Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-vdxz6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-23T19:04:23.914Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Non-agreeing degree constructions

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  04 June 2024

Jon Ander Mendia*
Affiliation:
Universitat Autònoma de Barcelona, Edifici B, Campus UAB, 08193 Bellaterra, Spain
M.Teresa Espinal
Affiliation:
Universitat Autònoma de Barcelona, Edifici B, Campus UAB, 08193 Bellaterra, Spain
*
Corresponding author: Jon Ander Mendia; Email: [email protected]
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

This paper deals with a construction, which we dub Non-Agreeing Degree (NAD) constructions, with the distinguishing property that the agreement pattern between subjects and degree predicates is optionally disrupted, even in languages (like Spanish) where verbs commonly agree with their subjects. We show that the agreeing versus non-agreeing alternation comes with important semantic differences for the interpretation of the degree construction. We provide a first systematic description of this type of constructions and postulate a formal syntactic and semantic analysis. We argue that NAD constructions are characterized by degree predicates that introduce a non-conventional nominal scale and by subjects that are interpreted as equally non-conventional units of measurement. We postulate an intensionalization process on the subject of NAD constructions, which we capture via a general nominalization function that allows a default as well as an ordinary agreement pattern between subject and copula.

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press

1. Introduction

It is common for natural languages to be furnished with means of expressing whether an object has more or less of a certain property than some other object. In languages that have them, these properties, usually referred to as being gradable, are prototypically expressed by lexical items, such as adjectives and adverbs. In turn, gradable expressions themselves may be further modified by other types of degree modifiers, like those introduced by comparative and superlative morphology, adverbs like much, very, and so on.

No doubt prototypical degree constructions like adjectives and their projected functional structures provide the best opportunities to investigate how expressions of degree at large work in natural language. But gradability is not just a property of adjectives and adverbs. Indeed, although they have received much less attention in the literature on degree expressions, nominal expressions may as well be used to express gradable properties, as in Bill is a big stamp-collector or Bill is more of a stamp-collector than Liz.

The mechanisms that underlie such non-canonical degree contexts remain largely understudied and mysterious. Thus, the broader goal of this paper is to shed further light into this lesser studied area of gradability by paying attention to a variety of degree constructions in which a degree modifier acts on an otherwise non-gradable nominal. In order to do so, we investigate a hitherto understudied phenomenon, one with the distinguishing grammatical feature of displaying a seeming agreement disruption between the subject and the main predicate of the clause even in languages where predicates must agree with their subjects. The following examples provide a minimal pair illustrating the agreeing versus non-agreeing contrast in Spanish.Footnote 1

Example (1a) is an ordinary sentence with no agreement disruption, as subject and predicate agree in plural number marking. Its semantic interpretation simply states that three books count as too many books (for whatever purpose is relevant in the context). But also possible are variants like (1b), with what seems like a disrupted agreement pattern on the surface. Nevertheless, despite the agreement mismatch, the sentence is perfectly grammatical. Contrasts like those in (1) are ubiquitous among a large variety of languages, including Romance and Germanic families, but throughout the paper, we focus on Spanish examples.

This type of construction thus seemingly involves a systematic violation of a fundamental grammatical principle, namely, subject-verb agreement. More important for us, however, is the fact that examples like that in (1b) are not fully semantically equivalent to (1a) but come instead with important truth-conditional differences. Intuitively, the sentence in (1a) states that a quantity of three books exceeds (or is sufficient for) some threshold of book quantities. But this may not be so for (1b). What counts as too much in this second case is largely underspecified: it could be virtually any property that may be sensibly predicated of its subject, three books. For instance, (1b) could refer to the fact that reading, writing, summarizing or reporting three books is too much (to meet certain criteria), that the weight of three books exceeds some contextually relevant limitation (e.g. they are too heavy to carry in a flimsy plastic bag), that the height of a stack of three books would be too much (to fill in a gap in a bookshelf), etc.

While the truth-conditional differences between the minimally different (1a) and (1b) are fundamental, the semantic underspecification can nevertheless be reduced by providing an overt nominal complement to the degree predicates demasiado and suficiente. Consider (2). Notice that in (2a) not only the overt nominal complement must be formally identical to the nominal in subject position, but degree expressions must also agree in number with the complement noun.Footnote 2 In (2b), by contrast, there is not only lack of subject-verb agreement but the degree expression cannot be plural, as illustrated in (3).

Thus, generally speaking, the purely syntactic effects of the agreement disruptions observed in like (1b) and (2b) seem to come along with non-trivial consequences for their semantic interpretations, an effect that is yet to be explained. For concreteness, throughout the rest of the paper, we will refer to cases such as (1b) and (2b) as Non-Agreeing Degree (NAD) constructions.

NAD constructions are not limited to expressions of excess and sufficiency, like those in (1b) and (2b) but, in fact, generalize quite broadly to a variety of other degree modifiers, as shown in (4).Footnote 3

The main goal of this paper is twofold, one descriptive and one theoretical. Descriptively, we provide a first investigation of the syntactic distribution as well as the accompanying semantic effects of NAD constructions, with a focus on predicates of excess and sufficiency. From a theoretical standpoint, our overarching goal is, in a nutshell, to investigate the syntactic and semantic principles that underlie alternations, such as those in (1) and (2). More concretely, the main question that we set to answer in this paper pertains to the syntax-semantic mapping puzzle raised by minimal pairs, such as (1) and (2): how can the different semantic interpretations associated with these minimal pairs be accounted for? On the way to answering this question, we will also address the issue of number mismatch: how can the different agreement patterns observed in these minimal pairs be accounted for?

Foreshadowing the upcoming discussion, our main claims about NAD constructions are as follows. From a purely syntactic standpoint, the pairs (1a, b) and (2a, b) share the fact that they are degree predicational sentences. However, semantically, they both perform different tasks. We suggest that semantically, NAD constructions like (1b) and (2b) are like other kinds of ordinary measuring constructions, such as (5). That is, the subject of a NAD construction introduces nominal expressions that may (kilos) or may not (books) be directly compatible with the dimension specified in the predicate (i.e. peso ‘weight’).

The intuition we pursue is that the semantic role of three books in (1b) and (2b) above is the same as that of three kilos in (5): to state that a plurality of three units of books (exactly like three units of kilos) exceeds/is sufficient with respect to some contextually relevant threshold of weight. We propose to break down the division of labor that leads to this semantic interpretation of NAD constructions as involving the following ingredients:

  • A nominal (possibly covert) such as weight, money, work, effort, etc., that contributes the required dimension along which to build a relevant scale.

  • A degree head expressing some form of comparison to a degree, such as too much and enough. Importantly, and unlike other types of gradable predicates, these heads do not by themselves determine any specific dimension.

  • A copula BE.

  • A subject that is interpreted as providing a unit of measurement.

We further propose that subjects of NAD constructions, if they are to provide such units of measurement, must be non-extensional, an intensionalization process that we propose to capture via a general nominalization function. The postulated predication over non-extensional subjects comes, in turn, with additional consequences, which we discuss now. First, subject-verb agreement in NAD constructions is rendered irrelevant, as already pointed out in (2b).

There are two important things to note out of the comparison between (1b) and (2b): (i) plural or singular copulas are both possible, and (ii) irrespective of the number morphology on the verbal form, there is no discernible semantic difference between these NAD constructions: they both convey the same proposition and thus share the same truth-conditions. That is, when measuring weight, money, etc., a three-book unit exceeds or is close to a certain threshold contextually fixed. We take these two properties to be characteristic of NAD constructions. Notice, furthermore, that in (2b) only the copula may ‘agree’ in plural with the subject. The Degree Phrase complement of the copula instead shows no trace of such putative agreement process. However, this is not canonical in Spanish, where predicative copular constructions require the copula and its complement to share phi-features, as illustrated in (2a). Together, these facts suggest that agreement in NAD constructions must be distinguished from the syntactic operation Agree (Chomsky Reference Chomsky, Martin, Michaels and Uriagereka2000, Reference Chomsky, Kenstowicz and Hale2001).

The second important piece of evidence suggesting that subjects of NAD constructions are non-extensional is that they don’t need to be witnessed to be true: unlike (1a) or (2a), neither (1b) nor (2b) imply the existence of values for sets of three books, such that they are too heavy. Instead, the subjects in the latter group of sentences convey ‘any three-book-entity’ has such-and-such property.Footnote 5

The remainder of the paper is organized as follows. Section 2 introduces the syntactic and semantic properties that characterize NAD constructions, such as the requirement of a degree predicate (with a copula BE, a degree head and a nominal complement), and provides an extensive discussion of the types of expressions that may and may not appear as subjects of NAD constructions. Section 3 presents the syntactic structure of predicational NAD constructions and discusses the semantic ingredients of the expression of excess and sufficiency. In this section, the semantics of standard gradable predicates are compared to the semantics of degree heads in combination with plural nominal complements (as in (1a) and (2a)). Section 4 presents the semantic composition of NAD constructions, both with an overt and a covert nominal complement (as in (1b) and (2b)).

2. Syntactic Make-up of NADs and Their Semantic Properties

This section provides a description of the syntactic distribution of the different components that make up NAD constructions. More concretely, we seek to answer the following three questions: (i) What kinds of predicates are involved in NAD constructions? (ii) What kinds of syntactic phrases may appear as subjects of NAD constructions? And (iii) What are the restrictions in each case?

2.1. Degree predicates

Generally speaking, predicates expressing some form of measurement or comparison, e.g. indicating degrees of difference or similarity, form good NAD constructions. This is true of the following constructions: comparatives, superlatives, equatives, proportionals (see (4)), as well as expressions of excess and sufficiency, such as be too much or be sufficient, which are the ones we focus on in this paper. We have already seen what such NAD constructions look like in (1b) and (2b), characterized syntactically by a seemingly disrupted agreement pattern.

