Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-lj6df Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-04T10:33:00.632Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Security, Society, and the Perennial Struggles over the Sacred: Revising the Wars of Religion in International Relations Theory

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  06 August 2024

Derek Bolton*
Affiliation:
King's College London, UK

Abstract

International relations theory tends to build on the conventional narrative of the Wars of Religion (WoR), which holds it was the irrationality of religious violence that generated the modern international system of pragmatic secular states—resulting in the presumed secularized, rational, and unemotive nature of politics. In contrast, this article reorients our focus to Durkheim's more social view of religion as a community of believers and to the continued role of the sacred and shared emotion/affect in social and political life. Specifically, it examines how modern communities (such as nations) remain constituted by a shared faith in conceptions of the sacred and how the corresponding sense of moral order is central to the enduring pursuit of ontological security. Therefore, it argues that international relations should focus on the perennial struggles over what communities hold sacred and that we can better understand the propensity for (“religious” or “secular”) violence by examining the continual interplay between the sacred, ontological security, and the hermeneutics of morality—with the so-called WoR being the locus classicus of this argument. Historical studies exploring how participants in the WoR navigated such struggles over the sacred thus allow us to explore these dynamics and further conceptualize our understanding of the sacred within modern “secular” politics. The article concludes by examining how the prospect for violence is interrelated with the perennial struggles over the sacred within, and between, political orders—a sentiment that brings into relief some of the hazards accompanying growing intrastate moral polarization and interstate ideological rivalry.

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The IO Foundation

Early modern Europe was beset with violence. The Reformation split political communities internally along religious lines while externally they engaged in protracted wars, often in reference to confessional lines. Such “religious” wars were to cease following the Peace of Westphalia, which solidified sovereignty and non-interference on religious grounds and ushered in pragmatic states and secular politics—or so the conventional myth goes. While Westphalia represented changes within post-Reformation Europe,Footnote 1 scholars have challenged its role in institutionalizing sovereignty and ushering forth the modern state system.Footnote 2 More recently, postsecular scholarship, which critically engages the “secular” and the various concepts considered to fall under its guise,Footnote 3 has criticized how the field of international relations (IR) invokes the Wars of Religion (WoR) and embraces the “Westphalian presumption”: the notion that prolonged battles over beliefs and doctrines exposed the need to eliminate religion from politics given its proclivity for irrationality and violence.Footnote 4 Not only did interfaith alliances emerge throughout the WoR, but scholars also struggle to distinguish “religious” from “secular” violence; definitions are often unable to incorporate religions they want included (such as Confucianism) or to exclude ideologies they hold separate (such as nationalism).Footnote 5

This article further pushes back against core assumptions within IR that, as laid out in the first section, are informed by myths around the WoR—specifically the presumed secularized, rational, and unemotive nature of politics. Rather than taking the WoR as dissimilar to modern secular politics, it argues we should focus on the continued role and importance of the sacred and collective emotions/affect in social and political life. Specifically, the article reorients our focus to Emile Durkheim's more social view of religion as an affective community constituted by shared faith in conceptions of the sacred and to how the corresponding sense of moral order is critical to the enduring pursuit of ontological security (OS)—the security of being. This allows us to recognize how perennial struggles over the sacred remain crucial to secular politics and violence. In other words, we can better understand the propensity for violence by examining the continual interplay between the sacred, OS, and the hermeneutics of morality—with the so-called WoR being the locus classicus of this argument.

Accordingly, the second section explores how communities are constituted by moral orders entwined with a shared faith in conceptions of the sacred and how we can consequently understand the pursuit of OS as interrelated with efforts to safeguard the sacred and act faithfully within/toward these moral orders. Conversely, the perceived defilement of the sacred can generate moral disorder and ontological insecurity—forcing actors to consider how best to repair their community. This allows us to consider the contemporary relevance of the shifting historiography of the WoR following Natalie Davis's argument it was the “community's sense of identity and autonomy, as well as its shared sense of purpose and meaning,” that motivated and justified violence,Footnote 6 particularly in France.Footnote 7 The WoR, from this perspective, were not derived from some irrational essence of religion, but interrelated with the moral disorder and ontological insecurity sparked by competing conceptions of what communities held sacred.

Following Durkheim, the third section argues that such concerns over the sacred are enduring and reveals the continued prevalence of the sacred within modern secular politics—as exemplified by political/civil religions and, of particular focus, nationalism.Footnote 8 Therefore, the WoR can be seen as merely one instance of a more general characteristic of the hostility that can accompany the perennial struggles over what communities hold sacred—further challenging the presumed uniqueness of post-Westphalian politics.Footnote 9 To this end, historical scholarship on the WoR, by exploring the “passions and emotions” of participants and how they contended with struggles over the sacred,Footnote 10 holds important insights for further conceptualizing the implications of the sacred and OS within modern secular politics and instances of violence.

Therefore, the remainder of the article draws out three major implications that emerge from exploring how the interplay between the sacred, OS, and the hermeneutics of morality influenced the WoR. This includes how the trajectory of conflict was interrelated with the processes through which participants return to the sources of the tradition to work out how best to refashion moral order; how social traditions and prevailing conceptions of the sacred informed the perceived legitimacy of peace; and how interpretations of the sacred and moral order (re)constructed social hierarchies and authority. Building on these insights, the article concludes by examining how, at a broader level, recognizing the perennial struggles over the sacred allows us to better account for the dynamism of raison d’état—that is, for the “relation between organized violence and political order of any sort.”Footnote 11 This is of critical importance given that the recurrence of organized violence—war, civil war, and terrorism—has been central to the study of IR. Accordingly, our understanding of IR is strengthened when we recognize that the prospect for such violence is interrelated with the perennial struggles over the sacred within and between political orders—a sentiment that brings into relief some of the potential dangers accompanying growing intrastate moral polarization and interstate ideological rivalry.

The Wars of Religion in International Relations

While IR theorists don't often engage with the WoR directly, we find core assumptions of the discipline are rooted in the “Westphalian presumption”—the argument by Enlightenment thinkers such as Hobbes and Locke that failure to separate civic and religious order generates violence by enabling irrational factors or because the diversity of religious beliefs cannot be mediated.Footnote 12 The implications of this narrative are profound. For one, it partakes in the modern invention of religion: the seventeenth-century reformulation of religion as “a set of propositions to which believers gave assent” and which could be compared against each other and “against natural science.”Footnote 13 Elites subsequently legitimated greater state power by framing the WoR as struggles over religious beliefs that only subsided with state centralization.Footnote 14

Moreover, the WoR feature as the “origin point of modern Western secularism,” wherein religious beliefs on salvation are differentiated from a doctrine that morality should be based solely on “the well-being of mankind in the present.”Footnote 15 Countries around the world subsequently “inherited, borrowed, had imposed upon them, or somehow ended up living with (or in tension with)” European narratives of secularism and secularization.Footnote 16 Specifically, there is a presumption that Westphalian sovereignty, which is (speciously) held as “devoid of theological content,” demarcates the modern state system from an “‘orientalized’ Other”—from the medieval era's “exotic congeries of ideas, institutions, and structures”—and juxtaposes an “increasingly advanced (because increasingly secular) West and a backward (because perpetually religious) rest.”Footnote 17 Importantly, “secularization” can have multiple interpretations. For one, there is the thesis's “definable core” regarding a historical process of increasing differentiation between religious and secular spheres, with the latter increasingly appropriating functions of the former.Footnote 18 Of more interest, however, are two additional propositions derived from Enlightenment critiques of religion: the supposed “decline of religious beliefs and practices, and . . . marginalization of religion to a privatized sphere.”Footnote 19 These propositions influenced IR in two interrelated ways: the understanding and application of rationality, and deficient discussion of religion given its presumed privatization.Footnote 20

Enlightenment narratives of the WoR, and especially Kant's turn to universal philosophy,Footnote 21 helped construct a dichotomy between the “perceived irrational, magical, or emotive qualities of religion and the inherent rationality of the secular” (for example, the state or economy).Footnote 22 Likewise, thinkers such as Hobbes and Locke championed the secular nature of sovereignty, emphasizing the resources only rulers could wield and that law is not about “moral assent … [but] controlling behavior and the disposition of property,” while obscuring those “forces in history and human nature that gave rise to sovereignty in the first place”—the ability to inspire awe and collective identity.Footnote 23 The WoR were thus used to support liberal modernity, which takes politicized religions as “dangerous to reason, freedom, and political stability” and religious adherents as “psychologically disturbed … inciters of intolerance and violence.”Footnote 24 However, it was assumed rational autonomous individuals will progressively evolve “from superstition to reason,” which is why secularization often assumed the abandonment of the sacred in society.Footnote 25 Faith and ritual are thus circumscribed to the private sphere, whereas “rational argument is said to exhaust public life.”Footnote 26 Accordingly, the “secular public sphere is construed as the domain of reason, objectivity, deliberation, and justice, and the religious private sphere the domain of subjectivity, transcendence, effeminacy, and affect.”Footnote 27

IR theory largely adopted this dichotomy,Footnote 28 alongside scholarship in the social sciences and on modernization theory suggesting a zero-sum relationship between tradition and modernity.Footnote 29 Religion is subsequently held as “peripheral” or a security problem due to its “absolutist, divisive and insufficiently rational character.”Footnote 30 For Hurd, realism and liberalism are “expressions of rationalist thought deeply antithetical to religion,” while “laicist assumptions sit quietly beneath the surface of structuralist and materialist” theories that take religion as “epiphenomenal to more fundamental material interests.”Footnote 31 Thomas similarly demonstrates links between the “Enlightenment project” and the mainstream neorealist/liberal conceptions of rationality as “independent of social and historical context or cultural or religious tradition.”Footnote 32 We also find a general tendency within IR to adopt “a deeper modern attitude” that places “emotions in opposition to rationality.”Footnote 33 Again, given the presumed privatization of religion, it was assumed that “primary ‘public’ institutions (state, economy) no longer need or are interested in maintaining a sacred cosmos or a public religious worldview,”Footnote 34 and that political decisions would be “free of passion.”Footnote 35 Emotions were thus either unincorporated into analysis or referenced to explain “irrational” decisions.Footnote 36

Rethinking the Narrative

The theoretical implications of the Westphalian presumption were not universally adopted by IR scholars—see, for example, Morgenthau's and Niebuhr's polemics against rationalism and the liberal idea that we can inhibit passions from stymying reason.Footnote 37 Both rejected the “power of reason … to solve the social problems of our age,” that the “social world is susceptible to rational control,”Footnote 38 and the dualism of rationality and emotion.Footnote 39 Likewise, both recognized the importance of anxiety and efforts to offset meaninglessness—that the “intellectual and moral history of mankind is the story of inner insecurity … of metaphysical anxieties,”Footnote 40 and that we require a “sense of what cannot be questioned, what one cannot go beyond.”Footnote 41 However, Morgenthau's critique of scientism chafes with his view of Westphalia as ushering forth sovereign states that will or should pursue “rational, objective, and unemotional” foreign policies.Footnote 42 Moreover, he feared this was jeopardized by the “political religion” of nationalism, which reverts war to the “religious type” of the sixteenth century.Footnote 43 Niebuhr likewise spoke of the dangers of nationalism, which, as Ross summarizes, becomes a greater “manifestation of selfishness and pride.”Footnote 44 Therefore, we again find remnants of the Westphalian presumption, with Philpott taking Morgenthau's emphasis on power and security and Niebuhr's advocacy of “the lesser of two evils” as emblematic of post-Westphalian secularization and the conception of states as “bereft of religious purposes.”Footnote 45 Still, we find in classical realism a preliminary recognition that politics remains interrelated with emotions, anxiety, and moral order—sentiments gaining traction with the growth of OS studies.

