Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-7cvxr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-27T19:33:21.744Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Introduction to Part 1 of the Themed Issue, ‘Racism and Colonialism in Hegel's Philosophy’: Rationale and Topics

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 April 2024

Daniel James
Affiliation:
Heinrich Heine Universität Düsseldorf, Germany [email protected]
Franz Knappik
Affiliation:
Universitetet i Bergen, Norway [email protected]

Extract

It is increasingly realized today that Western modernity has not only promoted progressive ideals such as scientific thought, human rights and democratic political systems. Its history is also marked by a much darker side, one of brutal conquest, biological and cultural destruction, enslavement and exploitation of non-European peoples in the context of European colonialism. This dark side of Western modernity was legitimized by pro-colonial ideologies of property, war, civilization, progress and race. Such ideologies emerged in areas like jurisprudence and philosophy since the 16th century, often building on views from classical antiquity (Pagden 1995). They shaped academic paradigms such as ‘scientific racism’, colonial anthropology and Orientalism in the 19th and early 20th centuries, and in many ways continue to influence contemporary societies and their academic practices.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Hegel Society of Great Britain

It is increasingly realized today that Western modernity has not only promoted progressive ideals such as scientific thought, human rights and democratic political systems. Its history is also marked by a much darker side, one of brutal conquest, biological and cultural destruction, enslavement and exploitation of non-European peoples in the context of European colonialism. This dark side of Western modernity was legitimized by pro-colonial ideologies of property, war, civilization, progress and race. Such ideologies emerged in areas like jurisprudence and philosophy since the 16th century, often building on views from classical antiquity (Pagden Reference Pagden1995). They shaped academic paradigms such as ‘scientific racism’, colonial anthropology and Orientalism in the 19th and early 20th centuries, and in many ways continue to influence contemporary societies and their academic practices.

Recognizing this dark side, several scholars have turned a critical eye to the works of Western canonical thinkers such as Locke, Hume, Kant and Marx (to name but a few: Bernasconi Reference Bernasconi2003; Sala-Molins Reference Sala-Molins2006; Arneil Reference Arneil2007; Smith Reference Smith2017; Bhambra and Holmwood Reference Bhambra and Holmwood2021; Lu-Adler Reference Lu-Adler2023, and many of the contributions in Valls Reference Valls2005; Muthu Reference Muthu2012; Dhawan Reference Dhawan2014; Flikschuh and Ypi Reference Flikschuh and Ypi2014). They have examined how these thinkers’ views on race and colonialism have shaped, and been shaped by, debates about the racial and colonial aspects of modernity. They have also explored how these views in turn related to other views held by such thinkers—not least on issues such as universal rights or the critique of domination. This approach has not only led to calls for a more ambivalent collective memory of these philosophers, one that does not shy away from confronting their troubling views of non-European peoples. It also raises questions about how contemporary philosophers can engage with these historical figures without perpetuating their racist and pro-colonial baggage.

Hegel presents a fascinating case for such research, for several reasons. First, he is an eminently systematic thinker, and it can be argued that his views on issues such as the alleged mental deficits of non-European peoples (cf., with further literature, de Laurentiis Reference De Laurentiis2021; James and Knappik Reference James and Knappik2023), the contemporary political debate on transatlantic slavery, or British rule in India and Spanish rule in Latin America (cf. James and Knappik MS) are carefully integrated into his philosophical account of reality. For example, Hegel himself explicitly links his partial legitimation of transatlantic slavery—as an institution with a positive and necessary ‘disciplinary’ function, to be abolished only gradually—to themes such as consciousness of freedom, ethical life, his theory of legal personhood and property, and the dialectic of lordship and bondage (cf. Jaarte, this issue; James and Knappik MS). Similarly, Alison Stone (2020) has shown that essential elements in Hegel's conception of freedom pave the way for pro-colonialist attitudes, and we have argued elsewhere that Hegel's hierarchical theory of race is closely linked to his more general views on scientific classifications and their metaphysical underpinnings (James and Knappik Reference James and Knappik2023). These systematic entanglements raise pressing questions: how are other, seemingly more emancipatory parts of his system affected by his views on race, colonialism and transatlantic slavery, and to what extent can post- and neo-Hegelian critical theory disentangle Hegelian insights from these connections, or revise them in ways that can ‘sav[e] Hegel from himself’ (Stone Reference Stone2020)?