We focus now on the properties and restrictions of the three pieces that make up the predicate of this construction: the copula BE, the degree head and the nominal complement of the degree predicate.

2.1.1. The copula

We begin first by noting that NAD constructions are strictly limited to (i) predicational copular sentences with (ii) degree predicates that express some form of measurement or comparison. Therefore, the examples in (6) are not NAD constructions, since their predicates do not involve any form of measurement or comparison and, furthermore, they only show ordinary agreement patterns.

It is important to remark that the limitations of the non-agreeing variants in (6) to form grammatical NAD constructions are syntactic. For instance, one could imagine that a NAD construction in (6a) could mean that a number of defenders equal to five has the required ability to stop the rival team. Such meanings are perfectly expressible via bona fide NAD constructions, as in (7).

We take it, thus, that NAD constructions require predicates that overtly establish some form of measurement or comparison. In fact, some predicates actually are found to be preferred as NAD constructions in their most common uses. For instance, dimensional nouns that can be predicates directly of units of measurement – such as distance, volume, weight, etc. – yield better results as NAD constructions in spite of their disrupted agreement, in contrast with ordinary agreeing counterparts.Footnote 6 Consider the data in (8) and (9).

It seems clear then that expressing some form of measurement/comparison is necessary, but as it turns out, this is by no means sufficient. Consider measure verbs such as pesar ‘to weigh’, etc. These types of predicates may form interesting semantic pairs with NAD constructions, as illustrated by the pair be enough weight vis-à-vis weigh enough; for instance, if 10 kgs is enough weight (for some purpose), then certainly 10 kgs weighs enough, too. Nevertheless, these types of predicates are ruled out in NAD constructions.

In both (10) and (11), we find the same exact contrasting pattern. The two (a) examples show that full plural agreement with the predicate is ungrammatical. These are the baseline NAD constructions. Instead, the (b) cases involve a verbal predicate modified by the degree predicate of excess demasiado ‘too much’ expressing that its subject exceeds a certain threshold along the dimension determined by the verbal predicate itself. These only admit ordinary subject-verb plural agreement patterns, which we take as evidence that they cannot form NAD constructions. In other words, verbal predicates like pesar ‘to weigh’ and durar ‘to last’ cannot partake in NAD constructions even though its nominal counterpart peso ‘weight’ and tiempo ‘time’ can.Footnote 7

We must be careful, however, when assessing the semantic status of the two grammatical variants of pairs, such as those presented in (10) and (11). Consider for clarity the following minimal pair, formed by the NAD construction in (12a) and the agreeing variant in (12b).

The meaning difference between (12a) and (12b) is ostensible, and thus the two sentences cannot be taken to be semantically analogous. (12a) states that, on a scale of weight, three books, any three books, exceed some contextually determined threshold of weight. (12b) instead states that there are some three books, say b1, b2 and b3 that weigh too much (either individually or jointly). Conceptually, (12a) is a statement about weight, where three-book objects are claimed to exceed a certain weight threshold, whereas (12b) is a statement about the weight of some three books.

2.1.2. The degree head

There is an interesting limitation to note about the requirement to have a degree expression in NAD constructions. Most strikingly, NAD constructions must always be interpreted as modified by a degree expression, either overtly or covertly. Consider (13).

While the examples in (13) without the degree predicate demasiado or suficiente are not ungrammatical, they only accept an interpretation according to which three books / cars count either as an amount of weight (in (13a)) or an amount of money (in (13b)). This type of interpretation is more natural with nouns such as money, which retains its amount interpretation also under expressions of paucity, such as apenas and negation:Footnote 8

What cases such as (13) and (14) cannot mean is that three books have the property of being weight, three cars have the property of being money and three millions have or lack the property of being money. The conclusion is that NAD constructions do not admit a bare counterpart: they must always be interpreted as degree expressions, either because they include an explicit degree expression, or because such degree expressions are covertly understood in the context.

2.1.3. Nominal complement

NAD constructions place virtually no restrictions on the type of nominal that may appear as complement to the degree predicate. Example (2b) above provides already a good array of different nominals (peso ‘weight’, dinero ‘money’, trabajo ‘work’, esfuerzo ‘effort’, lectura ‘reading’). Note that these nominals need not be either abstract or gradable, and thus also include sortal count nouns, such as huerto ‘garden’ or ordenador ‘computer’, as illustrated in (15).

While any nominal may partake in NAD constructions, no non-nominal may. We have already discussed (10b) and (11b) with measure verbs. One could also imagine that adjectives, being the prototypical way to express a gradable property, would be grammatical in such contexts. They are not, however: simply swapping the nominal with an adjective results in ungrammaticality. Consider the minimal contrast in (16).

In fact, any such alternations lead to ungrammaticality. Moreover, with adjectival predicates, subjects must always agree with the copula:

Adjectival predicates like pesado ‘heavy’ and caro ‘expensive’ may form ordinary agreeing predicative structures, such as those in the agreeing variants of (17). Because of this limitation, NAD constructions where the complement to the degree predicate is not explicitly provided (see e.g. (1b) above) are such that only a nominal expression may be recovered, but not an adjective. A reason for this behavior might be that the associated scale of adjectives is conventional by hypothesis, that is, they are lexically fixed to some scale. The associated scale of nominals instead depends on the nominal itself and, in most cases, on the context. For instance, although weight is limited to denote along a single dimension, scales built on top of more abstract dimension names, such as work, effort, trouble, etc., provide different ways to determine what counts as being ‘work’, ‘effort’, etc.

Summing up, the best NAD constructions are formed by predicational copular sentences with some form of degree head, namely, a head that expresses excess or sufficiency, and a nominal complement. NAD constructions may also take a possibly covert nominal as its complement. From a semantic perspective, NAD constructions provide a way to use ordinary nominals as non-conventional units of measurements, that is, units of measurement that are made on the fly without prior agreement as to how their corresponding scale is determined.

2.2. Subjects

When it comes to NADs’ subjects, Quantifier Phrases (QPs) headed by cardinal numerals, either modified or not, make the best and most natural subjects, as illustrated in (18).

In sharp contrast with how naturally such examples are construed, other existential as well as universal quantifiers cannot be subjects of NAD constructions.

As an anonymous reviewer pointed out to us, singular subjects like the indefinite in (20a) and (21a) below give rise to similar interpretations as those conveyed by NAD constructions, but notice that in these examples the number morphology on the copula must be singular. This is independent of the possibility of ascribing (20a) and (21a) a NAD-like interpretation, one whereby a single apple (any one apple) and a single mistake (any one) exceeds the relevant threshold of fruit amount and stir amount. (20b) and (21b) parallel those in (1a) and (2a) with non-canonical agreement with the postverbal Noun Phrase (NP).

If we look at definite determiners, it may appear at first glance that definite descriptions are also ruled out. Determiner Phrases (DPs) headed by either the definite article or other definite demonstratives yield ungrammatical results as subjects of NAD constructions:

Still, there are cases where definite descriptions may form good subjects of NAD constructions. This is especially apparent when the nominal inside the definite description is abstract, typically deverbal, resulting in an eventive denotation of the subject. Example (23a) below shows that conjoined definite DPs must agree with the main predicate of the sentence, as indicated by the ungrammaticality of the singular copula (i.e. (23a) corresponds to a non-predicational identificational copular sentence). The critical example in (23b) shows that with NAD constructions an agreeing copula is not required, conforming thus to the familiar predicational NAD pattern we have seen so far (e.g. (1b) and (2b)).Footnote 9

While highly reminiscent of (22), examples like those in (24) (provided to us by an anonymous reviewer) present interesting contrasts with (23):

On the surface, the main differences between (23b) and (24) are two: a lack of optionality in agreement and an ordinary non-eventive head noun in subject position in the latter. Were (24) grammatical with the singular copula, it would seem to suggest that our characterization of subjects in NAD constructions was incomplete or mistaken: as shown in (22)/(23b), only a reduced number of definite descriptions yield grammatical results, and DPs such as las escaleras in (24) is not one of them. The ungrammaticality of (24) in singular, when compared to (23b), suggests that, in fact, it is syntactically distinct to our NAD constructions. The pattern is, moreover, quite generalized: any type of plural definite phrase may appear as a subject in (24), but not in NAD constructions:

There are also important semantic differences between (24)/(25) and NAD constructions: unlike subjects of NAD constructions, the subjects of (24)/(25) refer to (extensional) individual entities, particular set of stairs.Footnote 10 These differences in agreement and interpretation lead us to believe that NAD constructions, understood as a natural class, exclude cases such as (24), which, in turn, may require a separate treatment from the one we offer in this paper.

In a very similar type of variation on the eventive definite DPs illustrated in (23) above, we find that clauses (both non-finite (26) and finite (27)) may also appear in subject position of NAD constructions. We first show in (26a)/(27a) below that conjoined clauses trigger plural agreement with the copula, whereas in (26b)/(27b), we point out how in the context of NAD constructions, the agreement pattern is reversed. Interestingly, note that conjoined infinitives (26b) and conjoined clauses (27b) do not admit plural copulas, in spite of being subjects of degree predicates. We do not have an explanation for this restriction, but what is critical for us is the possibility of the singular variant, as attested above (see footnote 3, too).