OS studies explore how efforts to manage the existential anxiety that accompanies our awareness of potential “nonbeing” “manifest in social and political behavior.”Footnote 46 Because one's community plays a vital role in the construction of self-identity and the management of anxiety around existence, meaninglessness, and guilt/condemnation—for example, providing stability, frameworks of meaning, and a sense of “home”Footnote 47—large segments of a population are invested in preserving the community's sense of self.Footnote 48 More recently, OS scholars have pursued a Lacanian-informed analysis of anxiety, wherein the unending desire to overcome our lack of a full sense of self drives individuals to identify with various signifiers and narratives.Footnote 49 Others, pulling from, for example, Heidegger and Kierkegaard, see subjects as constantly trying to become secure by not only managing anxiety but, at times, embracing it to allow for more authentic forms of being.Footnote 50 Unfortunately, mirroring IR theory more broadly, the role of shared emotions/affective contexts remains underdeveloped.Footnote 51

Only recently have studies started to remedy this disregard. For example, Steele briefly discusses the affective dimensions of soldier reunion videos as generating a sense of OS, while Mälksoo conceptualizes the identities around deterrence as interrelated with rituals that generate affective entanglements. In particular, Bolton pushes OS studies toward IR's “emotional turn” by reconceptualizing the sources of OS as interrelated with affective communities constituted by shared faith in a moral order entwined with the sacred.Footnote 52 These shifts have important implications for the presumed dichotomy within IR between premodern–irrational–religious and modern–rational–secular politics. Specifically, given that OS is taken as a fundamental and enduring human need,Footnote 53 they provide a new prism for elaborating on the continued entanglement between politics, emotional identifications, and conceptions of the sacredFootnote 54—and thus for exploring the contemporary relevance of historical scholarship on the WoR. To develop this argument, it helps to establish Durkheim's sociological view of religion, which informs much of the historical scholarship inspired by Davis,Footnote 55 and Bolton's reconceptualization of OS as interrelated with the sacred.

Moral (dis)Order, Ontological (in)Security, and the Sacred

Durkheim proposed a broader conception of religion as a moral community constituted by “beliefs and practices relative to sacred things, that is to say, things set apart and forbidden.”Footnote 56 He thus strove to understand the perennial nature of the sacred and how what is “set apart and forbidden” is subject to change between, and within, societies. Accordingly, the sacred is entwined with the emotional energies that arise from collective effervescence and are revitalized through ritual. During these moments, individuals are lifted out of egoism by the “self-transcending experience of social solidarity,”Footnote 57 experiencing emotions of strength and warmth. Because the power of these emotions is felt to be both internal and external to the individual, it becomes ascribed to an external force: a force associated with objects bestowed with sacred qualities within the collective conscience (for example, the objects, symbols, and myths at the center of rituals). Therefore, the “genesis of sacredness is a fundamentally anthropological phenomenon” interrelated with experiences of self-transcendence.Footnote 58 In other words, affective experiences are the foundation of the shared faith, a “predisposition toward believing that goes in advance of proof,” in the “beliefs, myths, dogmas, and legends … that express the nature of sacred things.”Footnote 59 The sacred is thus the focus of a shared reverence and devotion—it commands a willingness to sacrifice. It is these “emotional, symbolic and ideational forces” that in turn constitute society by allowing a moral order to emerge. Durkheim's interest in religion was thus related not to a Parsonian focus on order but to accounting for the “dynamic, always contingent, processes through which individuals become ‘social beings’.”Footnote 60

Bolton subsequently argues we can understand the drive for OS as leading actors to try to preserve the moral order, entwined with the sacred, that constitutes their community and provides meaning to its members.Footnote 61 This position is reinforced by Durkheim's argument that society is an “integral part of our being and, by the same stroke, uplifts it and brings it to maturity”: that those in moral unison experience a “confidence, courage and boldness in action,”Footnote 62 and that communing with the “gods” and the sacred provides the “strength to endure the trials of existence.” However, “these effects can be realized only in so far as the god is represented in his mind,” which requires that the gods (society) are “believed in with a collective faith.”Footnote 63 This dependence is why actors are willing to make a variety of sacrifices on the “gods’” behalf, or otherwise “feel extreme remorse.”Footnote 64 Importantly, this does not imply conservatism or that there is a single reading of faith. Instead, by taking seriously the dynamism of faith and tradition and recognizing that tradition and reflexivity are in no way antithetical, we find that the drive for OS is predicated on the hermeneutics of morality and the continued revitalization of a dynamic moral order—processes engendering varying degrees of change.Footnote 65 In other words, actors creatively return to the sources of the tradition and engage in an ongoing dialogue regarding the virtuous life and the sacrifices required for preserving the sacred.Footnote 66 This is qualitatively different from circumstances when the sacred becomes polluted and moral order destabilized, potentially generating anomie.

The Insecurity of Anomie

While it is commonly equated to normlessness, scholarship has shown Durkheim spoke of anomie in relation to règle, a prescriptive moral formulation, and dérèglement, a state of “corruption, evil, agitation, torment, impiety”—in short, moral disorder or “immorality.”Footnote 67 At the same time, he deployed anomie in reference to various conceptions of sin. Much as sin pertains to a “disease to be healed” and “general hostility against God,” anomie entails “moral pollution, and the profaning of the sacred,” resulting in a “painful state or condition felt by individuals as well as by society.”Footnote 68 Contradicting the strength of moral unity, anomie thus entails a weakening of the sources of OS, generating a “‘deranged’ state of disorganization” that “sets the stage for violence and abuse.” Therefore, when faced with anomie actors must work more intensely to refashion moral order—“establishing fixed normative referents, promoting social integration, and ensuring that existing norms are coordinated, incorporated into policies, and function properly.”Footnote 69 When curtailed by persistent “moral threats,” actors must then try to determine the sacrifices required to preserve the integrity of, and repair, the community, from “performing rites of purification” to using violence to remove the perceived “contamination.”Footnote 70

Anomie can be instigated by forces within and outside society. Regarding the latter, external actors might constrain a community's efforts to pursue its sense of “the good” or stigmatize it for the values it champions.Footnote 71 Regarding the former, we can examine the relationship between the “real” yet imperfect society that exists around us and the perfect society that is “a fancy, a dream … [of] aspirations toward the good.” The two cannot be separated, since it is by creating and recreating this ideal that society (re)makes itself. However, moments arise when society “hesitates over the manner in which it must conceive itself,” potentially leading to conflict between ideals,Footnote 72 or even antithetical ideals that divide society.Footnote 73 Likewise, the affective forces underpinning society might be revitalized in ways engendering revolutionary change and new formulations of the sacred (as in the French Revolution). However, this does not guarantee that the “revolutionary religion” is uniformly embraced, with the sacred becoming an “arena for conflict, change, and violence.”Footnote 74 Following scholarship inspired by Davis, we find this is precisely what occurred in France, where competing Catholic and Protestant conceptions of the sacred generated anomie and ontological insecurity.

The Wars of Religion: A Story of Anomie and Ontological Insecurity

By shifting analysis of the WoR to the “passions and emotions” of participants, Davis explains how, in contrast to earlier scholarship's emphasis on elites and state centralization, “religious divisions sparked violence in the localities even before leading grandees raised the banner of revolt,”Footnote 75 and how, far from following “ties of clientage or factional rivalry,” religious riots proved crucial to the outbreak and duration of civil war.Footnote 76 Conflict was thus linked to a palpable sense the body social “had been dangerously polluted and needed to be purified,” with Protestants and Catholics interpreting each other's purification efforts as further defiling the sacred.Footnote 77 This included the place of the Mass, the sacrament, and images and relics, all of which were critical to how France was defined—to its very identity and sense of order.

Specifically, a French national community had emerged in the late medieval/early modern era, one premised on links to the Franks and the perceived sanctity of France as the beacon of Christianity—fostering an early sense of ethnic election and the designation of “most Christian” for king, people, and territory.Footnote 78 Being French thus “meant to be a particularly good Christian,”Footnote 79 with the king swearing to defend the church, preserve “true peace for the Church of God,” and expel heretics.Footnote 80 This enabled the king to become “the focus of a new Christian cult, and France—a Church in its own right.”Footnote 81 By the fifteenth century France had become “personified [as the] most Christian domina Francia,” and there emerged a wider attachment to la France.Footnote 82 There was thus a prevailing image in which the “civic, monarchical, and Catholic symbols merged,”Footnote 83 with the community understood in reference to the “royal person, the high priest of a unique religious cult.”Footnote 84

Protestantism thus threatened to rupture society by radically breaking from France's “fathers,”Footnote 85 inhibiting concord (religious and political unity),Footnote 86 and profaning what was held sacred.Footnote 87 For example, visceral reactions to the emergence of placards attacking the Mass and the Eucharist derived from the fact that the Mass primarily represented “the bond between the communicants”Footnote 88 and, particularly for the laity, was about engaging in a “communal rite of greeting, sharing, giving, receiving, and making peace.”Footnote 89 The placards affair is thus emblematic of Protestants’ wider desire to “revolutionize society by eliminating false worship and idolatry and by renewing morals,” challenging the community's very foundation.Footnote 90 These rival interpretations of purity and pollution left members “fear[ing] for the safety of the entire community unless proper expiation was done.”Footnote 91 Protestants thus voluntarily withdrew from society to form “closed communities of the faithful” and were involuntarily excluded as they became equated to “gangrenous members.”Footnote 92

Where Protestant numbers grew, they began to purify churches—removing statues and whitewashing walls—and society, for example, by forbidding Mass and removing objects of idolatry.Footnote 93 For Catholics, these actions directly threatened “the social and sacral community,” resulting in an increasing militancy and “spiritual reawakening” and the use of various ceremonies “to repair the pollution of iconoclasm and restore the place of the sacred in society.”Footnote 94 For example, processions were used as a “symbolic (legal) appropriation of public space,” while edicts periodically confined Protestants to the private sphere and relegated worship to remote and degrading locations that represented their “social and religious distance … from a legitimate order.” Protestants, meanwhile, sought to reclaim space, for example, leaving workshop doors open and cooking meat on Lent, or singing psalms while marching to worship.Footnote 95 It was during such times, when “differences were publicly acted out,” that violence targeting the perceived sources of defilement erupted.Footnote 96

Therefore, the violence that culminated in, and prolonged, civil war in France was interrelated with the anomie and ontological insecurity that emerged from antithetical conceptions of the sacred coming into direct competition and inspiring actions destabilizing the other's sense of moral order. To this end, rather than taking the WoR as unconnected to modern secular politics, we should view the WoR as merely one instance wherein the perennial struggles over the sacred devolved into violence targeting perceived sources of defilement.

Perennial Struggles for the Sacred

Social understandings of religion, as adopted by Davis, have not gone without criticism. Cavanaugh, while sympathetic to this approach, laments that it still suggests there “is something out there called religion.”Footnote 97 At the same time, Cavanaugh emphasizes that his argument is that “people kill for all sorts of things that they treat as gods” and that secular causes are not “‘disenchanted’ at all, but are rather prone to idolatry.”Footnote 98 This focus on “gods” lends itself to Durkheim's position that sacred objects symbolize not only the “god(s)” but also society, “transfigured and imagined in the physical form”—and it is “because the gods are in a state of dependence on the thought of man that man can believe his help to be efficacious.”Footnote 99 Therefore, whether conceptions of the sacred are termed religious or secular, important insights are garnered from studying how individuals, driven by the desire for OS, are continuously willing to sacrifice on behalf of the sacred and how the sacred/profane boundary is constructed, negotiated, and managed. This allows us to explore how competition between conceptions of the sacred can turn violentFootnote 100—a position transcending Westphalia.

