Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-7cvxr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-25T01:41:04.041Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Reek of Cruelty and the Quest for Healing—Where Retributive and Restorative Justice Meet

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  25 September 2015

Extract

[T]his is the awful privilege of our generation and of my people, no one better than us has ever been able to grasp the incurable nature of the offence, that spreads like a contagion. It is foolish to think that human justice can eradicate it. It is an inexhaustible fount of evil; it breaks the body and the spirit of the submerged, it perpetuates itself as hatred among survivors, and swarms around in a thousand ways, against the very will of all, as thirst for revenge, as a moral capitulation, as denial, as weariness, as renunciation.

Primo Levi.

The Holocaust remains imprinted on western consciousness as the epitome of a crime “which no human justice can eradicate.” Primo Levi, an Italian Jewish survivor of Auschwitz, knew this well. The tragedy of the Holocaust is that the cry “never again,” which came in its wake, has failed to control human evil. Stories of the former Yugoslavia, Rwanda, Burundi, apartheid South Africa and elsewhere remind us of the capacity of humankind to commit the kind of heinous crimes that no amount of human justice nor reparation can assuage. This tragic reality motivates Carlos Nino in Radical Evil on Trial to pose the all-important question: “How shall we live with evil? How shall we respond to massive human rights violations committed either by State actors or by others with the consent and tolerance of their governments?”

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Center for the Study of Law and Religion at Emory University 1999

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1. Levi, Primo, The Truce in Friedlander, Albert A, ed, Out of the Whirlwind: A Reader of Holocaust Literature 426 (Schocken Books, 1976)Google Scholar. Emphasis added.

2. Nino, Carlos, Radical Evil on Trial 7 (Yale U Press, 1996)Google Scholar.

3. Minow, Martha, Between Vengeance and Forgiveness 12 (Beacon Press, 1998)Google Scholar.

4. Jacoby, Susan, Wild Justice: The Evolution of Revenge 10 (Harper & Row, 1983)Google Scholar.

5. Mackie, J.L., Morality and the Retributive Emotions, Criminal Justice Ethics 39 (1982)Google Scholar.

6. Murphy, Jeffrie & Hampton, Jean, eds, Forgiveness and Mercy 135 (Cambridge U Press, 1994)Google Scholar.

7. Shriver, Donald, An Ethic for Enemies: Forgiveness in Politics 13 (Oxford U Press, 1995)Google Scholar.

8. Malinowski, B., Myth in Primitive Psychology in Myth, Science and Religion and Other Essays 101 (Negro U Press, 1971)Google Scholar. Cited in Gorringe, Timothy, God's Just Vengeance 11 (Cambridge U Press, 1996)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

9. Id. See also Shriver, An Ethic for Enemies (cited in note 7) both on the Christian tradition and on Greek mythological reflections on the vengeance of the gods.

10. Berman, Harold, Law and Revolution: The Formation of the Western Tradition (Harv U Press, 1983)Google Scholar.

11. Luther, Martin, An Open Letter to The Christian Nobility of the German Nation Concerning the Reform of the Christian Estate, in 2 Works of Martin Luther (A.J. Holman Co, intro & trans by Jacobs, C.M., 1915)Google Scholar.

12. Cape Times (July 1, 1999).

13. Nietzsche, Friedrich, The Genealogy of Morals (Random House, 1969)Google Scholar.

14. Id at 25.

15. Id at 22.

16. von Harnack, Adolf, 6 History of Dogma 76 (Williams & Norgate, 1897)Google Scholar; Gorringe, , God's Just Vengeance at 101 (cited in note 8)Google Scholar.

17. Shriver, , An Ethic for Enemies at 46 (cited in note 7)Google Scholar.

18. Id at 49.

19. Levi, The Truce (cited in note 1).

20. Hart, H.L.A., Punishment and Responsibility 255 (Clarendon Press, 1968)Google Scholar. Also, Gorringe, , God's Just Vengeance at 23 (cited in note 8)Google Scholar.

21. Nino, , Radical Evil on Trial at 143, 160 (cited in note 2)Google Scholar. Emphasis added.

22. Murphy, & Hampton, , Forgiveness and Mercy at 130 (cited in note 6)Google Scholar.

23. Bolton, John R., The Global Prosecutors: Hunting War Criminals in the Name of Utopia, 78 For Affairs 157–64 (1999)Google Scholar.

24. Fuller, Lon, Positivism and the Fidelity to Law-A Reply to Professor Hart 71 Harv L Rev 630, 642 (1958)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

25. Dworkin, Ronald, Law's Empire 413 (Belknap Press of Harv U Press, 1986)Google Scholar.

26. Nino, , Radical Evil on Trial at 161 (cited in note 2)Google Scholar. The conceptual and practical difficulties involved in this situation are developed by Nino.