In general, the broader observation is that event-denoting expressions, such as non-finite subjects and propositional-denoting expressions, such as full clauses are good NAD subjects. In addition to these, we can also include deadjectival nominals, as shown below:

There is yet one more type of subject that is allowed with a subset of NAD constructions. These are QPs and DPs introduced by the preposition con ‘with’, which combine with degree predicates whose head is a verb conveying sufficiency, such as bastar, alcanzar, llegar ‘to be enough’, or excess, such as sobrar ‘to exceed’ (see footnote 7). The preposition con may appear modifying numeral QPs, definite DPs and non-finite clauses that otherwise would be ungrammatical. Its most remarkable feature is its ability to rescue two types of statements. First, it may rescue cases where the source of the ungrammaticality lies in the type of subject employed, as in (19) and (21) above, and forces a singular copula.

In addition, the preposition con may also rescue cases where sufficiency is lexically specified in a single verbal head, possibly as the result of spelling out the full degree predicate.Footnote 11

In sum, NAD constructions are but one in a family of constructions characterized by the ‘disruption’ of a canonical agreement pattern, where subject and predicate all share the same phi-feature specifications, a not uncommon property of Spanish copular sentences (see RAE 2009, chapters 33, 37).Footnote 12

2.3. Semantic building blocks

So far, we have limited the discussion to the syntactic components and distribution of the different phrases partaking in NAD constructions. It is nevertheless important to note that the semantic effects observed are homogeneous across all these different manifestations of NAD constructions: the expression of a dimension, a degree and a unit of measurement are always required. Let us illustrate this with (1), repeated for convenience.

We are interested in determining what the meaning of (1b) is and how it differs from its mandatorily agreeing counterpart in (1a). The intuition we pursue is that, while statement (1b) is about books, (1b) is about something else: for a writer who signed a contract, it could be work, commitment, effort; for a pre-schooler who has to carry them, it could be too much weight; for a Barnes and Noble executive, it could be too many to give away; for a struggling worker, it could be too expensive to buy, etc. None of these possible interpretations are available in (1a).

This description provides a good hint as to what the semantic ingredients of NAD constructions might be. For good measure, consider first what the role of ordinary gradable adjectives is in sentences like Jane is too tall. The main predicate tall expresses a relation between an (extensional) individual and a degree along some conventionally determined dimension – height in this case. The modifier too expresses that the degree provided by the adjective exceeds a certain contextually provided threshold. With this in mind, consider now the following case, taken from (13b) above:

Clearly, we do not typically use cars to measure amounts of money, and yet that is precisely what the NAD construction in (13b) expresses: that a cost-unit consisting of three cars exceeds a certain contextually determined threshold. The result is similar to the task performed by ordinary gradable adjectives, albeit one achieved by different means. The semantic ingredients required to capture such an interpretation for (13b) above seem to include three components:

  • The source of a dimension. This is the role of the nominal complement that is mandatory in NAD constructions (either explicitly provided or recovered from the context). In (13b), this is provided by the nominal dinero ‘money’.

  • A degree head like demasiado ‘too much’ and suficiente ‘enough’ (in addition to mucho ‘much’, comparative or superlative morphology, etc.). The role of this head is to introduce some form of comparison between a contextually provided degree, namely, a threshold on the dimension provided by the nominal; and

  • A subject that acts as a unit of measurement, that is, a subject that provides the measure that must be interpreted on the scale built upon the dimension provided by the nominal in predicate position.

From a semantic standpoint, we suggest that the copula BE in predicational sentences denotes the identity function for $ \left\langle e,t\right\rangle $ functions: the function of type $ \left\langle \left\langle e,t\right\rangle, \left\langle e,t\right\rangle \right\rangle $ that maps any $ \left\langle e,t\right\rangle $ function to itself.

The semantic task performed by the subject tres coches in (13b) above is less like the type of relation between individuals and degrees that has been posited for adjectival gradable predicates, and more analogous to numeral QPs with nominals that conventionally (i.e. lexically) denote units of measurement, such as kilo. Of course, different degree heads may contribute different semantic roles or even require different analytic pieces. But the general semantic contribution of the three pieces required to capture the interpretation of NAD constructions prevails across configurations. Thus, the difference between NAD constructions and sentences with standard gradable main predicates (such as adjectives) seems to be that while adjectives denote relations between extensional entities and degrees along a conventionally associated scale, nominal complements of the degree head in NAD constructions simply provide the name of the dimension that the degree head employs to express the threshold it denotes.

In what follows, we will assume this proposed characterization and take for granted that subjects of NAD constructions are semantically interpreted as providing a measuring unit, used to locate a degree on the basis of a scale whose dimension is either retrieved from the context or provided by the nominal in the post-copular position.

3. Baseline Analysis

3.1. NADs as predicational copular sentences

As we have seen in the previous section, one of the most notorious definitory properties of NAD constructions is their limitation to copular environments. Copular sentences have been traditionally divided into predicational (30a) and non-predicational ones, the latter including equative (i.e. identity) (30b), identificational (30c) and specificational sentences (30d).

According to Higgins (Reference Higgins1973), the subject and predicate of these four types of copular sentences are assumed to have different referential properties, which – after Mikkelsen’s (Reference Mikkelsen2005: 130) type-theoretic unification – are reduced to (31).Footnote 13

We submit that NAD constructions fit better the type of predicational copular clauses. This is better seen in comparison to otherwise semantically equivalent variants, such as (32), with a definite description in subject position and predicates such as be too much.

A predicational analysis of NAD constructions involves a referential subject of type $ e $ and a predicate of type $ \left\langle e,t\right\rangle $ , raising the issue as to whether numeral DPs, such as three books, can truly perform such a semantic task. As an anonymous reviewer suggests, this could be indicative of a new type of copular construction in Mikkelsen’s (Reference Mikkelsen2005) classification, one where both constituents are of a predicative $ \left\langle e,t\right\rangle $ type. Nevertheless, we believe that subjects of NADs are indeed referential: their referents are abstract in the same way that the referent of (32) above is abstract. Our own analysis, presented in detail in Section 4, involves lowering the subject to a referential type.Footnote 14 Notice that lowering the predicate to a referential type amounts to saying that expressions such as be too much weight, be the same as two pizzas, etc. are referential, which does not look like a tenable analysis for these cases.

From a syntactic standpoint, assume that in copular sentences, the predication is mediated by the projection of a functional head Pred (Bowers Reference Bowers1993, Svenonius Reference Svenonius1994, Adger & Ramchand Reference Adger and Ramchand2003 and others), as represented in (33).

In the specific case of NAD constructions, the Pred head corresponds to the copular verb BE, which will move to the head of the Functional Phrase responsible for Tense. The predicate XP, which in regular predicational copular sentences may either correspond to nouns, adjectives or prepositions, in the specific case of NAD constructions must be a Degree Phrase containing an NP that introduces a nominal scale (through the mediation of a required Measure Phrase). Finally, the subject of NAD constructions must be a QP with a (modified) cardinal head or (non-extensional) DP (as exemplified in Section 2.2). This means that the predication characteristic of NAD constructions is uniformly represented as in (34).Footnote 15

Note that the question of flexible agreement of NAD constructions is not entirely resolved by the syntactic properties introduced so far. Plural agreement can be claimed to correspond to the pre-copular canonical agreement, after a (plural) QP/DP is raised to Spec,TP: the [i $ \phi $ ] and [EPP] (Extended Projection Principle) features of QP/DP will check the [u $ \phi $ ] and [uEPP] features of T. However, it is unclear how singular agreement could be derived. Bearing in mind that agreement with the NP in post-copular position is not uncommon cross-linguistically in inflectional languages, one might hypothesize that singular agreement corresponds to post-copular non-canonical (inverse) agreement with the NP in complement position. However, there are two main problems with this kind of approach: for this to happen, the NP1 is expected to be defective for phi-features and NP2 is expected to be referential.Footnote 16 Given that none of these conditions apply in NAD constructions, we abandon this approach. In Section 4.1, we consider an alternative, according to which, once the NP1 is nominalized, plural agreement is no longer a requirement; in other words, singular number on the copula is a post-syntactic option after a semantic nominalization operation has occurred at Logical Form (LF).

3.2. The basic semantics of sufficiency and excess

In this section, we focus on the contrast between gradable phenomena expressed by means of adjectives and by means of nominal scales.

3.2.1. Adjectival predicates and degree modifiers

A common way to capture gradable phenomena in natural languages is to assume that certain expressions, such as adjectives, degree modifiers, etc., contain degree arguments that are lexically associated with scales.Footnote 17 Degrees provide a direct way of representing how much of something an object has. For our purposes, we will assume that degrees are primitives, atomic types in the model (of type d).Footnote 18 With degrees, gradable adjectives are typically expressed as relations between individuals and degrees, (35a). The value of the degree argument can also be additionally utilized by degree morphology (such as the comparative morpheme -er, degree modifiers like very, etc.) to impose further restrictions on its interpretation. Bare gradable adjectives, that is, with no such overt degree morphology, are often proposed to combine first with a null degree morpheme POS, for ‘positive form’ (originally introduced by von Stechow Reference von Stechow1984, (35b)):

POS serves a double function: it allows the whole Adjective Phrase to be predicated of an individual, and it relates the degree argument of the adjective to an appropriate contextually supplied standard of comparison.Footnote 19 Such standard of comparison is usually understood as an average, a prototypical value or the norm that is expected on the dimension provided by the gradable predicate.Footnote 20 This is typically computed on the basis of the comparison class identified in the context. Consider a sentence like (36):

If Jane happens to be a third grader, then the comparison class to properly compute the truth conditions of (36) will help determine what is the standard or typical height of third graders, disregarding other individuals. We can thus represent the meaning of (36) as follows:

Excess and sufficiency expressions like too and enough express something slightly different, however: They express that the degree of an individual on some scale is not above or below what is standard or prototypical but some other conventionally determined threshold. Both standards and thresholds are most often underspecified and vague and can thus be questioned, disagreed with, etc. But there are some intuitive differences between them as well. Consider the examples in (38).