Again, for Durkheim, while the sacred can change its form it remains a constant feature of society, given that the profane cannot morally unite individuals.Footnote 101 This leads into Cavanaugh's claim that the gap “between early modern and modern is not as wide as we would like to believe.”Footnote 102 From explorations into the early modern “migration of the holy” from Church to European nation-states,Footnote 103 to the contemporary “metamorphosis of the sacred” seen in “civil and political religions,”Footnote 104 we find a recurrence of collective emotions, faith, and the sacred. Therefore, in addition to instances where the division between “politics” and “religion” remains alien or contested, we must also consider, for example, the secular sacred: how “secular practices and values can take on well-nigh sacred dimensions,” becoming vital to contemporary “politics of binding, belonging and exclusion.”Footnote 105 Of particular interest is how nation-states—the supposed exemplars of secular politics—are constituted by the sacred and how religion “re-emerges within [modernity] in new guises … transmuted in and by nationalism.”Footnote 106

To establish this relationship we must go back to the fifteenth-century fragmentation of Christendom and the Council of Constance, during which a “new principle of territorial kingdoms, legitimated in terms of ‘nations’,” emerged.Footnote 107 At the same time, there was an increasing consciousness among sixteenth-century populations, particularly in Western Europe, of belonging to a “particular cultural and/or political community”—the “attachment of myths, symbols, traditions, values, and memories to certain culturally defined populations.”Footnote 108 This laid the groundwork for nationalist ideologies, as contemporaries creatively engaged the Old Testament.Footnote 109 Europe thus began experiencing the “ideological power generated by attaching reformed religious faith (and Catholic post-Tridentine counter-faith)” to nations.Footnote 110

While European rulers long applied the Old Testament notion of sacred kingship, Protestants began emphasizing the conditional covenant between God and the Israelites and the creation of a “holy nation.” This resulted in discussions of the elect nation and the emergence of religious nationalisms. In England, Catholic plots against the Crown and the threat of Spain facilitated a fusion of “English national sentiment with strong Protestant conviction” and, by the 1640s, a desire to forge a republic inspired by the Old Testament. Likewise, the Dutch revolt led to comparison with ancient Israel, with the Dutch people “described as ‘God's elect’ and ‘God's people’.”Footnote 111 On the other hand, France's emphasis on “one king, one faith, one law” developed into “divine right,” a synthesis of the Salic Law and the “most Christian” king's long-term independence from Rome into a “coherent and morally compelling system.” The Salic Law and “the community of which it was an emanation” thus became sacralized, while “the king's state … became an end in itself and a source of moral values.”Footnote 112

The WoR thus gave way to the religions of nationalism, which emphasized “the elevation of ‘the people’ … a people with a long past, now reborn to a new and authentic destiny as long as it adheres to God's will.”Footnote 113 While the emphasis on uniting these nations with a specific confession eventually tapered off, there still remains only a secondary difference between religion and nationalism, since “at the heart of both are the cult and the faith.”Footnote 114 Durkheim, for example, saw the French Revolution as birthing a new religious order, and equated the commemorations of national forbears who forged a “moral charter” to Christian celebrations of Christ.Footnote 115 Building on these sentiments, Hayes argues nationalism comprises religious sentimentality and ritual, as exemplified by national flags and anthems, commemorations of national heroes/events, and adherence to a national “theology” derived from “sacred” texts and past deeds.Footnote 116 Smith, meanwhile, elaborates on the beliefs and sentiments regarding the “sacred foundations” of nations to make sense of the “strength of national attachments.” This includes parallels between nationalism and traditional religions, including ideas of “chosenness,” attachment to a perceived “holy” land, and conceptions of the people as a sacred community. More generally, Smith takes nationalism as a “political religion surrogate,” with its object of concern being the “sacred—a sacred communion of the people.”Footnote 117 Underscoring this communion is a “cult of authenticity,” a form of holiness wherein that which is conceived as authentic to the nation—as derived from social and cultural traditions, heroic figures, and Golden Ages—is revered and held sacred.Footnote 118

Therefore, we can continue to see modern secular communities—and in particular nations—as constituted by shared faith in what their members hold sacred and are willing to sacrifice for,Footnote 119 enabling a sense of moral order and OS. Exploring how actors have historically contended with struggles over the sacred—and how such struggles can degrade into violence—thus allows us to develop our understanding of the recurrence of violence within, and between, modern communities (such as nations). The remainder of this article thus uses the WoR's rich historiography to explore how the interplay between the sacred, OS, and hermeneutics of morality influenced conflict and the broader implications this has for conceptualizing the sacred and OS in regard to secular politics and violence. Specifically, we find these relationships influenced the trajectory of conflict, framed the legitimation of acceptable settlements, and (re)constructed social order and authority.

Hermeneutics of Morality and the Trajectory of Violence in France

OS studies often explore the importance of national narratives, which offer an enduring sense of community,Footnote 120 and national signifiers, which offer a fantasy of homogeneity and stability.Footnote 121 However, we must avoid taking the nation as “no more than the sum of its cultural representations.”Footnote 122 Instead, we must maintain a “thick” view and appreciate the affective reality of communities (such as nations)Footnote 123—“the bonds of allegiance and belonging which so many people feel” and the “powerful and popular cultural resources and traditions … [that] endow them with a sense of tangible reality”Footnote 124 and which successful narratives draw on.Footnote 125 Turning to the WoR, we find the trajectory of conflict was greatly informed by the politics of interpreting faithful behavior, wherein Protestants and Catholics returned to sacred sources and reinterpreted social traditions to devise and debate legitimate solutions for refashioning moral order. Contrary to the assumptions of tradition rooted in modernization theory, as well as criticisms suggesting that OS studies have a status quo bias or foreclose space for ethical debate,Footnote 126 the WoR thus demonstrates how the quest for OS is interrelated with the dynamism and hermeneutics of morality.

Calling for the eradication of heretics, advocating coexistence, entering cross-confessional alliancesFootnote 127—these all represented different interpretations of how best to address the “moral questions at stake”Footnote 128 following the “difficult adjustment” to the emergence of competing confessions “for which little in the country's traditions prepared it.”Footnote 129 Of course, such interpretations did not occur in a vacuum; pre-existing aristocratic rivalries, systems of clientage, and socioeconomic tensions meant participants were navigating a “society long divided by social hierarchy”Footnote 130 and a political culture comprising a “constant interplay” between elite and popular politics.Footnote 131 These considerations thus intersected with the more fundamental anxieties that emerged over moral order, with the “most important question … the one that sparked the most intense passion and the most recurrent conflict on all sides” being over whether, and on what terms, the different confessions should coexist.Footnote 132 The determination of legitimate behavior in light of this central question greatly influenced the conflict's trajectory.

Initially, the Reformation sparked curiosity in France.Footnote 133 However, Protestantism's more radical thinking eventually prompted a backlash, with the Sorbonne condemning Luther and the Crown heavily repressing Protestants.Footnote 134 The continued advance of Protestantism, and the linking of confessional cleavages with rival nobles, subsequently heightened social unrest. As tensions flared, the regency government for Charles IX under Catherine de Medici drastically shifted policy to prioritize order, diminishing the influence of extreme positions on both sides while elevating moderates, including Protestants such as Gaspard de Coligny. Intent on preventing, and then ending, civil war, Catherine subsequently undertook three concerted efforts to instill coexistence: the edicts of January, Amboise, and Saint-Germain. Ultimately, these failed, given their incongruency with dominant interpretations of faithful behavior and inability to reduce tensions within a populace intent on safeguarding antithetical conceptions of the sacred or to curtail elite rivalries—and while nobles were often reluctant to harness the masses,Footnote 135 their continued recourse to war facilitated crowd violence. Accordingly, the edicts were interpreted by many as a source of angst and anomie.Footnote 136

To begin, the perceived potency of the Protestant moral threat was entwined with the emerging thinking of Protestant leaders.Footnote 137 In particular, the turn to iconoclasm, which sparked much Catholic outrage, was not “the implementation of some ‘off-the-peg’ doctrines” but a “gradually emerging logic of iconoclastic destruction that only made sense in the particular dynamic context that gave it force.”Footnote 138 Similarly, while some Protestants called for patiently enduring oppression and suggested the possibility of coexistence,Footnote 139 the most influential voices (such as Beza) stressed upholding the true faith—particularly given Calvinism's focus on social regulation.Footnote 140 Accordingly, many supported violence and the total elimination of Catholicism.Footnote 141 Meanwhile, the eventual turn from constitutional and legal arguments toward increasingly radical justifications for resistance, conceiving royal “authority as resting on contract and obligated to obey the divine will,”Footnote 142 augmented fears among Catholic nobles over “social and political order.”Footnote 143

Catholics, meanwhile, debated whether temporary coexistence was legitimate as a path to religious uniformity, or a harbinger of disorder and “new war and cruelty.”Footnote 144 Moderates justified edicts through biblical precedent and the need for loyalty to a king who could heal divisions.Footnote 145 At the same time, there was a turn to France's intellectual history, going back to Pierre du Chastel's opposition to the execution of heretics. More contemporary works by, for example, Michel de l'Hôpital subsequently pointed to the “unworkability of any ‘forcement de conscience’.”Footnote 146 Instead there was an effort to distinguish religious affairs, determined through Church councils, from temporal affairs, with the edicts devising “precise rules” for unity under the king.Footnote 147 Some moderates also tried to refashion the understanding of France. L'Hôpital stated in the lead-up to the Edict of January, “L'excommunié ne cesse pas d'estre citoyen,”Footnote 148 while commissioners under Charles established “civic reference points” as a new basis for unity.Footnote 149 Still, for most moderates, l'Hôpital included, coexistence was seen as “a temporary solution” until unification could be achievedFootnote 150—as a “mild but effective medicine” for the ills of society.Footnote 151 But opponents had the advantage of “France's most deeply rooted political myths, which linked the nation's existence to its historic success in combatting heresy.”Footnote 152 Many thus felt even temporary pluralism was immoral, let alone the Protestant demands that edicts should at least guarantee “religious freedom, public worship, and equal justice”—hence the widespread opposition to the Edict of Beaulieu, which came closest to these demands.Footnote 153

These dominant moral judgements among Catholics and Protestants, coupled with the posturing of elites, largely undermined the edicts. Starting with the 1562 Edict of January, Protestants continuously flaunted its restrictions,Footnote 154 while the legal recognition they gained was a “volte-face that most Catholics found difficult to swallow.”Footnote 155 Following a stalemate in the ensuing civil war, Catherine sought to restore peace with the 1563 Edict of Amboise. However, efforts to enforce the edict through commissioners, biconfessional courts, and a two-year royal tour of justice ultimately failed to alleviate widespread tensions,Footnote 156 particularly given the continued proliferation of Catholic confraternities intent on combatting heresy.Footnote 157 Coupled with the militant Guise's mounting influence in court, Protestant nobles opted for rebellion, and a period of protracted warfare took hold. The eventual result was the 1570 Edict of Saint-Germain.

Made possible by military exhaustion and reemergence of a moderate coalition at court, the edict appeased Protestants by authorizing worship in specific towns, offering legal recognition, and garrisoning four strategic fortified towns. Around this same time, Catherine finalized a marriage between her daughter and the Protestant Henry of Navarre. However, the edict ultimately failed to grapple with the fact that most Catholics remained adamant in “pursuing a new Jerusalem devoid of all infidels,” that many Catholic nobles were growing perturbed by Protestant rhetoric challenging sacral monarchy, and that people's exposure to war was leading the “religious zeal and piety of the masses … to display itself more openly,” resulting in further instances of crowd violence.Footnote 158

In addition to being perceived as illegitimate, the edicts often hindered participants from implementing stable mechanisms for restoring and maintaining moral order. Not only did fluctuation between edicts leave the legal place of Protestants unpredictable, heightening anxiety,Footnote 159 but they also became “a provocation, a cause and a pretext for the violence” they were intended to prevent,Footnote 160 facilitating hostile interactions associated with each side's efforts to “restore their imagined community.”Footnote 161 For Catholics, it was this failure to establish clear religious borders and hierarchy that tended to result in Protestants becoming “transformed from unwanted though generally harmless irritants … to dangerous pollutants that threatened civil order.”Footnote 162

Overall, many Protestants and Catholics interpreted the edicts as deepening anomie and ontological insecurity—as jettisoning “any sense of being carefree,” facilitating the “erosion of community,” and transforming “areas traditionally reserved for the reproduction of life” into zones of war.Footnote 163 These tensions came to a head during the St. Bartholomew's Day massacre, when a more limited effort to assassinate the Protestant leadership devolved into Catholics ritualistically killing Protestants throughout Paris and in cities where Protestants were still a sizeable minority.Footnote 164 Those Protestants who opted to remain subsequently began to openly oppose the Crown, reinforcing Catholic worries over “the traditional political and social order.”Footnote 165

However, while the breadth of this violence further polarized society, it also led many, repulsed by the savagery, to finally view temporary coexistence as morally tolerable. Crowd violence subsequently fell, given this guilt and the fact that confessional minorities had become regionally “less politically threatening” on both sides.Footnote 166 These shifts coincided with growing discontent with royal authority and taxation. A small group of malcontent Catholic nobles, eventually led by the king's brother François, then formed an interim alliance with Protestants to solidify coexistence and address shared “grievances about royal misgovernment,” excessive taxation, and the power of the Estates-General.Footnote 167 The Crown's weak position forced it to temporarily acquiesce with the Edict of Beaulieu, which included extensive Protestant concessions while rewarding François with the title Duke of Anjou.Footnote 168 While the ensuing Estates-General saw most Catholic representatives and the wider populace denounce Beaulieu, it also revealed an increasing gulf between moderate Catholics opposed to continued war and those wishing “to exterminate heresy entirely.”Footnote 169 However, even among the latter, many were reluctant to provide the necessary funds for war—and indeed a series of cross-confessional peasant riots erupted, spurred on by the Crown's reduced authority and long-standing socioeconomic concerns that had become compounded by constant warfare.Footnote 170

These divisions took on further dimensions in 1584, when François's death left the Protestant Henry of Navarre heir to Henry III, compounding Catholic anxiety over moral order. The eventual result was civil war between a Catholic League, emphasizing the Law of Catholicity, and the politiques, who, while agreeing to Catholicity, prioritized the Salic Law and royal authority. The designation politique, a derogatory term implying that they were “completely without religion,”Footnote 171 was thus disingenuous. Moderates supported unification and sacral monarchy—merely advising, in the words of one prominent politique, “sufferance of those of the new opinion for a short time.”Footnote 172 Where they differed was over Henry's “susceptibility to conversion” and later the sincerity of his conversion.Footnote 173 The emergence of inter-Catholic war and cross-confessional alliance between politiques and Navarre (explored later in the article) must be examined in the context of these increasingly hostile moral debates.Footnote 174 Accordingly, when the moral threat posed by Henry IV receded following his conversation in 1593 and absolution in 1595, coupled with efforts to demonstrate that “the body politic had been restored to the body of Christ,”Footnote 175 most Catholics pledged fealty. With this support in hand, Henry set about bringing Protestants into the fold, the result being the Edict of Nantes—the ostensible end of the French WoR.