27. Murphy, & Hampton, , Forgiveness and Mercy at 126 (cited in note 6)Google Scholar.

28. Nino, , Radical Evil on Trial at 7 (cited in note 2)Google Scholar. Emphasis added.

29. In an unpublished proposal to NYU, proposing an Institute for Transitional Justice.

30. Orentlicher, Dianne, Settling Accounts: The Duty to Prosecute Human Rights Violations of a Prior Regime 100 Yale L J 2537 (1991)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

31. Minow, Martha, Between Vengeance and Forgiveness 87 (Beacon Press, 1998)Google Scholar. See also Michael Marrus, History and the Holocaust in the Courtroom, a paper delivered at the conference, Searching for Memory and Justice: The Holocaust and Apartheid at Yale U, Feb 8-10, 1998 (copy on file with the author).

32. Fuller, , Positivism and the Fidelity to Law at 666 (cited in note 24)Google Scholar.

33. Dworkin, , Law's Empire at 413 (cited in note 25)Google Scholar.

34. See Kelman, Mark, A Guide to Critical Legal Studies (Harv U Press, 1987)Google Scholar.

35. 1 Truth and Reconciliation Commission Report chs 110-14 (Cape Town, 1998)Google Scholar.

36. Deterrent justice, rehabilitative justice, compensatory justice, justice given to the affirmation of human dignity and justice as exoneration are discussed within the context of retributive and restorative justice in my Restorative Justice article in Villa-Vicencio, C. & Verwoerd, W., eds, Looking Back/Reaching Forward (U Cape Town Press, 2000)Google Scholar.

37. Orentlicher, , Settling Accounts at 2596 (cited in note 30)Google Scholar.

38. Paul van Zyl, Justice Without Punishment: Guaranteeing Human Rights in Transitional Societies, in Villa-Vicencio & Verwoerd, Looking Back/Reaching Forward (cited in note 36).

39. He at the same time recognises that there may be illegitimate reasons for failing to prosecute. These include, political timidity, the preservation of privileges associated with political office, the concealment of the involvement of members of the new government in human rights abuse, and a willingness to pander to the interests of the political and economic elite.

40. Rome Statute, art 75.2.

41. See Mahomed J, AZAPO and Others v the President of the RSA and Others, 1996 (8) BCLR 1015 (CC). In a unanimous ruling, Mahomed DP stated that the country “has neither the resources nor the skills to reverse fully [the] massive wrongs” of the past. He argued that

the resources of the state have to be deployed imaginatively, wisely, efficiently and equitably, to facilitate the reconstruction process in a manner which best brings relief and hope to the widest sections of the community, developing for the benefit of the entire nation the latent human potential and resources of every person who has directly and indirectly been burdened with the heritage of the shame and the pain of our racist past.

Of the nine judges, only Didcott J. provided a separate concurring judgment, giving his own reasons for supporting the findings of the Court. He questions whether the court is in a position to conclude that it is impossible to compensate all victims of apartheid, suggesting that there is no way of assessing the cost involved. Accepting that the Act allows for “some quid pro quo for the loss” suffered as a result of gross human rights violations, Didcott J. concedes that nothing “more definite, detailed and efficacious could feasibly have been promised at this stage.” His substantial argument is, however, that § 33 (2) of the Interim Constitution allows for amnesty for vicarious liability. It is necessary in this regard to note that § 2, 32 (4) of the Interim Constitution allows that no section of the Constitution, including the postscript on amnesty should be regarded as having less validity than any other part of the Constitution.

42. See Rome Statute, art 79.

43. See also unpublished paper presented by Goldstone, Judge Richard, Truth Commissions and Tribunals: Contradictory or Complementary in Geneva, 12 1998 (copy on file with the author)Google Scholar.

44. Mda, Zakes, The Ugly Truth Behind SA Crime (Mail & Guardian, 07 2-8, 1999)Google Scholar.

45. Wilson, Richard, The Sizwe Will Not Go Away: the Truth and Reconciliation Commission, Human Rights and Nation-Building in South Africa, 55 African Studies 1418 (1998)Google Scholar.

46. Boraine, Alex, Dealing with the Past 15 (IDASA, 1994)Google Scholar.

47. Jonathan Allen, Balancing Justice and Social Unity: Political Theory and the Idea of a Truth and Reconciliation Commission (unpublished paper on file with the author).

48. Mahomed J, AZAPO and Others v the President of the RSA and Others at ¶ 21 (cited in note 41).

49. See note 41.

50. In a joint sitting of Parliament to debate the Report of the TRC on Feb 25, 1999.

51. 5 Truth and Reconciliation Commission Report ch 9 ¶ 33 (Cape Town, 1998)Google Scholar.

52. Shriver, , An Ethic for Enemies at 83 (cited in note 7)Google Scholar.

53. Id at 84.

54. Speech delivered at the Witwatersrand U Graduation Ceremony, Sept 1, 1998. Text provided in press release by Dr. Russell Ally, Project Manager, UN Office of the High Commissioner for Human Rights, Johannesburg (copy on file with the author).