These examples, while still vague and underspecified, locate the source of their vagueness on a notion different than the standard of comparison. The statements simply assert that Jane exceeds or does not reach a certain threshold that may, but need not coincide with the standard. That standards and thresholds may be different is supported by contrasts such as those illustrated in (39).

Only the first example yields a contradiction, since Jane cannot be both tall and not tall (not at least without further qualifications). This shows that unmodified positive adjectives rely on fixing a comparison class to be interpretable, since otherwise, they would lack the means to find a suitable standard. But the follow-ups in examples in (39b, c) above do not rely on a comparison class. We must only determine whether Jane exceeds or not the relevant threshold.

Let us assume then that interpreting (39b, c) requires comparing Jane’s degree of tallness to some contextually supported threshold $ {TH}^C $ . Given that we are interested in upper (for too) and lower (for enough) bounds, we determine two context dependent boundaries, $ {TH}_{max}^C $ and $ {TH}_{min}^C $ . We propose the following lexical entries for too and enough (which we take to be identical to demasiado and suficiente in Spanish):Footnote 21

Essentially, too means ‘more (than)’ and enough just means ‘not less (than).’ The difference is that the comparison is not relative to a standard (as with bare adjectives) or some other linguistically determined degree (as with comparatives). Instead, the comparison is done relative to some conventionally (or possibly conversationally) determined threshold.

We can now see how two expressions such as too tall and tall enough are interpreted relative to different threshold degrees: a maximal threshold for too and a minimal threshold for enough. We illustrate this by providing the interpretations of the two sentences in (38) above.

3.2.2. Degree heads and nominal scales

We turn next to the case of nominals modified by degree expressions. Consider again (2a):

Under the assumption that ordinary nominals typically denote (extensional) properties, we face a problem if we try to combine too and enough directly with an ordinary property like books, since the lexical entries provided in the formulas in (40) are tailored to combine with gradable predicates. A usual reaction is to posit some type of phonologically null syntactic structure that nevertheless acts as a semantic glue between the degree predicate and the NP, in this case, by introducing a degree argument and linking it to the nominal predicate.Footnote 22 Following the syntactic structure introduced in (34) above, we will call this projection a Measure Phrase, whose head M takes a nominal argument of a predicative type and returns a gradable predicate, as the formula in (42) expresses.Footnote 23

The semantic task of M is thus to take an ordinary property of individuals, such as the denotation of an ordinary nominal like books, and introduce a degree variable d that can later be used up by other degree predicates and modifiers, such as demasiados and suficientes. The gradable predicate mimics the ordinary meaning of adjectives, with the only difference being that the dimension of measurement is set by the nominal itself, rather than being lexically conventionalized. When applied to some individual, M will produce a set of degrees that represents their corresponding amount along some scale. The determination of the scale and its dimension, although context dependent, is not entirely unconstrained, however. In the case of plural nominals, as is the case with (2a) above, the relevant dimension of the scale is invariably a cardinality one, and the dimension is fixed simply to express a scale of a number of individuals, $ \mid x\mid =n $ (see, e.g. Rett Reference Rett2014, Solt Reference Solt2009, Reference Solt2015, Wellwood Reference Wellwood2019 a.o.).Footnote 24 Composing the meaning of (2a) up to the level of Pred’ looks as follows (where ‘*’ corresponds to the pluralizing operator in Link Reference Link, Bauerle, Schwarze and von Stechow1983).

In order to interpret the numeral QP in subject position, we will adopt the view that numerals express nominal modifiers, as defended at length by Ionin & Matushansky (Reference Ionin and Matushansky2006, Reference Ionin and Matushansky2018) (see also Bylinina & Nouwen Reference Bylinina and Nouwen2020), yielding the following denotation for the full QP.Footnote 25

We now have two predicates, PredP and QP of type $ \left\langle e,t\right\rangle $ that cannot, without further assumptions, combine in the usual way via Function Application. Here, we will simply assume the type-shifting operation A from Partee (Reference Partee1987), that shifts the type of an $ \left\langle e,t\right\rangle $ predicate into a generalized quantifier (type $ \left\langle \left\langle e,t\right\rangle, t\right\rangle $ ), introducing existential quantification on the way.

The resulting composition of (2a), after this lifting operation has applied over the subject, is as follows:

The resulting denotation of (2a) in the formula (46b) expresses that there is a cardinality of three books that exceeds or is close to some contextually determined threshold of book quantities. To be sure, the only available interpretation is one where three books count as too many / enough books; no other interpretation is possible.

The meaning composition of (1a) would parallel the derivation in (46), with the only difference that the nominal complement of the degree head appears to be elided.

Note that the difference with adjectival constructions (see Section 3.2.1) is quite apparent. Adjectives require contextually supplied information at two different levels in order to be successfully interpreted: They require a comparison class and a standard of comparison. For example, in order to interpret Jane is tall in (36), we first noted that the standard (average) of tallness varies depending on whether our comparison class is comprised of, for example, NBA players or 10-year-old children. Nominals in constructions like (1a) and (2a) do not show the same dependency on comparison classes. There is no relevant subset of books to be detected nor standards of comparison. There is again no notion of what counts as an ‘average’ number of books. Instead, the interpretations of (1a) and (2a) rely crucially on the notion of threshold, but this is not associated with the nominal itself but with the degree predicates too/enough.

While this difference between nominal and adjectival predicates might seem too obvious to mention, a caveat is in order here. The dimension of the nominal scale is set by the joint action of the context and information provided by the nominal. In the case of plural count nouns, the associated scales invariably range over quantities of things, that is, the corresponding dimension is always set to express cardinalities, and thus fixing such scales does not require much contextual support. This is so because on a scale of book quantities, three books rank higher than two books, which rank higher than one book, and so on, and little to no context manipulation will be able to alter those facts.

4. Semantic Composition of NAD Constructions

4.1. A general theory of NAD constructions

Consider (2b) as a working case.

In NAD constructions, complement nominals, such as weight, work, etc., are used to establish a dimension of measurement, with the help of context. Take for instance the case of money in (2b). What makes three book entities count as too much or enough money? We have well established units of measurement for scales along the dimension of cost/money (say dollars or euros), but clearly (2b) is not deploying those units of measurement. Instead, the role of money is to determine some aspect of cost, of which three books can be meaningfully said to determine one such unit of measurement. While this is relatively apparent in the case of money, things get more underspecified with other types of (typically abstract) nouns, such as work or effort, or even sortal count nouns, such as huerto ‘garden’ or ordenador ‘computer’ (see (15)). In what sense do we mean that three books counts as d-much / d-enough on a scale build upon the dimension of ‘work’? There is no single answer to this question, and different contexts will support different interpretations. For the proofreader, it will mean that three books exceed some threshold of proofreading work (or are sufficient with respect to it), for the author, the dimension will be set according to a dimension of amount of work in terms of book writing, and so on. In a way, any sense that falls within the denotational space of a nominal and can be meaningfully said to be part of its conceptual space might be exploited in order to build an ad hoc dimension.Footnote 26 And this is, we argue, precisely the main raison d’être of NAD constructions: to provide the means of constructing scales built upon ad hoc dimensions. In the next paragraphs, we explain how to capture the semantic properties of NAD constructions with our current assumptions.

In examples such as (2b), the semantic role of the two nominals is always the same: N1 (the subject) is interpreted as some unit of measurement that is located along a scale built upon the dimension provided by N2. At the end of the day, the only limitations to the pair of nominals we find in NAD constructions have to do with notional or conceptual considerations about what makes sense to be predicated of what: while it may be sensible to use physical books to measure weight (or even time, by considering the time it takes to read a book), it may not be so natural to use books to measure viscosity, electric charge and so on; however, whether this is possible or not, it is ultimately only determined by context.

With these considerations in mind, composing the meaning of (2b) for a complement noun such as peso ‘weight’ up to the level of Pred’ looks as follows:

The meanings in (48) are fully parallel to those in (43): the nominal weight, although interpreted as a predicate of individuals in (48a), provides the dimension to build a measure of entities on a contextually determined scale in (48b) and (48c). Now, recall that a sentence such as (49a), to which we assign the structure in (49b) would not be appropriately represented by means of the logical form in (49c).

Interpretations like (49c) miss a general point, since (49a) is not a statement about books: It is a statement about weight, using books as weight units; in other words, books are the entities whose weight can be measured on a scale of weight. This is, in full, parallel to statements such as Three kilos is too much weight: it is not a statement about (any particular) kilos, it is a statement about weight. The formula in (49c) fails to capture this fundamental property of NAD constructions. Note also that the NAD construction in (49a) has the inference that there are sets of three books, not any three particular books whose weight exceeds (or is sufficient for) a certain threshold; in other words, to properly capture the truth-conditions of a NAD statement, we must avoid a requirement that a quantificational statement should have witnesses. The statement in (49a) might be true even if it is not possible to find values to the variable bound by three books, such that these values are books and are too heavy or heavy enough. This observation is crucial to rule out other types of valency shifting operations on the subject. The formula in (49c) shows that this is the case for type lifters such as A, as defined in (45), which do not avoid such unwelcome existential entailments. But so do a number of type-shifting operations that nominalize the subject from a property type to an individual type (i.e. shifts from $ \left\langle e,t\right\rangle $ to $ e $ ). We provide three common possible alternatives below: Choice Functions (Reinhart Reference Reinhart1997, Winter Reference Winter1997), the iota definite description operator (Sharvy Reference Sharvy1980, Link Reference Link, Bauerle, Schwarze and von Stechow1983) and the epsilon indefinite description operator (Hilbert Reference Hilbert1922, Bierwisch Reference Bierwisch, Bierwisch and Lang1989, von Heusinger Reference von Heusinger1997):

As the paraphrases above indicate, none of these alternatives will do: (50a) conveys something too strong, it commits us to a way of choosing a three book individual that equals or exceeds the relevant threshold, which is not the intended meaning. (50b) fails because it requires finding the unique maximal individual consisting of three books, which need not exist. (50c) is weaker than (50b) in that it does not presuppose any uniqueness, but all the same, it commits us to the existence of one three book individual or other that is then said to equal or exceed the relevant threshold. In short, neither of the alternatives in the formulas in (50) account for the fact that three books is not interpreted as referring, predicating or quantifying over ordinary individuals.

