Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-dlnhk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-30T19:11:46.598Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Panel Comment: Why the Use of Anonymous Samples for Research Matters

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2021

Abstract

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Article
Copyright
Copyright © American Society of Law, Medicine and Ethics 1995

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

45 C.F.R. § 46.101–.409 (1994).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Annas, G.J. Glantz, L.H. Roche, P.A., The Genetic Privacy Act and Commentary (Boston: Boston University School of Public Health, 1995): § 131(d)(2).Google Scholar
Id. at 53–54. It is difficult to know what constitutes privacy interests, because that term is not defined either in the GPA or in the accompanying Commentary.Google Scholar
Id. § 131(g).Google Scholar
Hernnstein, R.J. Murray, C., The Bell Curve: Intelligence and Class Structure in American Life (New York: Free Press, 1994); and Fraser, S., ed., The Bell Curve Wars: Race, Intelligence and the Future of America (New York: Basic Books, 1995).Google Scholar
Nelkin, D. Tancredi, L., Dangerous Diagnostics: The Social Power of Biological Information (New York: Basic Books, 1989); Alper, J.S. Beckwith, J., “Genetic Fatalism and Social Policy: The Implications of Behavior Genetics Research,” Yale Journal of Biology and Medicine, 66 (1993): 511–24; Anonymous, “Genetic Expectations,” Nature, 373 (1995): 644; Horgan, J., “Eugenics Revisited,” Scientific American, 268, no. 6 (1993): 122–31; Kevles, D.J., “Vital Essences and Human Wholeness: The Social Readings of Biological Information,” Southern California Law Review, 65 (1991): 255–78; Maddox, J., “Wilful Public Misunderstanding of Genetics,” Nature, 364 (1993): 281; Rose, S., “The Rise of Neurogenetic Determinism,” Nature, 373 (1995): 380–82; and Rose, S., “Neurogenetic Determinism,” Science, 265 (1994): 1159.Google Scholar
For a particularly thoughtful analysis of similar issues in the context of anonymous HIV-seroprevalence testing, see Kopelman, L.M., “Informed Consent and Anonymous Tissue Samples: The Case of HIV Seroprevalence Studies,” Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 19 (1994): 525–52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
See generally Lippman, A., “Prenatal Genetic Testing and Screening: Constructing Needs and Reinforcing Inequities,” American Journal of Law & Medicine, XVII (1991): 1550; see also supra note 6.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Minimal risk means that the probability and magnitude of harm or discomfort anticipated in the research are not greater in and of themselves than those ordinarily encountered in daily life or during the performance of routine physical or psychological examinations or tests.” 45 C.F.R. § 46.102(1) (1994) (italics original).Google Scholar
45 C.F.R. § 46.116(d)(1).Google Scholar
Somatic or acquired mutations are an exception. This distinction, however, is not always clear in practice because some mutations that are frequently observed to be acquired, such as those in p53, may also be present in some individuals' germ line, as is observed in the families affected by Li-Fraumeni syndrome.Google Scholar
Heyman, S.J., “Foundations of the Duty to Rescue,” Vanderbilt Law Review, 47 (1994): 6730–755.Google Scholar
Callahan, D., “Bioethics: Private Choice and Public Good,” Hastings Center Report, 24, no. 3 (1994): 2829.Google Scholar
45 C.F.R. § 46.101(b)(4).Google Scholar
Kopelman, , supra note 7; and Clayton, E.W. et al., “Informed Consent for Genetic Research on Stored Tissue Samples,” JAMA, 274 (1995): 1786–92.Google Scholar
Kopelman, , supra note 7; and Clayton, et al., supra note 15.Google Scholar