rings of Finite Automorphism Groups of Associative Rings , Lecture Notes in Mathematics, Springer, Berlin, 1980.10.1007/BFb0091561CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Montgomery, S., Hopf Algebras and Their Actions on Rings , Regional Conference Series in Mathematics, 82, American Mathematical Society, Providence, 1993.Google Scholar
Moosa, R. and Scanlon, T., Jet and prolongation spaces . Journal of the Institute of Mathematics of Jussieu , vol. 9 (2010), no. 2, pp. 391430.Google Scholar
Moosa, R. and Scanlon, T., Generalized Hasse-Schmidt varieties and their jet spaces . Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society , vol. 103 (2011), no. 2, pp. 197234.Google Scholar
Moosa, R. and Scanlon, T., Model theory of fields with free operators in characteristic zero . Journal of Mathematical Logic , vol. 14 (2014), no. 2, p. 1450009.Google Scholar
Mumford, D., Abelian Varieties , Tata Institute of Fundamental Research Studies in Mathematics, Bombay [by] Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1974.Google Scholar
Ribes, L. and Zalesskii, P., Profinite Groups , Springer, New York, 2000.Google Scholar
Serre, J. P., Algebraic Groups and Class Fields: Translation of the French Edition , Graduate Texts in Mathematics Series, Springer, New York, 1988.Google Scholar
Sjögren, N., The Model Theory of Fields with a Group Action , Research Reports in Mathematics, Department of Mathematics Stockholm University, 2005. Available at http://www2.math.su.se/reports/2005/7/. Google Scholar
Waterhouse, W. C., Introduction to Affine Group Schemes , Springer, Berlin, 1979.Google Scholar