Our solution to this problem involves treating the subject of NAD constructions non-extensionally. The idea is simple: Subjects of NAD constructions denote entity correlates of properties, interpreted via a nominalized function (à la Chierchia Reference Chierchia1984, McNally Reference McNally1997). Consider the definition in (51).

What is crucial about this proposal is that subjects of NAD constructions do not denote or quantify over ordinary token entities. Rather, they denote or quantify over something more abstract, some form of higher order entity, which McNally (Reference McNally1997) modeled formally as a nominalized function (or entity correlate of a property) as expressed in (51), drawing from Chierchia & Turner’s (Reference Chierchia and Turner1988) property theoretic semantics. The main motivation for Chierchia (Reference Chierchia1984) and Chierchia & Turner (Reference Chierchia and Turner1988) to introduce entity correlates in the theory was that we can ascribe properties to other properties, as in fun is fun and goodness is good. They capture this by turning properties-as-functions (which correspond to their predicative uses) into their entity correlates (which correspond to their uses as arguments), thereby ‘nominalizing’ them.Footnote 27

An entity correlate is a sort of abstract individual, the reification of the property it is a correlate of. It is thus sortally different from Carlson’s (Reference Carlson1977) object-level entities (sometimes also referred to as tokens). Entity correlates are also similar but ultimately different from the notion of ‘trope’ in that entity correlates are not particularized properties: tropes are particular manifestations of properties in individuals, and thus they serve as natural referents of nominalizations such as Jane’s height, Socrates’ wisdom, etc. (Moltmann Reference Moltmann2004, Reference Moltmann2009). Entity correlates are not specific in the same way, as they do not invoke any one particular manifestation of a property itself but resemble instead an ideal of such property.

In this respect, our conception of an entity correlate resembles somewhat that of a kind (Carlson Reference Carlson1977), an analogy heightened by the similarity between our nominalizing function ‘ $ {}^{\downarrow } $ ’ and Chierchia’s (Reference Chierchia1998) popular rendition of the kind forming operation, ‘ $ {}^{\cap } $ ’. Nevertheless, we believe there are empirical as well as formal reasons to avoid treating subjects of NAD constructions as kinds, derived via the operator ‘ $ {}^{\cap } $ ’. Most notably, when QPs of the form ‘Numeral NP’ are interpreted as denoting kinds in Spanish, only a sub-kind interpretation is available (Borik & Espinal Reference Borik and Espinal2015): in (53), the numeral quantifies over whale-subkinds.

If subjects of NADs were interpreted as kinds, we would expect them to quantify over sub-kinds of the noun they modify, just like in (53) above. This is not so, however: NADs like (1b) and (2b) do not convey that there are three kinds of books exceeding a certain threshold of weight, nor do they mean that there are three kinds of books whose instances exceed such and such threshold. All else being equal, it does not seem right to subsume the referents of NADs’ subjects under kind interpretations.

Our alternative nominalizer ‘ $ {}^{\downarrow } $ ’ does not commit us to kinds, since entity correlates may but need not be kinds. Entity correlates are formal objects, abstractions of properties, bringing in no a priori ontological commitment. As long as we are able to find (or make up on the fly) a referent for them, they shall not fail to refer (they are, in this sense, not very different from situations, degrees, and other abstract objects typically employed in semantic analysis). In this respect, we take kinds to be a proper subclass of entity correlates of properties, and this is the difference that the distinction between our ‘ $ {}^{\downarrow } $ ’ and ‘ $ {}^{\cap } $ ’ (as discussed in Chierchia Reference Chierchia1998) is intended to capture.Footnote 28

With all this in mind, we return to the interpretation of (2b) by means of our nominalizing operator ‘ $ {}^{\downarrow } $ ’, represented in (54) below:

Feeding an entity correlate to the degree predicate, we obtain a statement about weight, not about books and, moreover, we avoid making incorrect existential claims about books. The denotation of the representation in (54b) then amounts to saying that the weight of the entity correlate of the property of being three books is at least as great as some contextually determined weight threshold. In other words, we use books as units of a measure of weight, as desired.

How exactly does an entity correlate then turn into a unit of weight? Ordinary nouns such as books cannot ordinarily be used as units of weight measurements; for instance, one cannot typically say that they bought three books of vegetables, meaning that they bought vegetables weighing as much as three books. We suspect that part of the reason for this behavior (and the reason why conventionalized units of measurement are helpful in general) is because books are not uniform objects with respect to dimensions such as weight, length, etc., as not all books weigh the same. Nevertheless, by obtaining the entity correlate of the property of being three books, we are indeed referencing an abstract object that is nonetheless uniform: uniform with respect to quantity, as the property that leads to the nominalization is comprised of three-book individuals only (Scontras 2017). We suspect, however, that such entity correlates are not just uniform with respect to quantity but with respect to other dimensions of which they may sensibly be predicated. Thus, being an idealization, the entity correlate of three books will, in addition to being uniform with respect to a quantity, involve a uniform weight, length, etc. but also a uniform amount of work, money, effort, etc. In this uniformity resides their ability to serve as units of measurement.

Extending this analysis to NAD constructions with null nominal complements (see (1b)) is straightforward. Assume first a contextually determined phonologically null nominal predicate DIM $ {}^C $ , complement to the head M.

The reasons for positing a null nominal here as well are mainly two: (i) as we have discussed in previous sections, only nominals are allowed in degree predicates of NAD constructions; and (ii) semantically, we need a nominal that provides the name of the relevant dimension and that can be measured. We write DIM C to remind us of this dimension-setting role of the nominal. When combined with M, the whole Measure Phrase denotes a relation between degrees and individuals, but one where the dimension is not set conventionally (lexically) but instead compositionally, by combining together M and its nominal complement.

Consider once again (2b) with a singular copula:

The way we account for it is as follows: (i) the postulated nominalization operation applies to Spec,PredP; (ii) this semantic operation gives as output an abstract entity, which makes it possible that (iii) at Spell-Out, a default third-person singular be instantiated on the copula. The relevance of this analysis is that an LF operation appears to be relevant at the time of the mapping from the structural representation of meaning to exponence.Footnote 29

To sum up, in this section, we have argued what the derivation of NAD constructions is, with overt as well as covert nominals in complement position of the degree head. We have shown that the meaning of NAD constructions is heavily underspecified, and without further contextual aids, there is no telling what the relevant scale is. This is so because, referring once more to our (1b) and (2b) examples, any aspect of being a book, or any possible relation to being a book that may be brought by invoking the name book can be retrieved to and utilized as the relevant dimension to fix a measuring scale. It could be that any unit of a number of books is too heavy, or too expensive or too much to keep up with, etc. This interpretation is, in turn, completely devoid of any commitment to the existence of three books, and, in fact, any plurality of three books would be taken to exceed (or be sufficient with respect to) the set threshold. These are fundamentally evaluative scales that rely on the multiple senses that are attributed to the interpretation of lexical nominals.

4.2. General assessment

We now have an analysis of NAD constructions that has been developed on the basis of numeral subjects. NAD constructions, however, come in different shapes, and it remains to be seen how our proposed analysis extends to accommodate the rest of cases explored in Section 2, as well as the observed limitations.

Looking at subjects, we observe that, from an analytical point of view, the only well-forming requirement our analysis requires is that the subject must be nominalized. Our analysis imposes this restriction on the grounds that subjects must be referential, but intensionalized entities, interpreted as entity correlates of properties in a predicative copular construction, where they simply provide the argument the degree predicate is seeking. Consequently, we expect expressions for which nominalizing operations are readily available to form good NAD constructions and, conversely, we expect other types of expressions for which nominalization is not an option to yield ungrammatical results.

We begin discussing the case of subjects that are ruled in by our analysis. We have now seen how unmodified numeral constructions are easily treated as we suggest, but the account extends seamlessly to cases of modified numeral constructions as well, which can also be constructed as properties. From a semantic standpoint, this is unsurprising: While numerals establish an equality relation to the cardinality of an object (e.g. $ \left\{x:\hskip0.35em |x|=4\right\} $ ), modified numerals simply vary in terms of the type of relation they express (e.g. more than four expresses the property $ \left\{x:\hskip0.35em |x|>4\right\} $ , etc.). Moreover, the fact that like unmodified numerals, modified numerals may appear in positions admitting only properties confirms this point:

Interestingly, this view also correctly sanctions the fact that, while más de la mitad ‘more than half’ is a good NAD subject la mayoría de ‘most / the majority of’ is not: While the former can be construed again as a relation between a number and the cardinality of an object, the latter is a definite description and thus imposes more stringent conditions on its denotational space and its ability to be modified by further semantic operations.

So what kind of definite descriptions are then ruled in versus out of NAD constructions by our account? First, definite descriptions headed by ordinary extensional object denoting NPs (including demonstratives and possessives) are correctly ruled out. These are typically extensional objects that refer to actual objects in the world and impose, in addition, certain requirements on the domain (such as presupposing the existence and uniqueness of their referents). We have argued extensively that NAD constructions require, instead, intensional individual objects, ideals of properties that do not have to be realized in the actual world and place no additional constraints in the context. Ordinary definite descriptions have actual referents, and thus do not fit the bill (see discussion around (22) through (25) above).