Second, as part of his global intellectual influence, Hegel has left various strands of legacy that themselves speak directly to issues of race and colonialism. On the one hand, there are strands that draw on the racist and pro-colonial aspects of Hegel's thought. For example, Park (Reference Park2013) has argued that Hegel's racially motivated exclusion of Africa and Asia from the history of philosophy played an important role in defining the modern, exclusionary canon in the historiography of philosophy. Hegel's equally racist exclusion of Africa from world history (see Tibebu Reference Tibebu2011) has subsequently become an influential racist trope, prominently invoked as recently as 2007 by the then French President Sarkozy in a notorious speech in Dakar. Hoffheimer (1993) has pointed out that in 1860, on the eve of the American Civil War, the Southern congressman Lucius Lamar quoted extensively from Hegel's Lectures on the History of Philosophy in defence of slavery. Applying Hegel's views on organic political unity to the level of international relations, several British Idealists developed a neo-Hegelian interpretation of the British Empire that would influence the creation of the League of Nations after the First World War (James and Knappik MS).

On the other hand, Hegel's philosophy has also served as an important philosophical inspiration for thinkers who represent, in Enrique Dussel's term, the ‘underside of modernity’ (Dussel Reference Dussel and Mendieta1996)—for thinkers who themselves belong to formerly colonized and enslaved groups, and who have developed philosophical critiques of colonialism and racism, as well as accounts of decolonial and abolitionist struggles. Frantz Fanon's seminal work Black Skin, White Masks engages Hegel's dialectic of domination and subjugation through the lens of Kojève's influential interpretation. This exploration, particularly in the context of slavery and its abolition in the French colonies, has attracted considerable exegetical interest (for a recent review, see Hogan Reference Hogan2023). Fanon's mentor, Aimé Césaire, uses Hegel's concept of ‘concrete universality’ as a model for conceptualising ‘négritude’ and, by extension, decolonization. Similarly, the postcolonial philosophy and poetics of their fellow Martinican, Éduoard Glissant, is deeply informed by a sustained engagement with Hegelian thought (Mascat Reference Mascat and Dhawan2014). Another Caribbean thinker, C. L. R. James, wrote a commentary on Hegel's Science of Logic to develop a theory of revolution, which he later applied retrospectively to his own account of the Haitian Revolution and to contemporary decolonial struggles (Renault Reference Renault2016; Ilieva, this issue). In the US, too, thinkers such as Martin Luther King, Jr. (Yonover MS) and Angela Davis (Renault Reference Renault2021; Reference James, Knappik, Congdon and KhuranaJames and Knappik forthcoming) have drawn on Hegel to theorize black struggles and liberation.

This themed issue is the first collection to bring together research on these topics. The articles presented shed new light on all the above aspects—the nature and systematic role of Hegel's views on race and colonialism, as well as Hegel's legacy, both pro-colonial and anti-colonial. (A bibliography of previous research on these topics can be found at hegelantikolonial.wordpress.com/bibliography.) We are glad that this issue has attracted contributions from a wide range of academic and geographical backgrounds, including both established and emerging scholars, and authors from within and outside the Anglosphere. (To facilitate the latter, we have allowed submissions in several languages and assisted with translations into English.) We are confident that the contributions collected here will stimulate further debate and research in this rich area of inquiry. The themed issue consists of two journal issues; the next issue will contain the second part of our editorial introduction, in which we discuss some common objections to such research and formulate questions for future investigation.

