Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-fscjk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-28T10:52:00.719Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Self before Self-Consciousness: Hegel's Developmental Account*

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  23 August 2013

Daniel Dahlstrom*
Affiliation:
Get access

Abstract

This paper examines three puzzles that arise from Hegel's account of the constitution of the self and self-consciousness. The puzzles mirror questions of the respective relation of (a) the self to self-consciousness, (b) self-consciousness to recognition of and by others, and (c) the struggle for recognition to ethical life. The paper argues that Hegel's developmental account of the constitution of the self and self-consciousness provides promising prospects for resolving puzzles about the status of the self before self-consciousness and the status of self-consciousness in the family before the struggle for recognition. However, the paper questions the adequacy of Hegel's account of ethical life, in view of the puzzle that it presents and appears unable to resolve. The paper suggests that Hegel's developmental account is too restrictive, since its move from a quest for mastery to mutual recognition apparently fails to account sufficiently for asymmetrical acts of generosity and sacrifice.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © The Hegel Society of Great Britain 2013 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

*

I am grateful to Tim Brownlee, Jeremy Butman, and Ian Dunkle for valuable comments on earlier drafts of this paper. My study of Hegel generally and the topic of self-consciousness in particular is deeply indebted to Professor Klaus Düsing's formidable body of work. For his scholarship and support through the years, I am deeply thankful.

References

Bubbio, P. D. (2012), ‘Sacrifice in Hegel's Phenomenology of Spirit, British Journal for the History of Philosophy 20/4: 797-815.Google Scholar
Carruthers, P. (1996), Language, Thought, and Consciousness: An Essay in Philosophical Psychology. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Curley, E. (ed.) (1994), Leviathan. Indianapolis, Indiana: Hackett.Google Scholar
Davidson, D. (1999), ‘The Problem of Objectivity’, Tijdschrift voor Filosofie 57: 203-220.Google Scholar
Descartes, R. (1904), Meditiations & Principes, in C. Adam and P. Tannery (eds.), Oeuvres, IX. Paris: Cerf.Google Scholar
Düsing, K. (1986), Intersubjektivität und Selbstbewußtsein. Köln: Dinter.Google Scholar
Düsing, K. (1997), Selbstbewußtseinsmodelle. München: Fink.Google Scholar
Düsing, K. (2002), ‘Konstitution und Struktur des Ich. Kants Theorie der Apperzeption und Hegels Kritik’ in Subjektivität und Freiheit: Untersuchungen zum Idealismus von Kant bis Hegel. Stuttgart-Bad Canstatt: frommann-holzboog.Google Scholar
Ferrarin, A. (2001), Hegel and Aristotle. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Flay, J. (1989), ‘Hegel, Derrida, and Bataille's Laughter’, in W. Desmond (ed.), Hegel and his Critics. Albany, New York: SUNY Press.Google Scholar
Hegel, G. W. F. (1969), Enzyklopädie der philosophischen Wissenschaften, hrsg. Friedhelm Nicolin und Otto Pöggeler. Hamburg: Meiner.Google Scholar
Hegel, G. W. F. (1970), Berliner Schriften: 1818-1831 in Werke, Bd. 11. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.Google Scholar
Hegel, G. W. F. (1976), Jenaer Systementwürfe III, hrsg. Rolf-Peter Horstmann und Johann Heinrich Trede, Gesammelte Werke, Rheinsch Westfällische Akademie der Wissenschaften, Band 8. Hamburg: Meiner.Google Scholar
Hegel, G. W. F. (1987), Jenaer Systementwürfe III: Naturphilosophie und Philosophie des Geistes, hrsg. Rolf-Peter Horstmann. Hamburg: Meiner.Google Scholar
Hegel, G. W. F. (1988), Phänomenologie des Geistes, hrsg. Hans-Friedrich Wessels und Heinrich Clairmont. Hamburg: Meiner.Google Scholar
Houlgate, S. (1991), ‘Power, Egoism and the “Open” Self’, The Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 22: 127-131.Google Scholar
Houlgate, S. (1996), ‘Hegel, Derrida, and Restricted Economy: The Case of Mechanical Memory’, Journal of the History of Philosophy 34/1: 79-93.Google Scholar
Kant, I. (1971), Kritik der reinen Vernunft. Hamburg: Meiner.Google Scholar
Leibniz, G. W. F. (1961), ‘Principes de la Nature et de la Grace, fondés en raison’, in C. J. Gerhardt (ed.), Die philosophischen Schriften, Band VI. Hildesheim: Olms.Google Scholar
Locke, J. (1975), An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, ed. P. H. Nidditch. Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
Mayr, E. (1964), ‘The Evolution of Living Systems’, Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 51: 934-941.Google Scholar
Mayr, E. (1988), Toward a New Philosophy of Biology: Observations of an Evolutionist. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Pinkard, T. (2007), ‘Liberal Rights and Liberal Individualism without Liberalism: Agency and Recognition’, in E. Hammer (ed.), German Idealism: Contemporary Perspectives. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Pippin, R. (2000), ‘What is the Question for which Hegel's Theory of Recognition is the Answer?European Journal of Philosophy 8/2: 156.Google Scholar
Pittendrigh, C. S. (1958), ‘Adaptation, Natural Selection and Behavior’, in A. Roe and G. G. Simpson (eds.), Behavior and Evolution. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Siep, L. (1992), Praktische Philosophie im Deutschen Idealismus. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.Google Scholar
Thomasson, L. (2000), ‘After Brentano: A one-level theory of consciousness’, European Journal of Philosophy 8/2: 190-209.Google Scholar
Williams, R. (1997), The Ethics of Recognition. Berkeley, California: University of California.Google Scholar
Zahavi, D. (2004), ‘Back to Brentano?Journal of Consciousness Studies 11/10-11: 66-87.Google Scholar
Zahavi, D. (2006), ‘Two Takes on a One-Level Account of Consciousness’, Psyche 12/2: 1-9.Google Scholar