There is, nevertheless, a natural class of definite descriptions that yield grammatical results as subjects of NAD constructions. These are definite descriptions headed by event-denoting (deverbal; (23)) or dimension-denoting (deadjectival; (28)) noun phrases. That deadjectival subjects perform well is perhaps unsurprising, given that they typically constitute the same type of nominals that may appear as complements to the degree expression, such as height, weight, etc. Event-denoting deverbal nouns instead are closer to non-finite subjects, which have long been argued to have nominalized interpretations (as first discussed by Chierchia Reference Chierchia1984). Our analysis extends seamlessly to such constructions, and, in addition, correctly captures the truth-conditional equivalence between the two types of subjects – when such minimal pairs exist. Notice that speakers allow ‘overtly’ nominalizing non-finite clauses with the definite determiner.

Similar observations can be made of clausal subjects as well (see (26b)/(27b) above). Summing up, our analysis accounts for (i) clausal subjects, both finite and non-finite, either with an overt definite determiner or without; (ii) nominalizations morphologically derived from adjectives and verbs and (iii) numeral NPs of various kinds (by our own hypothesis). Note, additionally, that nothing in our account rules out, in principle, singular subjects as long as they conform to any of the cases in (i) through (iii) – although in these cases, plural copulas are ruled out, as there is no single target for a goal seeking to check a plural feature; this is exemplified in (20a)/(21a) above.

Lastly, we focus on the case of subjects that our analysis rules out. Chief among these are quantified phrases, such as todo ‘all’, cada ‘each’, algunos ‘some’, varios ‘some’, etc. (see examples in (19) above) in subject position. These expressions quantify over instances of objects and do not have sensible interpretations of type $ e $ (Partee Reference Partee1987). In addition, our nominalizing function only applies to predicates (type $ \left\langle e,t\right\rangle $ ), but quantificational expressions also lack sensible interpretations as predicates, as explicitly shown by the examples in (58).

This means that, as a consequence, our nominalizing operation would not be able to apply to such quantificational expressions when they appear in subject position of NAD constructions, even if we were to assume a prior shift from a generalized quantifier type to a predicative type ( $ \left\langle \left\langle e,t\right\rangle, t\right\rangle $ to $ \left\langle e,t\right\rangle $ ).

Notice, too, that nothing in our analysis precludes singular NPs from appearing in subject position, although they do not conform to the narrow criteria we provided for NAD constructions – since they do not allow singular-plural alternations on the copula. Our semantic analysis, however, extends all the same to such constructions: nothing in the semantics of the nominalizing function precludes applying to, e.g. una manzana ‘one apple’ and un fallo ‘one mistake,’ with the numeral one (see (20a) and (21a)).

Our account most straightforwardly sanctions the class of expressions that may appear in subject position of NAD constructions, but as we saw in Section 2.1, there are certain limitations that affect the class of predicates that are allowed in NADs. Concretely, neither adjectives (e.g. heavy) nor verbs expressing some form of measurement (e.g. weigh) may form NAD constructions. Our account is rather agnostic as to why this is the case, and thus compatible with a number of analytical possibilities.

For one, we suspect that the reason why adjectives may not form good NADs is related to the fact that they perform fundamentally different semantic tasks. Adjectives being relations between (extensional) individuals and degrees, they are not easily predicated of other types of expressions. For instance, the most natural way to express that three kilos is an amount of weight exceeding some threshold is through a NAD construction:

Thus, even nominals expressing units of measurement along the scale conventionalized by a given adjective may not be subjects of said adjective.

Verbal non-copular verbs seem to be limited in a different fashion. As an anonymous reviewer suggests, it seems that verbs expressing measurement heavily rely on fixed units of measurements, and they may take as arguments no nominals other than those expressing such conventionalized units.

Overall, we believe that our analysis provides an accurate descriptive and explanatory analysis of a construction that has been unnoticed in the literature on Spanish, one which raises interesting theoretical challenges for the theory of grammar: the possibility that degree predicates introduce a non-conventional nominal scale, the possibility that subjects be interpreted as non-conventional units of measurement and the possibility that a singular number on the copula verb be a post-syntactic option after a semantic operation of nominalization has applied at LF. Our analysis also offers promising venues to fully understand the limitations we find in the distribution of predicates, but we leave for future research aspectual restrictions as those mentioned in footnote 10.

5. Conclusion

This paper presents an analysis of a construction with a unique number disrupt pattern, which we dubbed Non-Agreeing Degree constructions. These constructions involve (i) an overt degree predicate, such as demasiado ‘too’, suficiente ‘enough’, a comparative, a superlative, a proportional, mucho ‘much’, etc., in a predicational copular sentence; (ii) a nominal complement of the degree head that provides the relevant dimension for the scale that the degree predicate acts on; (iii) a nominalized property in subject position, denoting the entity correlate of such property and acting semantically as a unit of measurement on the scale determined by the nominal and (iv) a copula that can take a default singular morphophonological form at the time of allomorph selection (or lexical insertion).

In a sense, NAD constructions are the means offered by natural languages to use ad hoc units of measurements on scales that have heavily underspecified dimensions, in the sense that any property that can meaningfully be related to the nominal in the Measure Phrase may act as a proper dimension for that nominal.

The main feature of our proposed analysis is that NAD constructions involve predicational copular clauses where the lack of agreement pattern of the copular verb reflects the outcome of a semantic process. This semantic process is better detected where the result involves non-canonical agreement patterns, as in cases with plural subjects (e.g. (1b)/(2b)). This is not to say, however, that there cannot be singular NAD constructions, it only means that agreement will remain unaffected in such cases (as in (20a) and (21a)). It also means that, all else being equal, there may be NAD constructions where no covert semantic process is involved because the denotation of the subjects is of the right sort, as with deadjectival and deverbal nominalizations. And, in fact, there may be other means, possibly language specific, that contribute to NAD construction interpretations, as we discussed around the examples in (29).

Generally speaking, we typically measure weight with kilos and not with books: deploying dedicated conventional units of measurement such as kilos is the ordinary mechanism present in natural languages to determine how much we have of something. The main take-away of this paper is that natural languages allow additionally for constructions of measurement that do not rely on conventional units of measurement. In fact, the cases of NAD constructions discussed here are relevant not only for constructions of measurement but also as an investigation of the different ways in which natural languages may build scales that do not rely on conventionally determined, lexically based scales, as is the case with adjectives. In the analysis of NAD constructions discussed in this paper, scales are built by simply mentioning (or else by contextually recovering) the name of a dimension, and then using an abstract object, an intensionalized entity, as a unit of measurement on that scale. The result is not only semantically sound and conceptually unproblematic but also expressible in a variety of natural languages through NAD constructions, as we argued for and illustrated on the basis of Spanish examples.

Acknowledgments

Jon Ander Mendia is currently affiliated with the University of the Basque Country UPV/EHU & IKERBASQUE, Basque Foundation for Science, 48940 Leioa, Biscay, Spain. We thank the audiences at InSemantic2022, Sinn und Bedeutung 2023 and NELS53 for helpful discussion on the topics presented in this paper. We thank also the three reviewers of the Journal of Linguistics for their detailed and helpful comments. We also acknowledge financial support from the following institutions: Spanish Ministerio de Ciencia e Innovación (PID2020-112801GB-I00), Generalitat de Catalunya (2021SGR787) and AGAUR (BP2020-00121).

Footnotes

1 All examples are given in present tense, but the claims and arguments we discuss are independent of this choice.

2 The nominal complement of the degree head may also be a hyperonym of the noun in subject position.

3 As the question marks in examples (4a, b, d) indicate, the status of the singular and plural variants of NAD constructions is not the same. While singular variants are unequivocally good, for reasons unknown to us, plural variants do not show such a wider range of acceptability. Thus, although we will continue to provide both variants, our main goal is to provide a general account of NAD constructions as exemplified by the singular copula, hoping that future research will clarify the differences between the two variants.

4 The semantics of mucho ‘much’ presents some particular complications that we will largely ignore here. Most notably, statements with mucho (and many/much in English) are subject to systematic ambiguities between so-called absolute and proportional interpretations, and even a ‘reverse proportional’ interpretation according to some authors. For recent discussions (see Dobrovie-Sorin & Giurgea Reference Dobrovie-Sorin, Giurgea and Filip2021 and Romero Reference Romero2021).

5 NAD constructions could also be conceived as instances of lexical polysemy, whereby nouns contribute two main senses to the truth-conditions of the sentence: an ‘individual’ sense and a ‘degree’ sense (see e.g. Rett Reference Rett2014, Reference Rett2018; cf. Brasoveanu Reference Brasoveanu, Schardl, Walkow and Abdurrahman2009). We suggest to depart from such accounts on the grounds that (i) polysemous terms do not typically have additional effects on other types of grammatical processes (such as agreement), (ii) because they do not lend themselves easily to cases of co-predication (a hallmark of polysemous predicates; see discussion in Rett Reference Rett2018), (iii) polysemy-based analyses would suffer from over-predictive power, as the distribution of NAD constructions is heavily restricted to certain syntactic environments, even when semantically equivalent constructions are, in principle, available and (iv) because if we were to invoke polysemy, we would be missing a generalization, namely, that NAD constructions constitute essentially measuring constructions with subjects acting as units of measurement. To be clear, we are not claiming that nominals may not be polysemous and denote more than one sense (one of which may itself be represented as a degree), only that we believe the source of NAD constructions is not to be found there.

