We use cookies to distinguish you from other users and to provide you with a better experience on our websites. Close this message to accept cookies or find out how to manage your cookie settings.
An abstract is not available for this content so a preview has been provided. Please use the Get access link above for information on how to access this content.
Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)
References
REFERENCES
Bach, E. (1977). Review article on Postal, P. M. (1974) On Raising (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press). Lg 53. 621–654.Google Scholar
Bresnan, J. (1970). On complementizers: towards a syntactic theory of complement types. FL6. 297–321.Google Scholar
Bresnan, J. (1976). Nonarguments for Raising. LIn7. 485–501.Google Scholar
Botha, R. P. (1976). ‘The theory comparison method’ vs, ‘the theory exposition method’ in linguistic inquiry. Bloomington, Indiana: Indiana University Linguistics Club.Google Scholar
Chomsky, N. (1965). Aspects of the theory of syntax. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Chomsky, N. (1970). Remarks on nominalizations. In Jacobs, R. A. & Rosenbaum, P. S. (eds), Readings in English transformational grammar. Waltham, Mass.: Ginn & Co.Google Scholar
Chomsky, N. (1973). Conditions on transformations. In Anderson, S. R. & Kiparsky, P. (eds), A Festschrift for Morris Halle. New York: Holt, Rinehart & Winston.Google Scholar
Chomsky, N. (1975). The logical structure of linguistic theory. New York: Plenum.Google Scholar
Chomsky, N. (1976). Reflections on language. Glasgow: Fontana.Google Scholar
Dougherty, R. C. (1973). A survey of linguistic methods and arguments. FL10. 423–490.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. A. (1970). Three reasons for not deriving ‘kill’ from ‘cause to die’. LIn. 1429–438.Google Scholar
Hurford, J. R. (1973). Deriving S from S +is. In Kimball, J. (ed.), Syntax and semantics, Vol. 2. New York: Seminar Press.Google Scholar
Klima, E. S. (1964). Negation in English. In Fodor, J. A. & Katz, J. J. (eds) The structure of language. Englewood Cliffs. N.J.: Prentice-Hall.Google Scholar
Lakoff, G. (1970a). Irregularity in syntax. New York: Holt, Rinehart & Winston.Google Scholar
Lakoff, G. (1970b). Global rules. Lg46. 627–639.Google Scholar
Lightfoot, D. (1976). The theoretical implications of subject raising. FL14. 257–285.Google Scholar
Postal, P. M. (1972). The best theory. in Peters, S. (ed.), Goals of linguistic theory. Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall.Google Scholar
Postal, P. M. (1977). About a ‘nonargument’ for Raising. LIn8. 141–154.Google Scholar
Rosenbaum, P. S. (1967). The grammar of English predicate complement constructions. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Ross, J. R. (1969). Adjectives as noun phrases. In Reibel, D. & Schane, S. (eds), Modern studies in English. Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall.Google Scholar
Ross, J. R. (1970). On declarative sentences. In Jacobs, R. A. & Rosenbaum, P. S. (eds), Readings in English transformational grammar. Waltham, Mass.: Ginn & Co.Google Scholar