Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-7cvxr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T18:32:56.946Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Aggression and the symmetrical application of International Humanitarian Law*

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  09 February 2015

Pablo Kalmanovitz*
Affiliation:
Max Weber Fellow, Department of Law, European University Institute, Florence, Italy Assistant Professor, Department of Political Science, Universidad de los Andes, Bogotá, Colombia

Abstract

Recent scholarship in just war theory has challenged the principle of symmetrical application of International Humanitarian Law (IHL). This revisionist work, which is increasingly dominating the field of contemporary war ethics, rejects the idea that the rules of conduct of war (jus in bello) should be agnostic about the justice of the decision to go to war (jus ad bellum). Just wars are perceived to be inherently at odds with the principle of symmetrical application of IHL, which appears to create a hard choice between justice and legality. I show that this challenge to IHL is misplaced. It derives from a widespread view among just war theorists according to which only one side in a just war can be justified in using force. By looking closely at the nature of adjudication of just causes of war, I show that there can be cases of war in which both sides are justified in using force, and cases in which, though not objectively justified, both sides may be excused for fighting. On the basis of this understanding of jus ad bellum, I argue that the principle of symmetrical application of IHL in fact best reflects the uncertainty and complexity that should characterize the practical doctrine of jus ad bellum.

Type
Original Papers
Copyright
© Cambridge University Press 2015 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

*

Earlier versions of this article were presented at the 2011 Annual Meeting of the Association of Political Theory, the Political Theory Workshop at Yale University, before audiences in the political science departments at Columbia University, Brown University, and Ohio State University, and at the Inagural Conference of the Stockholm Centre for the Ethics of War and Peace.

