Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-r5fsc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-30T20:52:11.007Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Kierkegaard and the Limits of Thought

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  09 September 2016

Daniel Watts*
Affiliation:
University of Essex, [email protected]
Get access

Abstract

This essay offers an account of Kierkegaard’s view of the limits of thought and of what makes this view distinctive. With primary reference to Philosophical Fragments, and its putative representation of Christianity as unthinkable, I situate Kierkegaard’s engagement with the problem of the limits of thought, especially with respect to the views of Kant and Hegel. I argue that Kierkegaard builds in this regard on Hegel’s critique of Kant but that, against Hegel, he develops a radical distinction between two types of thinking and inquiry: the ‘aesthetic-intellectual’ and the ‘ethico-religious’. I clarify this distinction and show how it guides Kierkegaard’s conception of a form of philosophical practice that involves drawing limits to the proper sphere of disinterested contemplation. With reference to two rival interpretations of Kierkegaard’s approach to the limits of thought—which I call ‘bullet-biting’ and ‘relativizing’—I further show how my ‘disambiguating’ account can better explain how, and why, his work courts a form of self-referential incoherence, in which it appears that certain limits of thought are at once affirmed and violated.

Type
Articles
Copyright
© The Hegel Society of Great Britain 2016 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Allison, H. E. (1967), ‘Christianity and Nonsense’, Review of Metaphysics 20: 432460.Google Scholar
Burgess, A. (2009), ‘Henrich Steffens: Combining Danish Romanticism with Christian Orthodoxy’, in J. Stewart (ed.), Kierkegaard and his Danish Contemporaries, Tome I Farnham: Ashgate.Google Scholar
Conant, J. (1989), ‘Must We Show What We Cannot Say?’, in R. Fleming and M. Payne (eds.), The Senses of Stanley Cavell. Lewisburg: Bucknell University Press.Google Scholar
Conant, J. (1993), ‘Kierkegaard, Wittgenstein and Nonsense’, in T. Cohen, P. Guyer and H. Putnam (eds.), Pursuits of Reason. Texas: Texas University Press.Google Scholar
Evans, C. S. (1992), Passionate Reason: Making Sense of Kierkegaard’s Philosophical Fragments. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
Evans, C. S. (2008), ‘Kierkegaard and the Limits of Reason: Can There Be a Responsible Fideism?Revista Portuguesa de Filosofia 64: 10211035.Google Scholar
Ferreira, M. J. (1994), ‘The Point Outside the World: Kierkegaard and Wittgenstein on Nonsense, Paradox and Religion’, Religious Studies 30: 2944.Google Scholar
Frege, G. ((1977) [1918]), ‘Thoughts’, in his Logical Investigations. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Hannay, A. (2003), ‘Climacus among the Philosophers’, in Kierkegaard and Philosophy: Selected Essays. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Hopkins, R. (1998), Picture, Image and Experience: A Philosophical Inquiry. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kant, I. (2004), Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics, trans. G. Hatfield. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Lippitt, J. and Hutto, D. (1998), ‘Making Sense of Nonsense: Kierkegaard and Wittgenstein’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 98: 263286.Google Scholar
McDowell, J. (1998), ‘Two Sorts of Naturalism’, in his Mind, Value, and Reality. London: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Moran, R. (2001), Authority and Estrangement: An Essay on Self-Knowledge. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Mulhall, S. (1999), ‘God’s Plagiarist: The Philosophical Fragments of Johannes Climacus’, Philosophical Investigations 22: 134.Google Scholar
Mulhall, S. (2001), Inheritance and Originality: Wittgenstein, Heidegger, Kierkegaard. Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
Priest, G. (2001), Beyond the Limits of Thought. Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
Ross, S. (1974), ‘Caricature’, The Monist 58: 285293.Google Scholar
Rubenstein, M.-J. (2002), ‘Ecstatic Subjectivity: Kierkegaard’s Critiques and Appropriations of the Socratic’, Modern Theology 17: 442473.Google Scholar
Rudd, A. (2000), ‘On Straight and Crooked Readings: Why the Postscript Does Not Self-Destruct’, in P. Houe, G. D. Marino and S. H. Rossel (eds.), Anthropology and Authority: Essays on Søren Kierkegaard. Amsterdam: Editions Rodopi.Google Scholar
Schönbaumsfeld, G. (2007), A Confusion of the Spheres: Kierkegaard and Wittgenstein on Philosophy and Religion. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vidal, D. (2005), ‘The Pathos of Limit: Reading Kierkegaard Through the Dialectic of Limit’, in N. J. Cappelørn and H. Deuser (eds.), Kierkegaard Studies Yearbook: 2005. Berlin: de Gruyter.Google Scholar
Watts, D. (2007), ‘The Paradox of Beginning: Hegel, Kierkegaard and Philosophical Inquiry’, Inquiry 50: 533.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Watts, D. (2010), ‘Subjective Thinking: Kierkegaard on Hegel’s Socrates’, Hegel Bulletin 61: 2344.Google Scholar
Watts, D. (2013), ‘Kierkegaard and the Search for Self-Knowledge’, European Journal of Philosophy 21: 525549.Google Scholar
Weston, M. (1999), ‘Evading the Issue: The Strategy of Kierkegaard’s Postscript ’, Philosophical Investigations 22: 3564.Google Scholar