Therefore, to better appreciate how actors reason, we must take seriously the affective power of the sacred while simultaneously recognizing the hermeneutics of morality. Accordingly, a central feature of the WoR was the emergence of conflicting conceptions regarding “what was sacred and what was polluting, aggressively expressed in public spaces.”Footnote 176 How actors, driven by a desire for OS, (re)interpreted faithful behavior following these challenges—while simultaneously navigating socioeconomic tensions and concerns over social/political standing—was thus critical to the conflict's trajectory. Specifically, underlying the edicts, civil wars, and crowd violence was an ongoing and dynamic moral debate over the sacrifices required to stave off anomie and refashion moral order—processes that informed understandings of, and responses to, perceived moral threats.

Social Traditions in Conflict-Coexistence: The Edict of Nantes

In taking seriously the dynamism of moral order, we find that adherents of different traditions and conceptions of the sacred are not predestined to violence—there are always choices to be made.Footnote 177 During the WoR, violence was periodically avoided as Catholics successfully devised alternative mechanisms for refashioning moral order. In Tours, for example, once Protestants were “reduced to political impotence” they were “protected by a municipality determined to prove how firmly they were in control of events.”Footnote 178 Similarly, local leaders in Dijon avoided violence by enforcing Protestants’ second-class status and coercing certifications of conversion—not regarding theology, but promises “to ‘vivre catholicquement’,” indicating that the aim was to maintain “the unity of the Catholic community in practice and behavior … [and] the social and political order.”Footnote 179 This raises additional considerations regarding the implications of OS for conflict resolution.

OS studies often examine how conflict resolution, by disrupting constructed objects of fear that help provide answers to existential questions, generates an ambiguity that unsettles “previously taken-for-granted self-understandings about being and identity.”Footnote 180 The corresponding anxiety can generate the impetus required for the Self-Other reconstruction necessary for peace, but also lead to re-securitizing the Other. While anxiety is an important factor, greater focus needs to be placed on the sacredFootnote 181—on how the choices that are perceived as “legitimate” and that garner support are interrelated with the moral order participants are embedded in. As we have seen, the various edicts struggled to gain legitimacy within the existing social traditions of France and often exacerbated perceived threats to the sacred. Therefore, so long as one side feels that what it holds sacred is imperiled and they are able to try to oppose this through various means, settlements will be hard to implement.Footnote 182 Turning to the Edict of Nantes allows us to further explore these dynamics.

As we do this we must recognize that the participants were focused not on religious tolerance, which contemporaries associated with “being subjected to some evil,” but on legal permission.Footnote 183 Importantly, this permission became feasible because Nantes included provisions making it morally tolerable to at least the majority. Unfortunately, these provisions also made it unstable because they merely provided mechanisms for managing relations until one side could cement their conception of moral order. Louis XIV's eventual revocation thus represented more a change in the balance of power than a wholesale shift in attitude.Footnote 184

To begin, the edict was palatable to many Catholics because it clearly delineated Protestants as second-class citizens. While Protestants’ relative strength mandated the inclusion of contentious concessions,Footnote 185 the edict “underscored the Catholicity of the crown and the realm,” the universal right to Catholic worship, and observance of certain Catholic regulations and ecclesiastical tithes, all while restricting Protestant worship.Footnote 186 Protestant support, on the other hand, derived from the inclusion of two temporary brevets granting partial military and political independence. However, because the edict also contradicted these concessions in alluding to religious unity, most saw it “as transitory.”Footnote 187 Accordingly, Nantes represented enough Catholics accepting temporary coexistence, with Henry expecting reunification by 1606. It was this support, coupled with the peasantry's desire for peace and the fact many Protestants were encouraged by (provisional) guarantees of civil rights, security, and justice, that allowed the agreement to work temporarily,Footnote 188 with each side able to “assert its own identity materially … and liturgically.”Footnote 189 Therefore, what distinguished Nantes was its ability to present Catholics a morally justifiable settlement; Catholic support was always premised on accommodating “one faith, one king, one law.”Footnote 190

However, notwithstanding the spectrum of views on how much peace should be prioritized, and despite greater cross-confessional interactions, coexistence remained a “veneer.” While it introduced mechanisms for managing moral threats, Nantes failed to address the continued antithetical conceptions of moral order and the sacred, with most people rejecting coexistence as an appropriate long-term model for organizing society.Footnote 191 The result was a coexistence of intolerance,Footnote 192 with hard-liners working to reinforce boundaries and society maintaining a “strong tendency toward group endogamy,” allowing segregation to proliferate.Footnote 193 At the same time, royal dedication to the Gallican principle slowly eroded the concessions enabling Protestant support. While Henry's murder in 1610 increased Protestant anxiety, we must appreciate that both Henry and his successor, Louis XIII, worked toward confessional unification, with growth in the Crown's relative power enabling the enforcement of moral order by whittling away Protestant rights. When Protestants called for a rival government following Louis's campaign to restore Catholic worship in Béarn, Louis affirmed the actual Edict of Nantes by eliminating Protestant political and military resistance, underscoring “Catholic concord and unity” and leaving Protestants “heretics in a Catholic world.”Footnote 194

Therefore, when conceptualizing the implications of OS within peace settlements, we should consider the vital role of concerns over moral order in delineating relative support and perceived legitimacy. This is not to endorse subjugating morally threatening others—the demarcation of Protestants as second-class citizens was “disturbing and depressing.”Footnote 195 Instead, we can turn to Davis's call to “think less about pacifying ‘deviants’ and more about changing the central values.”Footnote 196 Of course, such processes face numerous hurdles—specifically how to facilitate such change. One possibility is that participants emphasize different groupings; Migault's emphasis on local community, for example, enabled peaceful relations. Yet such examples remained the minority, suggesting their difficulty.Footnote 197 A second possibility is that prolonged coexistence slowly changes central values.Footnote 198 However, coexistence must, in the first instance, be perceived as moral; for example, prevailing social traditions in the Low Countries facilitated more widespread coexistence than in France.Footnote 199 Accordingly, peace settlements must first strive to resonate with prevailing morals and values interrelated with the sacred. Meanwhile, the prolonged nature of value change provides opportunity for disruptive elements to intervene, or exploit changes in relative power, particularly when there is not a neutral arbitratorFootnote 200—hence Louis XIV's eventual revocation of Nantes due to diplomatic rationale and enduring hostility to pluralism.Footnote 201

Still, we need not adopt the pessimism of Huntington's clash thesis. Instead, it is by considering the OS motivation of participants to act faithfully within/toward a moral order that “legitimate” solutions might be developed. Therefore, by taking seriously concerns over the sacred—for example, by prioritizing symbolic gesturesFootnote 202 and treating the “language, culture, or religious vocabulary” of participants “as resources for a creative process”Footnote 203—we might develop the “political space in which a friend/enemy relationship … transform[s] into one of legitimate adversaries.”Footnote 204 Likewise, abstracting from Hassner's work on sacred space, we can emphasize how “religious” leaders “capable of shaping and reshaping the meaning, value, and parameters of sacred places can ameliorate or even resolve disputes.”Footnote 205 This, in turn, leads into questions around who is perceived as a “legitimate representative” of the sacred,Footnote 206 and the interrelationship between social hierarchies and interpretations of the sacred.

(Re)Constructing Authority in France

In thinking about the intersection of OS and authority, it helps to tun to Zarakol's exploration of the historical contingency of the modern arrangement of states as primary OS providers, and how “sovereignty itself cannot be thought of as separate from such an institutional monopolization of the provision” of OS. During the Axial Age, for example, religious institutions were the main OS providers, with political authority “subservient or irrelevant to religious authority.”Footnote 207 Building on these insights, we can think about power and authority as interrelated with questions of the sacred and moral order—as predicated on being taken as a legitimate defender and arbitrator of the sacred. This, in turn, substantiates works examining political authority as the result of “constant negotiation, definition, delimitation, and categorization.”Footnote 208 Accordingly, we find that the French struggles over the sacred were inherently linked to power, order, and legitimacy: that conceptions of the sacred “legitimated political authority, justified social hierarchies, and facilitated social order by establishing codes of right and wrong.”Footnote 209 To this end, hierarchies in France influenced, and were influenced by, interpretations of the sacred and moral order.

Two aspects emerge regarding the former. The first pertains to power relations within a community and how certain individuals/institutions are perceived as having (legitimate) authority over what acting morally entails—or who “can claim to speak in God's name in a given time and place.”Footnote 210 The Sorbonne, for example, was influential in interpreting the Protestant “threat” and, as we will see, propagating a Catholic cultural (and political) revolution. Likewise, Gallicanism provided the Crown a powerful allure that many were hesitant to defy. We must also appreciate that interpretation of moral threats often reinforced existing hierarchies, a sentiment exemplified by how cross-confessional peasant riots were, like Protestantism, described as “threats to proper order under a Gallican monarchy.”Footnote 211

The second aspect pertains to the relative power disparity between communities, which can influence perceived threats (for example, violence often erupted when “heretics” threatened political and judicial control)Footnote 212 and opportunities. For example, Protestants’ diminished power influenced reactions to Catholic aggression in the run up to the revocation of Nantes.Footnote 213 While some advocated rebellion, the dominant discourse emphasized the New Testament and Protestantism as “a peaceful and rational Christian tradition, defending an evangelical morality,” resulting in calls for “pan-Christian tolerance based on making clear distinctions between ecclesiastical and civil structures” and the need to love God and one's neighbor.Footnote 214

Meanwhile, by creatively returning to social traditions, participants were often revising existing structures.Footnote 215 This is most evident in Protestants’ open challenge to the existing social order, and later the monarchy, when they drew on traditions of the Franks and Gauls to draft a republican constitution. However, Catholic efforts to revitalize moral order also had significant implications, as demonstrated by events surrounding the Catholic League. Traditionally, there has been a focus on the political and socioeconomic motivations of the League, which comprised an aristocratic band of nobles loyal to Guise and a more independent band of urban notables. Certainly, through the League, the Guise opposed tax increases, strengthened their position, and pursued “political machinations aimed against Henry III and Henry of Navarre.” Likewise, urban notables used the League to press for political and social revolution—coming into tension with the more aristocratic strand. These various dimensions, however, cannot be disentangled from more fundamental concerns over the sacred: that this was a “Holy Union” driven, and held intact, by a mission to maintain a Catholic Crown and the purity of France.Footnote 216

Specifically, the emergence of, and support for, the League was interrelated with a growing sense of “religious duty” to enact reforms informed by a Tridentine Reformation–inspired cultural revolution. This stemmed from concerns over rampant corruption, that the royal court was becoming “a moral sink,” and that “institutions of political society” were failing in their intended task: “to combat the evil in man, remove temptations, punish and encourage, show the way to virtue.”Footnote 217 Magistrates thus began adopting measures to instill moral discipline in society, while a new wave of Sorbonne preachers turned “reformism into revolt” against “immoral” leadership.Footnote 218 This constructed an “alluring image of the League as ‘bon François’ and ‘bon Catholique’.”Footnote 219 Accordingly, what provided, for example, the League's “revolutionary movement credibility” was widespread support for its “opposition to Protestantism and its announced intention of keeping the monarchy Catholic” and the conveyance “of post-Tridentine Catholic piety.”Footnote 220 This helped demarcate the “alleged ethical purity of League officers and the alleged selfishness and corruption of royalists”Footnote 221—a division solidified when Henry, seeking to reassert royal authority, had the Guise brothers assassinated and leaders of the Paris League arrested. The result was bourgeoning support for the League and more expansive challenges to the Crown.Footnote 222 Royalists were forced into an alliance with Navarre—one “wholly favourable to the Protestant cause”Footnote 223—while League preachers justified war against the Crown by combining Augustine's “just war” with a theory of divine election of nobles.Footnote 224

Henry III's assassination in August 1589 brough the crisis to a head, presenting Catholics a “searing question of conscience.”Footnote 225 Each side subsequently appealed “to a deeply ingrained sense of sacred community” as they debated just “what it meant to be ‘bon François Catholique’”: abiding the Salic Law or Catholicity. Politiques, while intent on the triumph of Gallicanism and Henry IV's conversion, deployed historical and legal arguments to argue that only royal obedience “could lay the groundwork for a general religious reconciliation.” Leaguers meanwhile remained united in their drive to “defend the monarchy and church from the twin perils of heresy and moral corruption.” Henry's eventual conversion thus removed the primary obstacle for moderate Leaguers, who wanted to reaffirm a strong monarchy, to pledge fealty,Footnote 226 while his subsequent absolution brought most hard-liners around.

