Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-mkpzs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-27T18:07:18.606Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Interactive intentionality and norm formation

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  21 December 2018

Pietro Guarnieri*
Affiliation:
Department of Economics and Management, University of Pisa, Pisa, Italy
*
*Corresponding author. Email: [email protected]

Abstract

The paper aims at complementing Searle's social ontology with an epistemology capable of illustrating institution formation. To this purpose, I discuss Searle's conception of constitutive rules and show that it requires the specifications of normative powers and purposes identifying status functions to be taken as given. However, such specifications arise from underlying normative commitments that may be various and possibly conflicting. Hence, in order to account for the formation of institutions, it is necessary to understand how status function declarations may emerge from alternative normative commitments. I make the hypothesis of “interactive intentionality,” as an interactive and deliberative mode of practical reasoning, to describe the processes of convergence on definite constitutive rules. These processes show how interactive intentionality may frame both commitment and enforcement, thus providing some insights to make rule-based and equilibrium-based accounts of institutions epistemologically commensurable.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Millennium Economics Ltd 2018 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Aoki, M. (2007), ‘Endogenizing Institutions and Institutional Changes’, Journal of Institutional Economics, 3(1): 131.Google Scholar
Aoki, M. (2011), ‘Institutions as Cognitive Media between Strategic Interactions and Individual Beliefs’, Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization, 79(1): 2034.Google Scholar
Binmore, K. (2015), ‘Institutions, Rules and Equilibria: A Commentary’, Journal of Institutional Economics, 11(3): 493496.Google Scholar
Chang, R. (1997), Incommensurability, Incomparability, and Practical Reason, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Crespo, R. F. (2007), ‘“Practical Comparability” and Ends in Economics’, Journal of Economic Methodology, 14(3): 371393.Google Scholar
Crespo, R. F. (2016), ‘Aristotle on Agency, Habits and Institutions’, Journal of Institutional Economics, 12(4): 867884.Google Scholar
Fagin, R., Halpern, J. Y., Moses, Y. and Vardi, M. (1995), Reasoning about Knowledge, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Gilbert, M. (1989), On Social Facts, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Gilbert, M. (2007), ‘Searle and Collective Intentions’, in Tsohatzidis, S. L. (ed.) Intentional Acts and Institutional Facts, Basel, Switzerland: Springer, pp. 3148.Google Scholar
Gilbert, M. (2013), Joint Commitment: How We Make the Social World, Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Gintis, H. (2007), ‘The Evolution of Private Property’, Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization, 64(1): 116.Google Scholar
Gintis, H. (2009), The Bounds of Reason: Game Theory and the Unification of the Behavioral Sciences, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Greif, A. (2006), Institutions and the Path to the Modern Economy: Lessons from Medieval Trade, Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Greif, A. and Kingston, C. (2011), ‘Institutions: Rules or Equilibria?’ in Schoefield, N. and Caballero, G. (eds), Political Economy of Institutions, Democracy and Voting, Basel, Switzerland: Springer, pp. 1343.Google Scholar
Habermas, J. (1990), Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Hédoin, C. (2015), ‘Accounting for Constitutive Rules in Game Theory’, Journal of Economic Methodology, 22(4): 439461.Google Scholar
Hédoin, C. (2017), ‘Institutions, Rule-following and Game Theory’, Economics & Philosophy, 33(1): 4372.Google Scholar
Hindriks, F. (2009), ‘Constitutive Rules, Language, and Ontology’, Erkenntnis, 71(2): 253275.Google Scholar
Hindriks, F. and Guala, F. (2014), ‘Institutions, Rules, and Equilibria: A Unified Theory’, Journal of Institutional Economics, 11(3): 459480.Google Scholar
Hindriks, F. and Guala, F. (2015), ‘A Unified Social Ontology’, Philosophical Quarterly, 65(259): 177201.Google Scholar
Honohan, I. (2010), The Theory and Politics of Ius Soli, EUDO-Citizenship Comparative Report 2, Robert Schuman Centre for Advanced Studies, European University Institute, Florence, available at http://eudo-citizenship.eu/docs/IusSoli.pdf (accessed 13 November 2018).Google Scholar
Hodgson, G. M. (2006), ‘What Are Institutions?Journal of Economic Issues, 40(1): 123.Google Scholar
Hodgson, G. M. (2015), ‘On Defining Institutions: Rules versus Equilibria’, Journal of Institutional Economics, 11(3): 497505.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. (1969), Conventions, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Lillie, N. and Simola, A. (2016), ‘The Crisis of Free Movement in the European Union’, Mondi Migranti, 3: 719.Google Scholar
Sanchez-Cuenca, I. (2007), ‘A Behavioural Critique of Searle's Theory of Institutions’, in Tsohatzidis, S. L. (ed.), Intentional Acts and Institutional Facts, Basel, Switzerland: Springer, pp. 175189.Google Scholar
Sandel, M. J. (1982), Liberalism and the Limits of Justice, Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Schotter, A. (1981), The Economic Theory of Social Institutions, Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Searle, J. R. (1995), The Construction of Social Reality, New York: Simon & Schuster.Google Scholar
Searle, J. R. (2005), ‘What Is an Institution?Journal of Institutional Economics, 1(1): 122.Google Scholar
Searle, J. R. (2010), Making the Social World: The Structure of Human Civilization, Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Searle, J. R. (2015), ‘Status Functions and Institutional Facts: Reply to Hindriks and Guala’, Journal of Institutional Economics, 11(3): 507514.Google Scholar
Sugden, R. (1986), The Economics of Rights, Co-operation and Welfare, Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Sugden, R. (2015), ‘On “Common-sense Ontology”: A Comment on the Paper by Frank Hindriks and Francesco Guala’, Journal of Institutional Economics, 11(3): 489492.Google Scholar
Tuomela, R. (1991), ‘We Will Do It: An Analysis of Group-intentions’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 51(2): 249277.Google Scholar
Tuomela, R. (2005), ‘We-intentions Revisited’, Philosophical Studies, 125(3): 327369.Google Scholar
Tuomela, R. and Miller, K. (1988), ‘We-intentions’, Philosophical Studies, 53(3): 367389.Google Scholar
Urbinati, N. (2017), Art. 1 Costituzione Italiana, Rome, Italy: Carocci editore.Google Scholar
Velleman, J. D. (2009), The Possibility of Practical Reason, Ann Arbor, MI: Michigan Publishing, University of Michigan Library.Google Scholar
Viskovatoff, A. (2003), ‘Searle, Rationality, and Social Reality’, American Journal of Economics and Sociology, 62(1): 744.Google Scholar
Young, H. P. (1998), Individual Strategy and Social Structure: An Evolutionary Theory of Institutions, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Zaibert, L. and Smith, B. (2007), ‘The Varieties of Normativity: An Essay on Social Ontology’, in Tsohatzidis, S. L. (ed.), Intentional Acts and Institutional Facts, Basel, Switzerland: Springer, pp. 157173.Google Scholar
Zaibert, L. A. (2003), ‘Collective Intentions and Collective Intentionality’, American Journal of Economics and Sociology, 62(1): 209232.Google Scholar