References

Arneson, Richard J. 2006. “Just Warfare Theory and Noncombatant Immunity.” Cornell International Law Journal (39):663689.Google Scholar
Benbaji, Yitzhak. 2008. “A defense of the traditional war convention.” Ethics 118:464495.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bergsmo, Morten, and Kalmanovitz, Pablo. 2010. Law in Peace. Oslo: Torkel Opsahl Academic Publishing.Google Scholar
Booth, Ken, and Wheeler, Nicholas J.. 2008. The Security Dilemma: Fear, Cooperation and Trust in World Politics. Basingstoke and New York: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Buchanan, Allen. 2004. Justice, Legitimacy, and Self-determination: Moral Foundations for International Law. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Buchanan, Allen 2007. “Justifying Preventive War.” In Preemption: Military Action and Moral Justification, edited by Henry Shue and David Rodin. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Bull, Hedley. 1966. “The Grotian Conception of International Society.” In Diplomatic Investigations: Essays in the Theory of International Politics, edited by Herbert Butterfield and Martin Wight. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
CAVR. 2005. Chega! The Report of the Commission for Reception, Truth and Reconciliation. Dili, Timor Leste.Google Scholar
Clark, Christopher M. 2012. The Sleepwalkers: How Europe Went to War in 1914. London: Allen Lane.Google Scholar
Clark, Phil. 2009. “Grappling in the Great Lakes: The Challenges of International Justice in Rwanda, the Democratic Republic of Congo and Uganda.” In The Role of International Law in Rebuilding Societies after Conflict, edited by Brett Bowden, Hilary Charlesworth, and Jeremy Farrall, 244269. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Coady, Tony. 2008. “The Status of Combatants.” In Just and Unjust Warriors: The Moral and Legal Status of Soldiers, edited by David Rodin and Henry Shue, 153175. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Coates, Anthony Joseph. 1997. The Ethics of War. Manchester: Manchester University Press.Google Scholar
Cogan, Jacob Katz. 2002. “International Criminal Courts and Fair Trials: Difficulties and Prospects.” Yale Journal of International Law 27:111140.Google Scholar
Copeland, Dale C. 2000. The Origins of Major War. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Coppieters, Bruno. 2003. “War and Secession: A Moral Analysis of the Georgian-Abkhaz Conflict.” In Contextualizing Secession: Normative Studies in Comparative Perspective, edited by Bruno Coppieters and Richard Sakwa, 187212. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Dinstein, Yoram. 2011. War, Aggression and Self-defence, 5th ed.Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Doyle, Michael W. 2008. Striking First: Preemption and Prevention in International Conflict. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Fabre, Cécile. 2009. “Guns, Food, and Liability to Attack in War.” Ethics 120:3663.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fabre, Cécile 2012. Cosmopolitan War. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Fearon, James D. 1995. “Rationalist Explanations for War.” International Organization 49(3):379414.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fearon, James, and Laitin, David. 1996. “Explaining Interethnic Cooperation.” The American Political Science Review 90(4):715735.Google Scholar
Fletcher, George P. 1978. Rethinking Criminal Law. Boston: Little Brown.Google Scholar
Gaskins, Richard H. 1993. Burdens of Proof in Modern Discourse. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Glaser, Charles L. 2010. Rational Theory of International Politics: The Logic of Competition and Cooperation. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Gray, Christine. 2003. “The Use and Abuse of the International Court of Justice: Cases concerning the Use of Force after Nicaragua.” European Journal of International Law 14(5):867905.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gray, Christine 2014. “The International Court of Justice and the Use of Force.” In The Development of International Law by the International Court of Justice, edited by Christian Tams, and James Sloan, 237261. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Grotius, Hugo, and Kelsey, Francis W.. 1925. “De jure belli ac pacis libri tres.” Classics of International Law. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Haggenmacher, Peter. 1992. “Just War and Regular War in Sixteenth Century Spanish Doctrine.” International Review of the Red Cross 290:434445.Google Scholar
Hart, Herbert Lionel Adolphus. 1997. The Concept of Law, 2nd ed.Oxford and New York: Clarendon Press and Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Henckaerts, Jean-Marie, Louise, Doswald-Beck, and ICRC. 2007. Customary International Humanitarian Law. Volume I, Rules. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Howard, Michael. 2007. The First World War: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Jervis, Robert. 1976. Perception and Misperception in International Politics. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Jervis, Robert 1978. “Cooperation Under the Security Dilemma.” World Politics 30(2):167214.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Johnson, James Turner. 1975. Ideology, Reason, and the Limitation of War: Religious and Secular Concepts, 1200–1740. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Kaufman, Stuart J. 1996. “Spiralling to Ethnic War.” International Security 21(2):108138.Google Scholar
Kasfir, Nelson. 2004. “Domestic anarchy, Security Dilemmas, and Violent Predation: Causes of Failure.” In When States Fail: Causes and Consequences, edited by Robert I. Rotberg. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Kutz, Christopher. 2005. “The Difference Uniforms Make: Collective Violence in Criminal Law and War.” Philosophy and Public Affairs 33(2):148180.Google Scholar