Therefore, moral contestation between Leaguers and politiques was, by its very nature, interrelated with struggles over power, specifically the moral obligations that underpin configurations of authority, such as the Crown, aristocracy, or clergy. Moreover, (re)interpretations of the sacred and morality helped transform wider social structures, with debates over bon François Catholique resulting in people “slowly redefining and then reaffirming what they thought to be the traditional order of a society.” There was thus a return to the “moral bases” of the Crown's authority, and a sense that the “moral freins inherent in French kingship had to be re-established.”Footnote 227 In doing so, many advocated “wholesale reform and rejuvenation of all of French society through an infusion of moral purpose and integrity in its vital institutions.”Footnote 228 Likewise, Catholic reclamation of the landscape following Nantes was not “merely an attempt to restore what had been lost, but to sacralize and confessionalize the landscape,” generating “new rituals and perceptions of the sacred.”Footnote 229 In Orleans, for example, Catholics started venerating those who had fallen upholding the faith and appropriated elements of the city's history, with Jeanne d'Arc taking on a new “quasi sacred role.”Footnote 230 The Catholic Reformation engendered even more dramatic changes, as exemplified by seventeenth-century missions that purposively disrupted social life to prompt “deep emotional reactions” and alter how Catholics “thought and acted.”Footnote 231

Therefore, focusing on the pursuit of OS as interrelated with moral order allows us to appreciate how it is also inherently entwined with questions of power and hierarchy. As seen during the WoR, and exemplified by the Catholic League, participants were struggling “over power and control, as well as over meaning, doctrine, and definitions of the body social,” with violence often bestowing “novel roles, power, or status.”Footnote 232 In other words, the OS drive to refashion moral order was intrinsically linked with (re)establishing hierarchies of power. These events further demonstrate how change can emerge in ways perceived unthreatening to OS,Footnote 233 with many experiencing, for example, the Catholic Reformation as “ensuring the proper social and moral order.”Footnote 234

Conclusion: Political Order and Raison d’État

This article has pushed back against core assumptions within IR rooted in narratives distinguishing the “irrationality” of religious violence from modern, pragmatic, secular politics. I have argued that we are better served by examining how both premodern “religious” and modern “secular” politics are intrinsically linked to the interplay between the sacred, OS, and the hermeneutics of morality—particularly given the continued prevalence of civil/political religions and nationalism. In other words, we are better served by thinking of the WoR as merely one instance of the more perennial struggles over the sacred—as one in a series of crucibles from which can emerge misery and violence, but also new hope and ways of being. Exploring how participants navigated such struggles during the WoR is thus of great relevance to our more general understanding of the continued role of the sacred in politics and violence. Accordingly, we have seen that how participants interpreted faithful behavior—how they creatively returned to a moral order interrelated with the sacred—greatly influenced the conflict's trajectory, the perceived legitimacy of settlements, and the (re)construction of social structures and authority.

Building on these insights, we can conclude by examining how, more broadly, the perennial struggles over the sacred—the interplay between the sacred, OS, and the hermeneutics of morality—account for the dynamism of raison d’état: the relationship between organized violence and political order. Specifically, our understanding of raison d’état is advanced by starting with the conceptions of the sacred that constitute communities, legitimize authority, and provide members with meaning and OS. The sacred is thus the hinge of domestic and international politics, with the former informed by varying degrees of competition over interpretations of moral order and the latter informed by how the beliefs of the community intersect with international power structures and the beliefs and actions of others. The threat of anomie, and of the legitimation of violence, resides at both levels; domestic debates can degrade into antithetical interpretations of moral order, and external relations can fundamentally challenge the beliefs of a people.

This helps unpack the recognition within the tradition of raison d’état that political orders require a “consolidation of coercive, economic, and symbolic power and violence” and that symbolic logics often do not “conform to the same logic as one based on material fear and coercion.” The dilemma of politics for classical realists was thus an appreciation that political orders bereft of ultimate values become “hollowed out”Footnote 235 and that pure realism lacks four things essential to “effective political thinking: a finite goal, an emotional appeal, a right of moral judgment and a ground for action.”Footnote 236 Building on these insights, we can see decisions around domestic/foreign policy as partially related to the sacrifices actors feel are required to safeguard conceptions of the sacred which (re)constitute their political order. The implication is that the concerns of raison d’état are inseparable from a set of social traditions entwined with the sacred.Footnote 237 The policies of Cardinal Richelieu, for example, were informed by his place within a “social caste that had drawn much of its raison d’être from the martial luster of foreign ventures” and general societal faith in Gallicanism and divine absolutism, the French as a “chosen people,” and France as an exceptional nation. The result was a “pragmatic, yet religiously inflected, foreign policy ethos” defended in reference to “recovering France's ‘natural’ primacy on the continent.”Footnote 238

Therefore, as Aron asked, “What life does not serve a higher goal? What good is security accompanied by mediocrity?”Footnote 239 The understanding of this goal, however, is subject to the hermeneutics of morality and the ongoing revitalization of the sacred. Accordingly, we cannot assume a priori that “religion” will manifest in the type of violent nationalism feared by Morgenthau—resulting in pragmatism or barbarism. Hayes, for example, notes that nationalists, like medieval Christians, distinguish between types of unbelievers, with heretics, “fellow countrymen who have lapsed from the pure faith,” often treated more harshly than “infidels” and “pagans”—unnaturalized immigrants and “inhabitants of foreign countries.”Footnote 240 Yet violence in the face of heretics or pagans/infidels is not predestined—such encounters take numerous forms.Footnote 241

This helps us understand some of the potential dangers accompanying the increasing moral polarization within many societies.Footnote 242 Davis, for example, draws parallels between the WoR and unrest in North America in the 1960s and 1970s, or more extreme violence, such as Kristallnacht.Footnote 243 The question then is what sacrifices actors might feel compelled to make to offset perceived moral threats and moral disorder—for example, storming the US Capitol. Similar concerns arise regarding the progressive ideological contestation within the international system.Footnote 244 While actors during the WoR predominantly focused on threats of pollution within their communities, concerns over moral order also resulted in strong reactions to heresy close to one's border,Footnote 245 competing models of international society,Footnote 246 and constrained alliances.Footnote 247 We find similar considerations regarding the Cold War, which for Morgenthau and Aron was “a combination of traditional power politics and ideological competition.”Footnote 248 Specifically, as Cesa summarizes, Aron felt a negotiated settlement on the former was impossible given the latter,Footnote 249 hence his argument for envisioning the international system in terms of power (bipolar or multipolar) and values/ideals (homogeneous or heterogeneous).Footnote 250 Therefore, when powerful “pagans and infidels” are seen as hindering efforts to act in accordance with “the good,” or as promoting or expanding formations of international society premised on values incongruent with one's own,Footnote 251 the potential for moral threats to intercede in decision making becomes particularly acute.

However, despite these current trends, appreciating the hermeneutics of morality and the dynamism of tradition allows us to avoid becoming overly pessimistic—there is always opportunity for hope and change. Take the Soviet debates over ideological reforms that facilitated peace with the West. While the Soviets originally imitated “the spirit of the Crusades” in seeking to “spread the New Faith,” Gorbachev's “counterreformation” began prioritizing Finlandization and incorporating “values created against the will of” the established orthodoxy.Footnote 252 While certainly impacted by material considerations, these values were the result of long-term intellectual (“theological”) evolution, with advocates endowing with “normative significance” ideas partially codified during détente.Footnote 253 These changes were successfully legitimated by “appealing to norms that resonated in the Soviet political culture”Footnote 254 and remaining faithful to a more fundamental understanding of Russia as the center of international political leadership.Footnote 255 On the other hand, in explaining the resurgence of conflict between Russia and the West it helps to examine the struggle between liberals and traditionalists within the post-Soviet “spiritual vacuum,” with the latter ascending since 2000 and embracing values that are taken, particularly by Putin, as threatened by the West.Footnote 256

To better understand how actors reason, and to develop more “legitimate” policies and agreements, policymakers should thus remain attuned to how raison d’état is understood in relation to a dynamic set of social traditions interrelated with the sacred. Consider Serbia–Kosovo. Throughout the 1980s, as communism waned, Serbians engaged in processes of national revival, tapping into social traditions interrelated with long-held myths of Kosovo as the sacred land of Serbia. Accordingly, Serbians focused on enforcing their control over Kosovo through military force, and later through diplomatic and legal tactics. The independence of Kosovo subsequently ignited a moral debate; while many maintained hard-line positions, new interpretations emerged legitimating the relinquishment of Serbia's physical control. However, the continued sacred status of Kosovo has thus far stymied the legitimacy of recognizing Kosovo's independence—despite political costs.Footnote 257 Similarly, conflict in Northern Ireland was interrelated with competing cultural religions, comprising their “own sacred events and symbols, their own fraternal orders, and their own versions of both the past and the future.”Footnote 258 However, it was by devising new, creative ways to incorporate these rival social traditions and conceptions of community, and by finding a way for “political leaders to govern together without compromising the basic principles of their constitutional identities,” that progress was made toward peace.Footnote 259

Therefore, the ability to creatively appeal to the OS-inspired motivation of actors to remain faithful within/toward their conceptions of the sacred will go some way in charting how well we navigate the increasingly hot crucible of moral polarization and ideological rivalry. To this end, we must take heart—and take care—in recognizing that such hurdles are not unique. International politics is a story of trying to navigate perennial struggles over the sacred, and while this has resulted in bloodshed, it has also resulted in creativity and hope.

Acknowledgments

I am indebted to Scott Thomas, whose earlier writings helped construct the theoretical space that made this article possible and who proved to be an invaluable sounding board during the construction of my arguments. Likewise, I would like to thank Gregorio Bettiza for reading earlier drafts of this article. Finally, I am grateful to the editorial board of International Organization, as well as the two anonymous reviewers, whose support and critical engagement greatly improved the article.

Footnotes

4. Thomas Reference Thomas2005, 54.

6. Davis Reference Davis1973, 53–54; see also Desan Reference Desan and Hunt1989, 56.

9. A presumption that sanitizes its “imperial hierarchical formations” (de Carvalho, Leira, and Hobson Reference de Carvalho, Leira and Hobson2011, 756) and, by assuming Europe bequeathed “civilised and rational institutions to the inferior Eastern societies” (Costa Lopez et al. Reference Costa Lopez, De Carvalho, Latham, Zarakol, Bartelson and Holm2018, 507–508) obscures forms of sovereignty in premodern, non-Western, contexts.

10. Holt Reference Holt1993, 534.

11. Wagner Reference Wagner2007, x.

12. Cavanaugh Reference Cavanaugh2009, 125–30.

13. Asad Reference Asad1993, 40–41.

14. Thomas Reference Thomas2005, 22–23.

15. Connolly Reference Connolly1999, 21; Hurd Reference Hurd2008, 14.

17. Cavanaugh Reference Cavanaugh2009, chap. 4; Costa Lopez et al. Reference Costa Lopez, De Carvalho, Latham, Zarakol, Bartelson and Holm2018, 497–98, 506–508.