6 Notice that in cases where the measure nominal (e.g. peso ‘weight’) has a dual life as the head of a measure phrase (i) and as a sortal noun (ii), the resulting sentence with plural agreement is not ungrammatical, but its truth-conditions are different from its NAD counterpart.

7 The only possible counterexamples to this generalization that we could consider involve a few verbal predicates expressing sufficiency (like bastar, alcanzar, llegar ‘to be enough’) and excess (like sobrar ‘to be too much’).

We found more cross-speaker variation with these than with other NAD constructions, so we will not discuss them further in this paper. What seems to be interesting, at any rate, is that there seem to be some ill-understood differences across these types of verbal predicates.

8 We thank an anonymous reviewer for pointing this out to us.

9 A reviewer pointed out that, according to Real Academia Española (RAE) (2009:2568), the possibility of a singular copula in (23b) may be due to the fact that the speaker conceives the reading and the presentation of the book as just one entity. We do not think this is the case, since in (23a) they are identified as being two different things/events. Rather, (23a) is a non-predicational identificational copular sentence, while (23b) is a predicational NAD construction.

10 Moreover, unlike NAD constructions, examples like in (24)/(25) do not seem to be possible in episodic contexts. Consider the contrast in (i):

We leave this issue for future study.

11 A possible reason for the ubiquity of con headed subjects of NAD constructions could be due to verbal elision of an infinitive. For this reason, we will leave these cases out of our main focus (see Mendia & Espinal Reference Mendia, Espinal, Lam and Ozaki2023 for details on the rescuing capacity of con).

12 Notice that number is not the only disrupted feature in the grammar of Spanish. See Höhn (Reference Höhn2016) for person mismatches in so-called unagreement constructions of the sort illustrated below.

13 The original classification in Higgins (Reference Higgins1973) with four types of copular sentences in (30) looks like (i):

14 Alternatively, as a reviewer has pointed out to us, one might claim that the subjects of NAD constructions are quantificational with the proviso that not all quantificational statements must have witnesses to be true. This would lead to lifting the subject to a quantificational type $ \left\langle \left\langle e,t\right\rangle, t\right\rangle $ . For the time being, we leave this alternative aside, and in Section 4, we only present a compositional analysis of NAD constructions according to which subjects of NADs are nominalized at the level of Predication Phrase (before they are moved to Specifier of TP; see the structure in (34)). On recent studies on witness-based quantification see, among others, von Fintel & Keenan (Reference von Fintel and Keenan2018) and Cooper (Reference Cooper2023).

15 See also Moro (Reference Moro1997) for a raising syntactic analysis of existential copular sentences, according to which the complement of be is a Small Clause with two constituents, one of which is involved in a raising operation. This type of analysis would require a lot of accommodation to be able to account for our NAD constructions (in which the complement of be is a DegP) and, in particular, for the contrast between (1a, b) and (2a, b). We, therefore, leave aside this type of analysis.

16 This phenomenon has been previously discussed by Moro (Reference Moro1997) for Italian, Heggie (Reference Heggie1988) for French and English, den Dikken (Reference den Dikken, Alexiadou and Wilder1998) and Heycock (Reference Heycock2012) for Germanic languages, Costa (Reference Costa, Castro, Ferreira, Hacquard and Salanova2004) for Portuguese and Alsina & Vigo (Reference Alsina, Vigo, Butt and King2014) for Catalan. These analyses mostly rely on movement of both NP1 and NP2, or only of NP1 to a pre-copular position. See also Béjar & Kahnemuyipour (Reference Béjar and Kahnemuyipour2017) for an alternative account to NP2 agreement that dissociates it from the syntax of inversion.

17 For early uses of degree semantics applied to gradable predicates, see Seuren (Reference Seuren, Kiefer and Ruwet1973), Cresswell (Reference Cresswell and Partee1976), Klein (Reference Klein1980, Reference Klein, von Stechow and Wunderlich1991), von Stechow (Reference von Stechow1984), Heim (Reference Heim1985), Bierwisch (Reference Bierwisch, Bierwisch and Lang1989), among others. See Morzycki (Reference Morzycki2016) for a gentle introduction to modification and degree semantics.

18 Degrees come very handy in order to construct scales, tuples $ \left\langle {D}_{\varDelta i},{\ge}_{\varDelta i}\right\rangle $ including a set of degrees $ {D}_{\varDelta i} $ along some dimension $ \varDelta $ and an ordering relation $ {\ge}_{\varDelta i} $ . The ordering $ \ge $ is non-strict, and thus it is also transitive, antisymmetric and reflexive. A scale is then defined as a set of degrees with ordering relation $ \ge $ that is linear and dense.

19 We represent this context dependency by introducing a parameter $ C $ on the interpretation function with the superscript $ C $ , as in ⟦.⟧ C. We follow the tradition of writing ‘ $ {ST}^C\left( tal{l}^{\prime}\right) $ ’ to express that the standard degree is set to the dimension conventionally associated to the gradable predicate.

20 The reasons to adopt POS have to do with compositional transparency and the fact that in some languages positive forms are morphologically marked (e.g. Mandarin; see Sybesma Reference Sybesma1999).

21 We ignore, here, the question of whether expressions of excess and sufficiency lexically convey a modal component, as well as the fact that they optionally take clausal complements. For a recent discussion, see Grano (Reference Grano2022).

22 The idea that a covert operand mediates between NPs and degree predicates of various sorts has a long tradition, going back at least to the null functional nouns NUMBER and AMOUNT in Kayne (Reference Kayne2005). In a similar fashion, Schwarzschild (Reference Schwarzschild2006) poses a syntactic null head Mon (which stands for ‘monotonicity’) connecting quantity words to nominal expressions by introducing a dimension of measurement.

23 This is not the only possibility. Another common strategy is to simply provide (at least) some nominals with a degree argument of their own, such that the meaning of some noun N would mimic that of gradable predicates: ⟦N⟧ = $ \lambda d.\lambda x.N(x)=d $ (see, e.g. Morzycki Reference Morzycki2009). As a reviewer pointed out to us, this seems to be the case with certain nominals, as in Three books is a chore to read. Yet another option would be to have M denote an ordinary relation between individuals and degrees and adopt a new rule of composition that allows to combine the two directly (such as, e.g. Degree Argument Introduction in Solt Reference Solt2015, modeled following Variable Identification in Kratzer Reference Kratzer, Rooryck and Zaring1996).

24 Many languages realize this division morpho-phonologically: while many in English only applies to plural (countable) entities and expresses numerosity or cardinality, much applies to mass (uncountable) entities and expresses an amount of some substance (as in much wine) or even an abstract concept (as in much love). We believe that this follows from independent restrictions imposed by PL. Notice that the key contrast is not between PL nouns versus abstract nouns but between morphologically PL and morphologically SG nouns. PL morphology requires counting, which, in turn, requires having access to the atoms in the extension of the noun (see, e.g. Scontras Reference Scontras2022 for a recent exposition). This difference tracks many morphological phenomena across languages, such as the choice of much/many in English, the use of tantos versus tanto in Spanish, among many others.

25 The full definition is slightly more complicated, as it requires a means of counting where, for some numeral $ n $ , all and only $ n $ -many individuals are counted. For recent discussion, see Champollion (Reference Champollion2017), Rothstein (Reference Rothstein2017) and Ionin & Matushansky (Reference Ionin and Matushansky2018), among others.

26 Another way to state this is that any quale in the denotational space of the nominal may be picked up to provide the relevant dimension. If writing is a quale of book, we may use the latter to determine a unit of measurement of the former: Three books is too much writing. See Pustejovsky (Reference Pustejovsky1995) and much subsequent work for the formalization of qualia information in the lexicon.

27 McNally (Reference McNally1997) further proposed that any NP with a predicative use (as demonstrated by their ability to appear as the pivots in existential sentences and in predicative positions of copular sentences) could be interpreted as a nominalized function. McNally treated numerals very close to the way we do, as introducing cardinality restrictions on the denotation of NPs (but she did so by appealing to their instantiated discourse references).

28 For more discussion on this point, see McNally (Reference McNally1997, Reference McNally, Giannakidou and Rathert2009).

29 See Bobaljik & Wurmbrand (Reference Bobaljik and Wurmbrand2012) for the view that LF (broadly conceived) is calculated first and determines PF. See also Cyrino & Espinal (Reference Cyrino and Espinal2015, Reference Cyrino and Espinal2020) for arguments in support of the hypothesis that agreement in Romance must not be necessarily considered a phenomenon of narrow syntax and that post-syntactic agreement is also relevant in this group of languages.

