Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-2brh9 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-30T18:51:29.126Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Reason in Politics

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  22 April 2013

David P. Levine*
Affiliation:
Josef Korbel School of International Studies, University of Denver, [email protected]
Get access

Abstract

In this essay, I explore the role of philosophy in politics and public policy along one dimension that is suggested by the question ‘Does reason have a place in the shaping of public policy and institutions?’ In considering this question, I focus on the factors that prevent reasoned argument from influencing political process and outcome. Among the factors standing in the way of reason, two, I think, are of special importance. The first is the dominance of interests, and the second is the dominance of fixed ideas rooted not in interests but in myth and fantasy. I begin with the role of interests in politics arguing that interest provides a limited role for reason, but that this role erodes the more interest is an expression of greed. I then turn to belief and the way belief systems operate as the more powerful of the two factors excluding reason from politics.

While interest-based politics can create space for reason, what now tends to dominate in politics is not interests so much as other factors operating on an altogether different plane. These are the factors associated with fixed ideas, convictions made impervious to any doubt by forces over which reason has no power. It is possible, of course, to attempt to treat conviction as a kind of interest. We can, after all, be said to take an interest in our belief systems. Yet, an important distinction can still be drawn, within the set of objects in which we might take an interest, between those associated with belief and those associated with the narrower matter of economic well being.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Hegel Society of Great Britain 2012

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Bion, W. (1967), Second Thoughts. London: Maresfield Library.Google Scholar
Bion, W. (1961), Experiences in Groups. London: Tavistock.Google Scholar
Fairbairn, W. (1958), ‘On the Nature and Aims of Psychoanalytic Treatment’, International Journal of Psychoanalysis 31: 374–85. (Is there an issue number following vol. 31, as in Glasser?) No issue number.Google Scholar
Freud, S. (1959), Group Psychology and the Analysis of the Ego. New York: Norton.Google Scholar
Glasser, M. (1992), ‘Problems in the Psychoanalysis of Certain Narcissistic Disorders’, The International Journal of Psychoanalysis 73.3: 493503.Google ScholarPubMed
Hegel, G. W. F. (1952), Hegel's Philosophy of Right, trans. Knox, T. M.. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kernberg, O. (1986), ‘Factors in the Treatment of Narcissistic Personalities’, in Morrison, A. (ed.), Essential Papers on Narcissism. New York: New York University Press.Google Scholar
Levine, D. (2008), Welfare, Right and the State. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Levine, D. (2011), The Capacity for Civic Engagement: Public and Private Worlds of the Self. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Marx, K. and Engels, F. (1977), The Manifesto of the Communist Party, in Karl Marx: Selected Writings, ed. McLellan, D.. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Miller, A. (1980), ‘Depression and Grandiosity as Related Forms of Narcissistic Disturbances’, in Morrison, A. (ed.), Essential Papers on Narcissism. New York: New York University Press. (Why is the date different from the Kernberg entry?)Google Scholar
Turquet, P. (1985), ‘Leadership, the Individual, and the Group’, in Coleman, A. and Geller, M. (eds.), Group Relations Reader 2. Jupiter, FL: A.K. Rice Institute.Google Scholar