18. Casanova Reference Casanova1994, 7, 13.

19. Casanova Reference Casanova1994, 211; Cavanaugh Reference Cavanaugh2009, chap. 3.

20. On variants of secularism aligning more with Huntington's clash thesis, see Hurd Reference Hurd2008, 15–16.

22. Schwarz and Lynch Reference Schwarz and Lynch2016.

23. Lovin Reference Lovin, Carlson and Owens2003,157–58; Williams Reference Williams2010, 311–12.

24. Lynch Reference Lynch2000, 742; Thomas Reference Thomas2005, 21.

25. Casanova Reference Casanova1994, 16–17; Farrands and Wrightson Reference Farrands and Wrightson2000, 35; Hurd Reference Hurd and Snyder2011, 65–66.

26. Connolly Reference Connolly1999, 5, 20.

28. Sandal and Fox Reference Sandal and Fox2013, chap. 1; see also Philpott Reference Philpott2009.

30. Mavelli Reference Mavelli2011, 178; Williams Reference Williams1998.

32. Thomas Reference Thomas2005, 68, 62; see also Philpott Reference Philpott2002, 80.

33. Hutchinson and Bleiker Reference Hutchison and Bleiker2014.

34. Casanova Reference Casanova1994, 37.

35. Hutchison and Bleiker Reference Hutchison and Bleiker2014, 49.

38. Morgenthau Reference Morgenthau1947, 10; Niebuhr Reference Niebuhr1932, 214.

39. Ross Reference Ross2013, 280–81.

40. Morgenthau Reference Morgenthau1947, 9–10.

41. Niebuhr, cited in Farrands and Wrightson Reference Farrands and Wrightson2000, 43.

42. Morgenthau Reference Morgenthau1960, 7.

43. Morgenthau Reference Morgenthau1949, 87.

44. Ross Reference Ross2013, 285.

45. Niebuhr Reference Niebuhr1932, 174; Philpott Reference Philpott2002, 78, 80.

46. Kinnvall and Mitzen Reference Kinnvall and Mitzen2020, 246.

53. Zarakol Reference Zarakol2017, 50.

57. Mellor Reference Mellor1998, 92–93.

58. Joas Reference Joas2016, 27–28.

59. Durkheim Reference Durkheim and Fields1995, 34, 364. On larger discussions around whether the sacred emerges from violence, see Heinämäki Reference Heinämäki2015.

60. Mellor Reference Mellor2002, 18–19.

62. Durkheim Reference Durkheim and Fields1995, 211, 213, 427.

63. Durkheim Reference Durkheim and Fields1995, 421, 489.

64. Kubálková Reference Kubálková2000, 685.

65. From “questioning the status quo, to revivals, renewals, and revolutions.” Bolton Reference Bolton2023, 236.

66. Bolton Reference Bolton2023, 247–249; Nexon Reference Nexon and Snyder2011, 157–58.

67. Meštrović and Brown Reference Meštrović and Brown1985, 84; Meštrović and Lorenzo Reference Meštrović and Lorenzo2008, 183.

68. Meštrović Reference Meštrović1985, 126–27; Meštrović and Brown Reference Meštrović and Brown1985, 81–83.

69. Meštrović and Lorenzo Reference Meštrović and Lorenzo2008, 180.

70. Hassner Reference Hassner2011, 29.

71. Bettiza, Bolton, and Lewis Reference Bettiza, Bolton and Lewis2023; Bolton Reference Bolton2023.

72. Durkheim Reference Durkheim and Fields1995, 422–23, 425.

73. Gentile Reference Gentile2005, 24.

75. Benedict Reference Benedict2012, 164.

77. Diefendorf Reference Diefendorf2017a, 384.

78. Smith Reference Smith2008, 98–99.

81. Greenfield Reference Greenfield1993, 95.

82. Smith Reference Smith2008, 100–101.

83. Holt Reference Holt1993, 539.

84. Greenfield Reference Greenfield1993, 102.

86. Roberts Reference Roberts2007b, 298; Turchetti Reference Turchetti1991.

88. Diefendorf Reference Diefendorf1991, 28–48; Holt Reference Holt2005, 18.

89. Reinburg, Reference Reinburg1992, 531–33.

90. Diefendorf Reference Diefendorf2012, 35; Turchetti Reference Turchetti1991.

92. Diefendorf Reference Diefendorf2012, 37–38.

94. Diefendorf Reference Diefendorf2012, 40, 42; Greengrass Reference Greengrass, Levene and Roberts1999, 71–72.

95. Foa Reference Foa2006, 373, 380–82.

97. Cavanaugh Reference Cavanaugh2009, 119, 158–60. For a contrary view, see Benedict Reference Benedict, Palaver, Rudolph and Regensburger2016.

98. Cavanaugh Reference Cavanaugh2014, 490, 497.

99. Durkheim Reference Durkheim and Fields1995, 208, 349–50.

101. For a discussion, see Bolton Reference Bolton2023, 244–45.

102. Cavanaugh Reference Cavanaugh2009, 177.

103. Cavanaugh Reference Cavanaugh2009, 174–78.

104. Both of which “consecrate ‘a collective entity,’ formalise a ‘code of commandments,’ consider their members a ‘community of the elect’ … and institute a ‘political liturgy’ which represents a ‘sacred history’.” Gentile Reference Gentile2005, 30.

106. Smith Reference Smith2000, 811.

107. Hirschi Reference Hirschi2012, 85; Smith Reference Smith2008, 116.

108. Cavanaugh Reference Cavanaugh2009, 175; Smith Reference Smith2005, 410.

110. Smith Reference Smith2005, 409–410.

111. Smith Reference Smith2008, 125–27, 129.

112. Greenfield Reference Greenfield1993, 111–15, 118; Harding Reference Harding1981, 409.

113. Smith Reference Smith2005, 410.

114. Smith Reference Smith2003, 28.

115. Durkheim Reference Durkheim and Fields1995, 215–16, 429.

116. Hayes Reference Hayes1926, 106–110.

117. Smith Reference Smith2003, 4–5, 17–18, Reference Smith2005, 412–14.

118. Smith Reference Smith2003, 32–33, 38, 66.

119. Cavanaugh Reference Cavanaugh2009, 175–76.

122. Smith Reference Smith1998, 137.

123. Bolton Reference Bolton2023, 240–41.

124. Smith Reference Smith1998, 137.

125. Kinnvall Reference Kinnvall2018, 533.

127. Cavanaugh Reference Cavanaugh2009, 144–47.

130. Holt Reference Holt2005, 51; see also Diefendorf Reference Diefendorf2014.

131. Carroll Reference Carroll1995, 125.

133. Nicholls Reference Nicholls1996, 183–86.

134. Knecht Reference Knecht1982, 252.

135. The influential Guise family, for example, initially preferred to rely on “traditional conventions of court politics.” Carroll Reference Carroll1995.

136. On this angst, see Diefendorf Reference Diefendorf2012, 46–47; Foa Reference Foa2004.

140. Holt Reference Holt2005, 23.

141. Benedict Reference Benedict and Grell2009, 68, 70, 92.

143. Holt Reference Holt2005, 79.

144. Roberts Reference Roberts2007a, 150–53, Reference Roberts2007b, 307.

145. Roberts Reference Roberts2007b, 299.

146. Benedict Reference Benedict and Grell2009, 68–69.

149. Foa Reference Foa2004, 267.

150. Roberts Reference Roberts2012, 77.

151. Roberts Reference Roberts2007a, 163.

152. Benedict Reference Benedict and Grell2009, 92; see also Pollmann Reference Pollmann2006, 112.

154. For example, Diefendorf Reference Diefendorf1991; Holt Reference Holt2012, 63.

155. Holt Reference Holt2005, 47–48.

157. Pollmann Reference Pollmann2006, 96–97; Roberts Reference Roberts2007a, 154.

158. Holt Reference Holt2005, 72, 74.

159. Holt Reference Holt2012, 71.

160. Roberts Reference Roberts2012, 77.

161. Diefendorf Reference Diefendorf2012, 34; see also Foa Reference Foa2006, 378–79, 383.

162. Holt Reference Holt2012, 54

163. Foa Reference Foa2017, 428–29, 430–31.

164. On these events, see Davis Reference Davis1973; Diefendorf Reference Diefendorf1991.

165. Holt Reference Holt2005, 100.

168. Holt Reference Holt2005, 107.

169. Diefendorf Reference Diefendorf2014, 559–60; see also Holt Reference Holt2005.

170. Holt Reference Holt2005, 113

171. Beame Reference Beame1993, 355, 379.

172. Holt Reference Holt2005, 128–29.

173. Wolfe Reference Wolfe1987, 293.

174. For an overview, see Venard Reference Venard, Benedict, Marnef, van Nierop and Venard1999, 146–47.

175. Holt Reference Holt2005, 160, 163.

177. Appleby Reference Appleby2000.

178. Nicholls Reference Nicholls1994, 32.

179. Holt Reference Holt2012, 68–70.

180. Rumelili Reference Rumelili2015, 16.

182. Hassner Reference Hassner2011, 30–31.

183. Benedict Reference Benedict and Grell2009, 67; see also Gold Reference Gold1988, 7; Kaplan Reference Kaplan2010, 8–9.

184. Gold Reference Gold1988, 6; Luria Reference Luria2005, 8; Turchetti Reference Turchetti1991, 22–24.

185. Sutherland Reference Sutherland and Gold1988, 31–33.

186. Holt Reference Holt2005, 168; Luria Reference Luria2005, 5–6.

187. Sutherland, Reference Sutherland and Gold1988, 33–34, 28 n2.

188. Benedict Reference Benedict and Grell2009, 83; Holt Reference Holt2005, 150, 172–73.

189. Lualdi Reference Lualdi2004, 733.

190. Holt Reference Holt2005, 198.

191. Diefendorf Reference Diefendorf2017a, 385; Marr Reference Marr2017, 448. On peaceful relations, see Hanlon Reference Hanlon1993.

192. Benedict Reference Benedict2007, 250. For exceptions, see Konnert Reference Konnert1989.

193. Diefendorf Reference Diefendorf2017b, 75; see also Benedict Reference Benedict and Grell2009, 87, 91; Lualdi Reference Lualdi2004, 722.

194. Holt Reference Holt2005, 192; For discussion, see Luria Reference Luria2005, 309–10, 317; Sutherland Reference Sutherland and Gold1988, 29–30, 41–43, 48.

195. Holt Reference Holt2012, 72.

196. Davis Reference Davis1973, 91.

197. Luria Reference Luria2005, 314–15.

200. Luria Reference Luria2005, 316.

201. Benedict Reference Benedict and Grell2009, 82–83; Diefendorf Reference Diefendorf2017a, 385.

203. Podziba Reference Podziba2018, 384.

204. Aggestam, Cristiano, and Strömbom Reference Aggestam, Cristiano and Strömbom2015, 1738.

205. Hassner Reference Hassner2009, 153–54.

206. Podziba Reference Podziba2018, 389.

207. Zarakol Reference Zarakol2017, 49, 54.

208. Costa Lopez Reference Costa Lopez2020, 229.

209. Diefendorf Reference Diefendorf2014, 553–54. See also Roberts Reference Roberts2004.

210. Diefendorf Reference Diefendorf2014, 561.

211. Holt Reference Holt2005, 117.

213. Luria Reference Luria2005, 85.

215. As seen with confessionalization. Cavanaugh Reference Cavanaugh2009, 168–71.

217. Harding Reference Harding1981, 403, 406.

218. Harding Reference Harding1981, 397–99, 401.

219. Wolfe Reference Wolfe1987, 305.

220. Holt Reference Holt1993, 542, Reference Holt2005, 124–25.

221. Harding Reference Harding1981, 404.

222. Wolfe Reference Wolfe1987, 290. The Sorbonne theologian Jean Boucher, for example, removed “the monarch from the contract between God and the people.” Holt Reference Holt2005, 134.

223. Holt Reference Holt2005, 135. See also Greengrass Reference Greengrass1983.

224. Harding Reference Harding1981, 406–409.

226. Wolfe Reference Wolfe1987, 296–98, 304, 309.

227. Wolfe Reference Wolfe1987, 299, 303–304. Wolfe, borrowing from Claude de Seyssel, uses freins as another word for constraints.