References

Adger, David & Ramchand, Gillian. 2003. Predication and equation. Linguistic Inquiry. 34(3). 325359.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alsina, Álex & Vigo, Eugenio M.. 2014. Copular inversion and non-subject agreement. In Butt, Miriam & King, Tracy Holloway (eds.), Proceedings of the LFG14 Conference, 525. Stanford CSLI Publications.Google Scholar
Béjar, Susana & Kahnemuyipour, Arsalan. 2017. Non-canonical agreement in copular sentences. Journal of Linguistics. 53. 463499.Google Scholar
Bierwisch, Manfred. 1989. The semantics of gradation. In Bierwisch, Manfred & Lang, Ewald (eds.), Dimensional adjectives: Grammatical structure and conceptual interpretation, 71261. Berlin: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bobaljik, Jonathan D. & Wurmbrand, Susi. 2012. Word order and scope: Transparent interfaces and the 3/4 signature. Linguistic Inquiry. 43(3). 371421.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Borik, Olga & Espinal, M.Teresa. 2015. Reference to kinds and to other generic expressions in Spanish: Definitveness and number. The Linguistic Review. 32(2). 217275.Google Scholar
Bowers, John. 1993. The syntax of predication. Linguistic Inquiry. 24(4). 591656.Google Scholar
Brasoveanu, Adrian. 2009. Measure noun polysemy and monotonicity: Evidence from Romanian pseudopartitives. In Schardl, A., Walkow, M. & Abdurrahman, M. (eds.), Proceedings of NELS 38, 139150. Amherst, MA: GSLA Publications.Google Scholar
Bylinina, Lisa & Nouwen, Rick. 2020. Numeral semantics. Language and Linguistics Compass. 14. e12390. doi:https://doi.org/10.1111/lnc3.12390.Google Scholar
Carlson, Gregory. 1977. Reference to kinds in English. Amherst, MA: University of Massachusetts at Amherst dissertation.Google Scholar
Champollion, Lucas. 2017. Parts of a whole. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chierchia, Gennaro. 1984. Topics in the syntax and semantics of infinitives and gerunds. Amherst, MA: University of Massachusetts, Amherst dissertation.Google Scholar
Chierchia, Gennaro. 1998. Reference to kinds across languages. Natural Language Semantics. 6(4). 339405.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chierchia, Gennaro & Turner, Raymond. 1988. Semantics and property theory. Linguistics and Philosophy. 11. 261302.Google Scholar
Chomsky, Noam. 2000. Minimalist inquiries: The framework. In Martin, Roger, Michaels, David & Uriagereka, Juan (eds.), Step by step: Essays on minimalist syntax in honor of Howard Lasnik, 89156. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Chomsky, Noam. 2001. Derivation by phase. In Kenstowicz, Michael (ed.), Hale, Ken: A life in linguistics, 152. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Cooper, Robin. 2023. Witness-based quantification. In From perception to communication: A theory of types for action and meaning, 296349. Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/oso/9780192871312.003.0008.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Costa, João. 2004. Subjects in Spec,vP: Locality and Agree. In Castro, Ana, Ferreira, Marcelo, Hacquard, Valentine & Salanova, Andrés P. (eds.), Romance, op. 47: Collected papers on Romance syntax, vol. 47 MIT Working Papers in Linguistics, 115. Cambridge, MA: MIT.Google Scholar
Cresswell, Max J. 1976. The semantics of degree. In Partee, Barbara H. (ed.), Montague grammar, 261292. New York: Academic Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cyrino, Sonia & Espinal, M.Teresa. 2015. Bare nominals in Brazilian Portuguese: More on the DP/NP analysis. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory. 33. 471521.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cyrino, Sonia & Espinal, M.Teresa. 2020. On the syntax of Number in Romance. Studia Linguistica. 74(1). 165203.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
den Dikken, Marcel. 1998. Predicate inversion in DP. In Alexiadou, Artemis & Wilder, Chris (eds.), Possessors, predicates and movement in the determiner phrase, 177214. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.Google Scholar
Dobrovie-Sorin, Carme & Giurgea, Ion. 2021. Proportional “many”/“much” and “most”. In Filip, Hana (ed.), Countability in natural language, 1451. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Grano, Thomas. 2022. Enough clauses, (non)finiteness, and modality. Natural Language Semantics. 30. 115153. doi:https://doi.org/10.1007/s11050-022-09190-w.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heggie, Lorie. 1988. The syntax of copular structures. Los Angeles, CA: University of Southern California dissertation.Google Scholar
Heim, Irene. 1985. Notes on comparatives and related matters. Manuscript, University of Texas at Austin. https://semantics.uchicago.edu/kennedy/classes/w11/comparatives/docs/heim85.pdf.Google Scholar
Heycock, Caroline. 2012. Specification, equation and agreement in copular sentences. Canadian Journal of Linguistics. 57(2). 209240.Google Scholar
Higgins, Roger. 1973. The pseudo-cleft construction in English. Boston, MA: MIT dissertation.Google Scholar
Hilbert, David. 1922. Neubegründung der Mathematik: Erste Mitteilung. Abhandlungen aus dem Seminarder Hamburgischen Universität, 1: 157177. English translation in: Mancosu, Paolo. 1998. From Brouwer to Hilbert, the Debate on the Foundations of Mathematics in the 1920s. 198–214. Oxford University Press, New York.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Höhn, Georg F. K. 2016. Unagreement is an illusion. Apparent person mismatches and nominal structure. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory. 34. 543592. doi:10.1007/s11049-015-9311-y.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hurtado, Alfredo. 1985. The unagreement hypothesis. In King, Larry & Maley, Catherine (eds.), Selected papers from the Thirteenth Linguistic Symposium on Romance Languages, 187211. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.Google Scholar
Ionin, Tania & Matushansky, Ora. 2006. The composition of complex cardinals. Journal of Semantics. 23. 315360.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ionin, Tania & Matushansky, Ora. 2018. Cardinals: The syntax and semantics of cardinal-containing expressions. Cambridge, Massachusetts: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Kayne, Richard S. 2005. On the syntax of quantity in English. In Movement and silence, 176214. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Klein, Ewan. 1980. A semantics for positive and comparative adjectives. Linguistics and Philosophy. 4(1). 145.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Klein, Ewan. 1991. Comparatives. In von Stechow, A. & Wunderlich, D. (eds.), Semantik/semantics: An international handbook of contemporary research, 673691. Berlin: De Gruyter.Google Scholar
Kratzer, Angelika. 1996. Severing the external argument from its verb. In Rooryck, Johan & Zaring, Laurie (eds.), Phrase structure and the lexicon, 109137. Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Kluwer Academic Publishers.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Link, Godehard. 1983. The logical analysis of plurals and mass terms. In Bauerle, R., Schwarze, C. & von Stechow, A. (eds.), Meaning, use and interpretation of language, 302323. Berlin: De Gruyter.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McNally, Louise. 1997. A semantics of the English existential construction. New York: Garland Press.Google Scholar
McNally, Louise. 2009. Properties, entity correlates of properties, and existentials. In Giannakidou, Anastasia & Rathert, Monika (eds.), Quantification, definiteness, and nominalization, 163187. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Mendia, Jon Ander & Espinal, M.Teresa. 2023. A note on sufficiency predicates. In Lam, Suet-Ying & Ozaki, Satoru (eds.), Proceedings of the 52 Annual Meeting of the North East Linguistic Society, 199208. Amherst, MA: GSLA Publications.Google Scholar
Mikkelsen, Line. 2005. Copular clauses. Specification, predication and equation. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moltmann, Friederike. 2004. Nonreferential complements, derived objects and nominalizations. Journal of Semantics. 21(1). 143.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moltmann, Friederike. 2009. Degree structure as trope structure: A trope-based analysis of positive and comparative adjectives. Linguistics and Philosophy. 32(1). 5194.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moro, Andrea. 1997. The raising of predicates. Predicative Noun Phrases and the theory of clause structure. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morzycki, Marcin. 2009. Degree modification of gradable nouns: Size adjectives and adnominal degree morphemes. Natural Language Semantics. 17(2). 175203.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morzycki, Marcin. 2016. Modification. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Partee, Barbara. 1987. Noun phrase interpretation and type-shifting principles. Studies in Discourse Representation Theory and the Theory of Generalized Quantifiers. 8. 115143.Google Scholar
Pustejovsky, James. 1995. The Generative Lexicon. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
RAE (Real Academia Espa ñ ola). 2009. Nueva Gramática de la Lengua Española. Madrid: Espasa Libros.Google Scholar
Reinhart, Tanya. 1997. Quantifier scope: How labor is divided between QR and Choice Functions. Linguistics and Philosophy. 20(4). 335397.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rett, Jessica. 2014. The polysemy of measurement. Lingua. 143. 242266.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rett, Jessica. 2018. Individual/degree polysemy. The emergence of number conference. Handout. OSU. https://linguistics.ucla.edu/people/Rett/Rett_2018_degree_polysemy.pdfGoogle Scholar
Romero, Maribel. 2021. The many readings of many: POS in the reverse proportional reading. Linguistics and Philosophy. 44. 281321.Google Scholar
Rothstein, Susan. 2017. Semantics for counting and measuring. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Schwarzschild, Roger. 2006. The role of dimensions in the syntax of noun phrases. Syntax. 9. 67110.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scontras, Gregory. 2022. On the semantics of number morphology. Linguistics and Philosophy. 45. 11651196.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Seuren, Pieter A. M. 1973. The comparative. In Kiefer, F. & Ruwet, N. (eds.), Generative grammar in Europe, 528564. Dordrecht: Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sharvy, Richard. 1980. A more general theory of definite descriptions. Philosophical Review. 89. 607–64.Google Scholar
Solt, Stephanie. 2009. The semantics of adjectives of quantity. New York: The City University of New York dissertation.Google Scholar
Solt, Stephanie. 2015. Q-adjectives and the semantics of quantity. Journal of Semantics. 32(2). 221273.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Svenonius, Peter. 1994. Dependent nexus: Subordinate predication structures in English and the Scandinavian languages. Santa Cruz, CA: University of California, Santa Cruz dissertation.Google Scholar
Sybesma, Rynt. 1999. The Mandarin VP. Boston: Kluwer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wellwood, Alexis. 2019. The meaning of more. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Winter, Yoad. 1997. Choice functions and the scopal semantics of indefinites. Linguistics and Philosophy. 20. 399467.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
von Fintel, Kai & Keenan, Edward L.. 2018. Determiners, conservativity, witnesses. Journal of Semantics. 35. 207217. doi:10.1093/jos/ffx018.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
von Heusinger, Klaus. 1997. Definite descriptions and choice functions. Logic, Language and Computation. 5. 6191.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
von Stechow, Arnim. 1984. Comparing semantic theories of comparison. Journal of Semantics. 3(1–2). 177.CrossRefGoogle Scholar