Lauterpacht, Hersch. 1953. “Rules of Warfare in an Unlawful War.” In Law and Politics in the World Community: Essays on Hans Kelsen’s Pure Theory and Related Problems in International Law, edited by George A. Lipsky, 89113. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Lieber, Keir A. 2007. “The New History of World War I and What It Means for International Relations Theory.” International Security 32(2):155191.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lindley, Dan. 2007. Promoting Peace with Information: Transparency as a Tool of Security Regimes. Princeton and Oxford: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Luban, David. 2004. “Preventive War.” Philosophy and Public Affairs 32(3):207248.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Luban, David 2007. “Preventive War and Human Rights.” In Preemption: Military Action and Moral Justification, edited by Henry Shue and David Rodin, 171201. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Mamdani, Mahmood. 2009. Saviors and Survivors: Darfur, Politics, and the War on Terror. New York: Pantheon Books.Google Scholar
Mapel, David R. 1998. “Coerced Moral Agents? Individual Responsibility for Military Service.” Journal of Political Philosophy 6(2):171189.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McMahan, Jeff. 2004. “The Ethics of Killing in War.” Ethics 114(4):693733.Google Scholar
McMahan, Jeff 2005. “Just Cause for War.” Ethics & International Affairs 19(3):121.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McMahan, Jeff 2006. “Preventive War and the Killing of the Innocent.” In The Ethics of War: Shared Problems in Different Traditions, edited by Richard Sorabji and David Rodin, 169190. Hants and Burlington, VT: Ashgate.Google Scholar
McMahan, Jeff 2008. “The Morality of War and the Law of War.” In Just and Unjust Warriors: The Moral and Legal Status of Soldiers, edited by David Rodin and Henry Shue, 1943. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
McMahan, Jeff 2009. Killing in War. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
McMahan, Jeff 2013. “The Prevention of Unjust Wars.” In Reading Walzer, edited by Yitzhak Benbaji and Naomi Sussmann, 233255. Londong: Routledge.Google Scholar
McMeekin, Sean. 2011. The Russian Origins of the First World War. Cambridge and London: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Nardin, Terry. 1983. Law, Morality, and the Relations of States. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
National Conference of Catholic Bishops. 1983. The Challenge of Peace: God’s Promise and Our Response. Washington, DC: Office of Publishing Services, United States Catholic Conference.Google Scholar
Neff, Stephen C. 2005. War and the Law of Nations: A General History. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Osiel, Mark. 2009. The End of Reciprocity: Terror, Torture, and the Law of War. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pagden, Anthony, and Lawrance, Jeremy. 1991. Francisco de Vitoria: Political Writings. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Posen, Barry. 1993. “The Security Dilemma and Ethnic Conflict.” Survival 35(1):2747.Google Scholar
Reichberg, Gregory. 2008. “Just War and Regular War: Competing Paradigms.” In Just and Unjust Warriors: The Moral and Legal Status of Soldiers, edited by David Rodin and Henry Shue, 193213. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Roberts, Adam. 2008. “The Equal Application of the Laws of War: A Principle Under Pressure.” International Review of the Red Cross 90(872):931962.Google Scholar
Robinson, Geoffrey. 2010. If You Leave Us Here, We Will Die: How Genocide was Stopped in East Timor. Princeton and Oxford: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Rodin, David. 2004. War and Self-defense. Oxford and New York: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Rodin, David 2008. “The Moral Inequality of Soldiers: Why jus in bello Asymmetry is Half-right.” In Just and Unjust Warriors: The Moral and Legal Status of Soldiers, edited by David Rodin, and Henry Shue, 4468. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rodin, David 2011. “Morality and Law in War.” In The Changing Character of War, edited by Hew Strachan and Sibylle Scheipers, 446463. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Schelling, Thomas C. 1966. Arms and Influence. New Haven and London: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Schelling, Thomas C 1980. The Strategy of Conflict. Cambridge: Harvard University.Google Scholar
Schwartz, Daniel. 2012. “The Justice of Peace Treaties.” Journal of Political Philosophy 20(3):273292.Google Scholar
Shue, Henry, and Rodin, David. 2007. Preemption: Military Action and Moral Justification. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Snyder, Jack. 1984. “Civil-Military Relations and the Cult of the Offensive, 1914 and 1984.” International Security 9(1):108146.Google Scholar
Snyder, Jack 1985. “Perceptions of the Security Dilemma in 1914.” In Psychology and Deterrence, edited by Robert Jervis, Richard Ned Lebow, and Janice Gross Stein, 153179. Baltimore and London: Johns Hopkins University Press.Google Scholar
Snyder, Jack 2008. “Correspondence: Defensive Realism and the ‘New’ History of World War I.” International Security 33(1):174185.Google Scholar
Snyder, Jack L, and Jervis, Robert. 1999. “Civil War and the Security Dilemma.” In Civil Wars, Insecurity, and Intervention, edited by Barbara F. Walter and Jack L. Snyder, 1537. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Steinhoff, Uwe. 2012. “Rights, liability, and the Moral Equality of Combatants.” Journal of Ethics 16:339366.Google Scholar
Stone, Julius. 1977. Conflict through Consensus: United Nations Approaches to Aggression. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.Google Scholar
Tang, Shiping. 2009. “The Security Dilemma: A Conceptual Analysis.” Security Studies 18:587623.Google Scholar
Taylor, John G. 1991. Indonesia's Forgotten War: The Hidden History of East Timor. London and Leichhardt: Zed Books and Pluto Press Australia.
Trachtenberg, Marc. 1990–1991. “The Meaning of Mobilization in 1914.” International Security 15(3):120150.Google Scholar
Van Evera, Stephen. 1984. “The Cult of the Offensive and the Origins of the First World War.” International Security 9(1):58107.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Walzer, Michael. 1977. Just and Unjust Wars: A Moral Argument with Historical Illustrations. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Wedgwood, Ruth. 2003. “The Fall of Saddam Hussein: Security Council Mandates and Preemptive Self-defense.” The American Journal of International Law 97(3):576585.Google Scholar
Williams, Gwladys L. 1944. Selections from Three Works of Francisco Suárez. 2 vols, Classics of International Law. Oxford and London: Clarendon Press and H. Milford.Google Scholar