References

Arneil, B. (2007), John Locke and America: The Defence of English Colonialism. Oxford/New York: Clarendon.Google Scholar
Bernasconi, R. (2003), ‘Will the Real Kant Please Stand Up: The Challenge of Enlightenment Racism to the Study of the History of Philosophy’, Radical Philosophy 117 https://www.radicalphilosophy.com/article/will-the-real-kant-please-stand-up.Google Scholar
Bhambra, G. and Holmwood, J. (2021), Colonialism and Modern Social Theory. Cambridge: Polity.Google Scholar
De Laurentiis, A. (2021), Hegel's Anthropology: Life, Psyche, and Second Nature. Evanston IL: Northwestern University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dhawan, N. (ed.) (2014), Decolonizing Enlightenment. Transnational Justice, Human Rights and Democracy in a Postcolonial World. Opladen/Berlin/Toronto: Barbara Budrich.Google Scholar
Dussel, E. (1996), The Underside of Modernity: Apel, Ricoeur, Rorty, Taylor, and the Philosophy of Liberation, trans. Mendieta, E.. Atlantic Highlands NJ: Humanities Press.Google Scholar
Flikschuh, K. and Ypi, L. (eds.) (2014), Kant and Colonialism: Historical and Critical Perspectives. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hoffheimer, M. (1993), ‘Does Hegel Justify Slavery?The Owl of Minerva 25:1: 118–19.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hogan, B. (2023), ‘Reading Fanon on Hegel’, Philosophy Compass 18:8: e12939.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
James, D. and Knappik, K. (2023), ‘Exploring the Metaphysics of Hegel's Racism: The Teleology of the “Concept” and the Taxonomy of Races’, Hegel Bulletin 44:1: 99126.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
James, D. and Knappik, F. (forthcoming), ‘G. W. F. Hegel, Frantz Fanon, and Angela Davis on Recognition, Slavery, and Liberation’, in Congdon, M. and Khurana, T. (eds.), The Philosophy of Recognition: Expanded Perspectives on a Fundamental Concept. London/New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
James, D. and Knappik, K. (MS), Hegel and Colonialism.Google Scholar
Lu-Adler, H. (2023), Kant, Race, and Racism: Views from Somewhere. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mascat, J. (2014), ‘Hegel and the Black Atlantic: Universalism, Humanism, and Relation’, in Dhawan, N. (ed.) Decolonizing Enlightenment. Transnational Justice, Human Rights and Democracy in a Postcolonial World. Opladen/Berlin/Toronto: Barbara Budrich.Google Scholar
Muthu, S. (ed). (2012), Empire and Modern Political Thought. Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pagden, A. (1995), Lords of All the World. Ideologies of Empire in Spain, Britain and France c.1500-c.1800. New Haven/London: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Park, P. (2013), Africa, Asia, and the History of Philosophy. Racism in the Formation of the Philosophical Canon, 1780–1830. Albany NY: State University of New York Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Renault, M. (2016), ‘Decolonizing Revolution with C. L. R. James: or, What is to Be Done with Eurocentrism?Radical Philosophy 199: 3545. https://www.radicalphilosophy.com/article/decolonizing-revolution-with-c-l-r-james.Google Scholar
Renault, M. (2021), ‘Counter-Violence, a “Hegelian” Myth: Minor Variations on the Master-Slave Dialectic’, Radical Philosophy 210: 2132. https://www.radicalphilosophy.com/article/counter-violence-a-hegelian-mythGoogle Scholar
Sala-Molins, L. (2006), Dark Side of the Light: Slavery and the French Enlightenment. Minneapolis: University Of Minnesota Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, J. (2017), Nature, Human Nature, and Human Difference: Race in Early Modern Philosophy. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Stone, A. (2020), ‘Hegel and Colonialism’, Hegel Bulletin 41:2: 247–70.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tibebu, T. (2011), Hegel and the Third World. The Making of Eurocentrism in World History. Syracuse NY: Syracuse University Press.Google Scholar
Valls, A., ed. (2005), Race and Racism in Modern Philosophy. Ithaca NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Yonover, J. (MS), ‘King and Hegel on History and Contradiction’.Google Scholar