228. Wolfe Reference Wolfe1987, 305.

229. Luria Reference Luria2005, 86–88; Spicer Reference Spicer2007, 250–51.

230. Reinburg Reference Reinburg2017; Spicer Reference Spicer2007, 260, 264–65.

231. Harding Reference Harding1980; Luria Reference Luria2005, 48, 53, 89.

232. Desan Reference Desan and Hunt1989, 66–67. See also Roberts Reference Roberts2004.

233. Solomon Reference Solomon2018.

234. Marr Reference Marr2017, 445, 453.

235. Williams Reference Williams2010, 312.

236. Carr Reference Carr1941, 113.

237. This aligns with OS studies discussing ethical/moral arguments in policy debates and the power of “sacred” places. Ejdus and Subotić Reference Ejdus, Subotić, Ognjenović and Jozelić2014; Steele Reference Steele2008.

238. Church Reference Church1972; Rehman Reference Rehman2019, 44–46, 60.

239. Aron Reference Aron1962, 598.

240. Hayes Reference Hayes1926, 115.

241. A focal point of the journal Medieval Encounters.

242. Bolton Reference Bolton2021a; Crimston, Selvanathan, and Jetten Reference Crimston, Selvanathan and Jetten2022.

244. Bettiza, Bolton, and Lewis Reference Bettiza, Bolton and Lewis2023.

246. Wight Reference Wight1986, 82.

248. Cesa Reference Cesa2009, 182.

250. Aron Reference Aron1962, 99–104.

251. Bolton, Reference Bolton2021b, 280.

252. Koslowski and Kratochwil Reference Koslowski and Kratochwil1994, 229, 234 n52.

254. Evangelista Reference Evangelista2001, 16.

256. Stoeckl and Uzlaner Reference Stoeckl and Uzlaner2022, 33.

258. Demerath Reference Demerath2000, 132.

References

Appleby, Scott R. 2000. The Ambivalence of the Sacred: Religion, Violence, and Reconciliation. Rowman and Littlefield.Google Scholar
Aggestam, Karin, Cristiano, Fabio, and Strömbom, Lisa. 2015. Towards Agnostic Peacebuilding? Exploring the Antagonism-Agonism Nexus in the Middle East Peace Process. Third World Quarterly 36 (9):1736–53.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Aron, Raymond. 1962. Peace and War: A Theory of International Relations. Routledge, repr. 2003.Google Scholar
Asad, Talal. 1993. Genealogies of Religion: Discipline and Reasons of Power in Christianity and Islam. Johns Hopkins University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Balkenhol, Markus, van den Hemel, Ernst, and Stengs, Irene. 2020. Introduction: Emotional Entanglements of Sacrality and Secularity—Engaging the Paradox. In The Secular Sacred, edited by Balkenhol, Markus, van den Hemel, Ernst, and Stengs, Irene, 118. Palgrave.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beame, Edmond. 1993. The Politiques and the Historians. Journal of the History of Ideas 54 (3):355–79.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Benedict, Philip. 1999. Introduction. In Reformation, Revolt and Civil War in France and the Netherlands, 1555–1585, edited by Benedict, Philip, Marnef, Guido, van Nierop, Henk, and Venard, Marc, 122. Royal Netherlands Academy of Arts and Sciences.Google Scholar
Benedict, Philip. 2006. Religion and Politics in Europe, 1500–1700. In Religion und Gewalt: Konflikte, Rituale, Deutungen (1500–1800), edited by Greyerz, Kaspar von and Siebenhuner, Kim, 155174. Vandenhoeck and Ruprecht.Google Scholar
Benedict, Philip. 2007. Thinking About Religion and Society in the Seventeenth and Eighteenth Century: Confessionalization, the History of Toleration, and Beyond. SZRKG (Swiss Journal for Religious and Cultural History) 101:247–56.Google Scholar
Benedict, Philip. 2009. Un Roi, Une Loi, Deux Fois: Parameters for the History of Catholic-Reformed Co-existence in France, 1555–1685. In Tolerance and Intolerance in the European Reformation, edited by Grell, Ole Peter, 6593. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Benedict, Philip. 2012. Prophets in Arms? Ministers in War, Ministers on War: France 1562–74. Past and Present 214:163–96.10.1093/pastj/gtr022CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Benedict, Philip. 2016. Were the French Wars of Religion Really Wars of Religion? In The European Wars of Religion: An Interdisciplinary Reassessment of Sources, Interpretations, and Myths, edited by Palaver, Wolfgang, Rudolph, Harriet, and Regensburger, Dietmar, 6186. Ashgate.Google Scholar
Berenskoetter, Felix. 2014. Parameters of a National Biography. European Journal of International Relations 20 (1):262–88.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Berenskoetter, Felix. 2020. Anxiety, Time and Agency. International Theory 12 (2):273–90.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bettiza, Gregorio, Bolton, Derek, and Lewis, David. 2023. Civilizationism and the Ideological Contestation of the Liberal International Order. International Studies Review 25 (2).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bolton, Derek. 2021a. Targeting Ontological Security: Information Warfare in the Modern Age. Political Psychology 42 (1):127–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bolton, Derek. 2021b. Balancing Identity: The Sino-Soviet Split, Ontological Security, and North Korean Foreign Policy. Security Studies 30 (2):271301.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bolton, Derek. 2023. The Unbearable Lightness of Being? Reconfiguring the Moral Underpinnings and Sources of Ontological Security. International Theory 15 (2):234–26.Google Scholar
Browning, Christopher. 2018. Brexit, Existential Anxiety and Ontological (In)security. European Security 27 (3):336–55.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carr, E.H. 1941. The Twenty Years’ Crisis 1919–1939. Macmillan and Co.Google Scholar
Carroll, Stuart. 1995. The Guise Affinity and Popular Protest During the Wars of Religion. French History 9 (2):125–52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Casanova, Jose. 1994. Public Religions in the Modern World. University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cavanaugh, William. 2009. The Myth of Religious Violence: Secular Ideology and the Roots of Modern Conflict. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cavanaugh, William. 2014. Religious Violence as Modern Myth. Political Theology 15 (6):486502.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cesa, Marco. 2009. Realist Visions of the End of the Cold War: Morgenthau, Aron and Waltz. British Journal of Politics and International Relations 11:177–91.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Christin, Oliver. 1999. From Repression to Pacification: French Royal Policy in the Face of Protestantism. In Reformation, Revolt and Civil War in France and the Netherlands, 1555–1585, edited by Benedict, Philip, Marnef, Guido, van Nierop, Henk, and Venard, Marc, 201214. Royal Netherlands Academy of Arts and Sciences.Google Scholar
Church, William. 1972. Richelieu and Reason of State. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Connolly, William. 1999. Why I Am Not a Secularist. University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Costa Lopez, Julia. 2020 Political Authority in International Relations: Revisiting the Medieval Debate. International Organization 74 (2):222–52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Costa Lopez, Julia, De Carvalho, Benjamin, Latham, Andrew A, Zarakol, Ayse, Bartelson, Jens, and Holm, Minda. 2018. Forum: In the Beginning There Was No Word (for It): Terms, Concepts, and Early Sovereignty. International Studies Review 20 (3):489519.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crimston, Charlie, Selvanathan, Hema Preya, and Jetten, Jolanda. 2022. Moral Polarization Predicts Support for Authoritarian and Progressive Strong Leaders via the Perceived Breakdown of Society. Political Psychology 43 (4):671–91.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crouzet, Denis. 1999. Calvinism and the Use of the Political and Religious. In Reformation, Revolt and Civil War in France and the Netherlands, 1555–1585, edited by Benedict, Philip, Marnef, Guido, van Nierop, Henk, and Venard, Marc, 99114. Royal Netherlands Academy of Arts and Sciences.Google Scholar
Davis, Natalie. 1973. The Rites of Violence: Religious Riot in Sixteenth-Century France. Past and Present 59:5191.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davis, Natalie. 1981. The Sacred and the Body Social in Sixteenth-Century Lyon. Past and Present 90 (1):4070.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davis, Natalie. 2012. Writing “The Rites of Violence” and Afterward. Past and Present 214 (S7):829.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
de Carvalho, Benjamin, Leira, Halvard, and Hobson, John M.. 2011. The Big Bangs of IR: The Myths that Your Teachers Still Tell You About 1648 and 1919. Millennium 39 (3):735–58.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Demerath, N.J. 2000. The Rise of “Cultural Religion” in European Christianity: Learning from Poland, Northern Ireland, and Sweden. Social Compass 47 (1):127–39.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Desan, Suzanne. 1989. Crowds, Community and Ritual in the Works of E.P. Thompson and Natalie Davis. In The New Cultural History, edited by Hunt, Lynn, 4771. University of California Press.Google Scholar
Diefendorf, Barbara. 1991. Beneath the Cross: Catholics and Huguenots in Sixteenth-Century Paris. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Diefendorf, Barbara. 2012. Rites of Repair: Restoring Community in the French Religious Wars. Past and Present 214:3051.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Diefendorf, Barbara. 2014. Were the Wars of Religion About Religion? Political Theology 15 (6):552–63.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Diefendorf, Barbara. 2017a. Reflections on Community and Identity. French Historical Studies 40 (3):383–90.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Diefendorf, Barbara. 2017b. Religious Conflict and Civic Identity: Battles over the Sacred Landscape of Montpellier. Past and Present 237 (1):391.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Durkheim, Emile. 1995 [1912]. The Elementary Forms of Religious Life, translated by Fields, Karen. Free Press.Google Scholar
Ejdus, Filip, and Subotić, Jelena. 2014. Kosovo as Serbia's Sacred Space: Governmentality, Pastoral Power, and Sacralization of Territories. In Politicization of Religion, the Power of Symbolism, edited by Ognjenović, Gorana and Jozelić, Jasna, 159–84. Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Evangelista, Matthew. 2001. Norms, Heresthetics, and the End of the Cold War. Journal of Cold War Studies 3 (1):535.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Farrands, Christopher, and Wrightson, Patricia Stein. 2000. The Ambiguous Revival of “Community” in IR: Religion, the Sacred and Niebuhr on the Limits of Rationality. Theoria 95:3458.Google Scholar
Foa, Jérémie. 2004. Making Peace: The Commissions for Enforcing the Pacification Edicts in the Reign of Charles IX (1560–1574). French History 18 (3):256–74.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Foa, Jérémie. 2006. An Unequal Apportionment: The Conflict over Space Between Protestants and Catholics at the Beginning of the Wars of Religion. French History 20 (4):369–86.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Foa, Jérémie. 2017. Who Goes There? To Live and Survive During the Wars of Religion, 1562–1598. French Historical Studies 40 (3):425–38.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gentile, Emilio. 2005. Political Religion: A Concept and Its Critics—A Critical Survey. Totalitarian Movements and Political Religions 6 (1):1932.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ginges, Jeremy, and Atran, Scott. 2014. Sacred Values and Cultural Conflict. In Advances in Culture and Psychology, Vol. 4., edited by Gelfand, Michele J., Chiu, Chi-yue, and Hong, Ying-yi, 273301. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Gold, Richard, ed. 1988. The Huguenot Connection: The Edict of Nantes, Its Revocation, and Early French Migration to South Carolina. Kluwer Academic.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Greenfield, Liah. 1993. Nationalism: Five Roads to Modernity. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Greengrass, Mark. 1983. The Sainte Union in the Provinces: The Case of Toulouse. Sixteenth Century Journal 14 (4):469–96.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Greengrass, Mark. 1999. Hidden Transcripts: Secret Histories and Personal Testimonies of Religious Violence in the French Wars of Religion. In The Massacre in History, edited by Levene, Mark and Roberts, Penny, 6988. Bergahn.Google Scholar
Greengrass, Mark. 2000. Plauralism and Equality: The Peace of Monsieur, May 1576. In The Adventure of Religious Pluralism in Early Modern France, edited by Cameron, Keith, Greengrass, Mark, and Roberts, Penny, 4563. Peter Lang.Google Scholar
Greengrass, Mark. 2013. Europe's “Wars of Religion” and Their Legacies. In Protestant-Catholic Conflict from the Reformation to the Twenty-first Century: The Dynamics of Religious Difference, edited by Wolffe, John, 2245. Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Grosse, Christian. 2017. Praying Against the Enemy: Imprecatory Prayer and Reformed Identity from the Reformation to the Early Enlightenment. French Historical Studies 40 (3):409–23.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hain, Peter. 2007. Peacemaking in Northern Ireland: A Model for Conflict Resolution? Speech by Peter Hain MP, Secretary of State for Northern Ireland, Chatham House, 12 June. Available at <https://cain.ulster.ac.uk/issues/politics/docs/nio/ph120607.pdf>..>Google Scholar
Hanlon, Gregory. 1993. Confession and Community in Seventeenth-Century France: Catholic and Protestant Coexistence in Aquitaine. University of Pennsylvania Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harding, Robert. 1980. The Mobilization of Confraternities Against the Reformation in France. Sixteenth Century Journal 11 (2):85107.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harding, Robert. 1981. Revolution and Reform in the Holy League: Angers, Rennes, Nantes. Journal of Modern History 53 (3):379416.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hassner, Ron. 2009. War on Sacred Grounds. Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Hassner, Ron. 2011. Blasphemy and Violence. International Studies Quarterly 55 (1):2345.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hastings, Adrian. 1997. The Construction of Nationhood: Ethnicity, Religion and Nationalism. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hayes, Carlton J.H. 1926. Essays on Nationalism. Macmillan.Google Scholar
Heinämäki, Elisa. 2015. Durkheim, Bataille, and Girard on the Ambiguity of the Sacred: Reconsidering Saints and Demoniacs. Journal of the American Academy of Religion 83 (2):513–36.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Herman, Robert. 1996. Identity, Norms and National Security: The Soviet Foreign Policy Revolution and the End of the Cold War. In The Culture of National Security: Norms and Identity in World Politics, edited by Katzenstein, Peter, 271–316. Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Hirschi, Caspar. 2012. The Origins of Nationalism. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Holt, Mack. 1993. Putting Religion Back into the Wars of Religion. French Historical Studies 18 (2):524–51.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Holt, Mack. 2005. The French Wars of Religion, 1562–1629. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Holt, Mack. 2012. Religious Violence in Sixteenth-Century France: Moving Beyond Pollution and Purification. Past and Present 214:5274.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hunt, Lynn. 1988. The Sacred and the French Revolution. In Durkheimian Sociology: Cultural Studies, edited by Alexander, Jeffrey, 2543. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hurd, Elizabeth Shakman. 2008. The Politics of Secularism in International Relations. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Hurd, Elizabeth Shakman. 2011. Secularism and International Relations Theory. In Religion and International Relations Theory, edited by Snyder, Jack, 6090. Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Hutchison, Emma, and Bleiker, Roland. 2014. Theorizing Emotions in World Politics. International Theory 6 (3):491514.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Joas, Hans. 2016. Sacralization and Desacralization: Political Domination and Religious Interpretation. Journal of the Society of Christian Ethics 36 (2):2542.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kaplan, Benjamin. 2010. Divided by Faith: Religious Conflict and the Practice of Toleration in Early Modern Europe. Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kim, Seong-Hak. 1993. The Chancellor's Crusade: Michel de l'Hôpital and the Parlement of Paris. French History 7 (1):129.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kinnvall, Catarina. 2018. Ontological Insecurities and Postcolonial Imaginaries: The Emotional Appeal of Populism. Humanity and Society 42 (4):523–43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kinnvall, Catarina, and Mitzen, Jennifer. 2020. Anxiety, Fear, and Ontological Security in World Politics: Thinking With and Beyond Giddens. International Theory 12 (2):240–56.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Knecht, R.J. 1982. Francis I. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Konnert, Mark. 1989. Urban Values Versus Religious Passions: Chalons-sur-Marne During the Wars of Religion. Sixteenth Century Journal 20 (3):387405.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Koslowski, Rey, and Kratochwil, Friedrich. 1994. Understanding Change in International Politics: The Soviet Empire's Demise and the International System. International Organization 48 (2):215–47.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kubálková, Vendulka. 2000. Towards an International Political Theology. Millennium 29 (3):675704.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lovin, Robin. 2003. A Christian Realist Perspective. In The Sacred and the Sovereign: Religion and International Politics, edited by Carlson, John D. and Owens, Erik C., 154–69. Georgetown University Press.Google Scholar
Lualdi, Katharine. 2004. Persevering in the Faith: Catholic Worship and Communal Identity in the Wake of the Edict of Nantes. Sixteenth Century Journal 35 (3):206217.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Luria, Keith. 2005. Sacred Boundaries: Religious Coexistence and Conflict in Early-Modern France. Catholic University of America Press.Google Scholar
Lynch, Cecelia. 2000. Dogma, Praxis, and Religious Perspectives on Multiculturalism. Millennium 29 (3):741–59.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Marr, Scott. 2017. Conversion, Family, and Authority in Seventeenth-Century Saumur. French Historical Studies 40 (3):439–56.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mälksoo, Maria. 2021. A Ritual Approach to Deterrence: I Am, Therefore I Deter. European Journal of International Relations 27 (1):5378.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mavelli, Luca. 2011. Security and Secularization in International Relations. European Journal of International Relations 18 (1):177–99.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mellor, Philip. 1998. Sacred Contagion and Social Vitality: Collective Effervescence in “Les formes élémentaires de la vie religieuse.” Durkheimian Studies 4:87114.Google Scholar
Mellor, Philip. 2002. In Defence of Durkheim: Sociology, the Sacred and “Society.” Durkheimian Studies 8:1534.Google Scholar
Meštrović, Stjepan. 1985. Anomia and Sin in Durkheim's Thought. Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion 24 (2):119–36.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Meštrović, Stjepan, and Brown, Hélène. 1985. Durkheim's Concept of Anomie as Dérèglement. Social Problems 35 (2):81–99.Google Scholar
Meštrović, Stjepan, and Lorenzo, Robert. 2008. Durkheim's Concept of Anomie and the Abuse at Abu Ghraib. Journal of Classic Sociology 8 (2):179207.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morgenthau, Hans J. 1947. Scientific Man vs. Power Politics. Latimer House.Google Scholar
Morgenthau, Hans J. 1949. The Twilight of International Morality. Ethics 58 (2):81107.Google Scholar
Morgenthau, Hans J. 1960. Politics Among Nations. 3rd ed. Knopf.Google Scholar
Neuschel, Kristen. 1989. World of Honor. Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Nexon, Daniel. 2009. The Struggle for Power in Early Modern Europe: Religious Conflict, Dynastic Empires, and International Change. Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nexon, Daniel. 2011. Religion and International Relations: No Leap of Faith Required. In Religion and International Relations Theory, edited by Snyder, Jack, 141–67. Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Nicholls, David. 1994. Protestants, Catholics and Magistrates in Tours, 1562–1572: The Making of a Catholic City During the Religious Wars. French History 8 (1):1433.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nicholls, David. 1996. Heresy and Protestantism, 1520–1542: Questions of Perception and Communication. French History 10 (2):185205.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Niebuhr, Reinhold. 1932. Moral Man and Immoral Society: A Study in Ethics and Politics. Charles Scribner's Sons.Google Scholar
Philpott, Daniel. 2002. The Challenge of September 11 to Secularism in International Relations. World Politics 55 (1):6695.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Philpott, Daniel. 2009. Has the Study of Global Politics Found Religion? Annual Review of Political Science 12 (1):183202.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Podziba, Susan. 2018. Mediating Conflict over Sacred Land. Conflict Resolution Quarterly 35:383–91.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pollmann, Judith. 2006. Countering the Reformation in France and the Netherlands: Clerical Leadership and Catholic Violence 1560–1585. Past and Present 190:83120.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rehman, Iskander. 2019. Raison d’État: Richelieu's Grand Strategy During the Thirty Years’ War. Texas National Security Review 2 (3):3875.Google Scholar
Reinburg, Virginia. 1992. Liturgy and Laity in Late Medieval and Reformation France. Sixteenth Century Journal 23:381–99.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reinburg, Virginia. 2017. Storied Place: Land and Legend at Notre-Dame de Garaison. French Historical Studies 40 (3):391407.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Roberts, Penny. 2004. Royal Authority and Justice During the French Religious Wars. Past and Present 184:332.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Roberts, Penny. 2007a. The Kingdom's Two Bodies? Corporeal Rhetoric and Royal Authority During the Religious Wars. French History 21 (2):147–64.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Roberts, Penny. 2007b. The Languages of Peace During the French Religious Wars. Cultural and Social History 4 (3):297315.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Roberts, Penny. 2012. Peace, Ritual, and Sexual Violence During the Religious Wars. Past and Present 214:7599.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ross, Andrew. 2013. Realism, Emotion, and Dynamic Allegiances in Global Politics. International Theory 5 (2):273–99.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rumelili, Bahar, ed. 2015. Conflict Resolution and Ontological Security. Routledge.Google Scholar
Rumelili, Bahar. 2020. Integrating Anxiety into International Relations Theory: Hobbes, Existentialism, and Ontological Security. International Theory 12 (2):257–72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sandal, Nukhet, and Fox, Jonathan, eds. 2013. Religion in International Relations Theory: Interactions and Possibilities. Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schwarz, Tanya B., and Lynch, Cecelia. 2016. Religion in International Relations. Oxford Research Encyclopedia of Politics. Available at <https://oxfordre.com/politics/view/10.1093/acrefore/9780190228637.001.0001/acrefore-9780190228637-e-122>.CrossRef.>Google Scholar
Smith, Anthony. 1998. Nationalism and Modernism. Routledge.Google Scholar
Smith, Anthony. 2000. The “Sacred” Dimension of Nationalism. Millennium 29 (3):791814.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, Anthony. 2003. Chosen Peoples: Sacred Sources of National Identity. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, Anthony. 2005. Nationalism in Early Modern Europe. History and Theory 44 (3):404415.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, Anthony. 2008. The Cultural Foundation of Nations. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Smith, Malcolm. 1994. Early French Advocates of Religious Freedom. Sixteenth Century Journal 25 (1):2951.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Solomon, Ty. 2014. Time and Subjectivity in World Politics. International Studies Quarterly 58 (1):671–81.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Solomon, Ty. 2018. Ontological Security, Circulations of Affect, and the Arab Spring. Journal of International Relations and Development 21 (4):934–58.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Spicer, Andrew. 2007. (Re)building the Sacred Landscape: Orleans, 1560–1610. French History 21:247–68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Steele, Brent. 2008. Ontological Security in International Relations: Self Identity and the IR State. Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Steele, Brent. 2019. Welcome Home! Routines, Ontological Insecurity and the Politics of US Military Reunion Videos. Cambridge Review of International Affairs 32 (3):322–43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stoeckl, Kristina, and Uzlaner, Dmitry. 2022. The Globalist International. Fordham University Press.Google Scholar
Sutherland, N.M. 1988. The Crown, the Huguenots, and the Edict of Nantes. In The Huguenot Connection: The Edict of Nantes, Its Revocation, and Early French Migration to South Carolina, edited by Gold, Richard, 2848. Kluwer Academic.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thomas, Scott. 2005. The Global Resurgence of Religion and the Transformation of International Relations. Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Turchetti, Mario. 1991. Religious Concord and Political Tolerance in Sixteenth- and Seventeenth-Century France. Sixteenth Century Journal 12 (1):1525.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Venard, Marc. 1999. Catholicism and Resistance to the Reformation in France, 1555–1585. In Reformation, Revolt and Civil War in France and the Netherlands, 1555–1585, edited by Benedict, Philip, Marnef, Guido, van Nierop, Henk, and Venard, Marc, 133–48. Royal Netherlands Academy of Arts and Sciences.Google Scholar
Vieira, Marco. 2018. (Re-)imagining the “Self” of Ontological Security: The Case of Brazil's Ambivalent Postcolonial Subjectivity. Millennium 46 (2):142–64.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wagner, Harrison. 2007. War and the State. University of Michigan Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wight, Martin. 1986. Power Politics. Pelican Books.Google Scholar
Williams, Michael C. 1998. Security and the Politics of Identity. European Journal of International Relations 4 (2):204225.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, Michael C. 2010. The Legacies of Raison d’État: A Brief Commentary on R. Harrison Wagner's War and the State. International Theory 2 (2):306316.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, Michael C. 2013. In the Beginning: The International Relations Enlightenment and the Ends of International Relations Theory. European Journal of International Relations 19 (3):647–65.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wolfe, Michael. 1987. The Conversion of Henri IV and the Origins of Bourbon Absolutism. Historical Reflections 14 (2):287309.Google Scholar
Wolffe, John, ed. 2013. Protestant-Catholic Conflict from the Reformation to the Twenty-first Century: The Dynamics of Religious Difference. Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Zarakol, Ayşe. 2017. States and Ontological Security: A Historical Rethinking. Cooperation and Conflict 52 (1):4868.CrossRefGoogle Scholar