Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-q99xh Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-28T11:25:29.306Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Hegel on the Productivity of Action: Metaphysical Questions, Non-Metaphysical Answers, and Metaphysical Answers

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  22 July 2019

Edgar Maraguat*
Affiliation:
University of Valencia, [email protected]
Get access

Abstract

Charles Taylor claims that not only Kant, but also successors of Kant such as Fichte and Hegel, advocate a primitive concept of action, namely, a basic, irreducible, indispensable concept allegedly essential to our self-understanding. This paper shows how philosophers like Robert Brandom agree with Taylor explicitly with regard to Hegel, and attribute to him transcendental non-metaphysical arguments in support of such a concept. It then proceeds to challenge this attribution (both of the concept and the type of argument), offering a brief presentation of an alternative non-transcendental metaphysical approach to the Hegelian idea of giving actuality to a concept (or end) through a productive activity.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © The Hegel Society of Great Britain, 2019 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Anscombe, G. E. M. (1957), Intention. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Brandom, R. (1979), ‘Freedom and Constraint by Norms’, American Philosophical Quarterly 16:3: 187–96.Google Scholar
Brandom, R. (1994), Making It Explicit: Reasoning, Representing, and Discursive Commitment. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Brandom, R. (2009), Reason in Philosophy: Animating Ideas. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press.10.4159/9780674053618Google Scholar
Brandom, R. (2010), ‘Response to Rödl’, in Weiss, B. and Wanderer, J. (eds.), Reading Brandom: On Making It Explicit. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Brandom, R. (2019), A Spirit of Trust: A Reading of Hegel's Phenomenology. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press.10.2307/j.ctvfjczmkGoogle Scholar
Fichte, J. G. (1970), ‘Zweite Einleitung in die Wissenschaftslehre, für Leser, die schon ein philosophisches System haben’ in Gesamtausgabe der Bayerischen Akademie der Wissenschaften, vol. I/4. Stuttgart: Frommann-Holzboog.Google Scholar
Gardner, S. (2007), ‘The Status of the Wissenschaftslehre: Transcendental and Ontological Grounds in Fichte’, Internationales Jahrbuch des Deutschen Idealismus 5: 90125.Google Scholar
Henrich, D. (1982), Selbstverhältinisse. Ditzingen: Reclam.Google Scholar
Kreines, J. (2008), ‘The Logic of Life: Hegel's Philosophical Defense of Teleological Explanation of Living Beings’, in Beiser, F. (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Hegel and Nineteenth-Century Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Knowles, D. (2010), ‘Hegel on Actions, Reasons, and Causes’, in Laitinen, A. and Sandis, C. (eds.), Hegel on Action. Basingstoke: Palgrave-Macmillan.Google Scholar
McDowell, J. (2009), ‘Towards a Reading of Hegel on Action in the ‘Reason’ Chapter of the Phenomenology‘, in Having the World in View. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Nagel, T. (1986), The View from Nowhere. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Pippin, R. (2008), Hegel's Practical Philosophy: Rational Agency as Ethical Life. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9780511808005Google Scholar
Quante, M. (2004), Hegel's Concept of Action, trans. Moyar, D.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9780511498299Google Scholar
Sellars, W. (1963), ‘Philosophy and the Scientific Image of Man’, in Science, Perception and Reality. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Strawson, P. F (1985), Skepticism and Naturalism: Some Varieties. The Woodbridge Lectures 1983. New York: Columbia University Press.10.7312/stra92820Google Scholar
Taylor, Ch. (1979), ‘The Validity of Transcendental Arguments’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 79:1: 151–66.10.1093/aristotelian/79.1.151Google Scholar
Taylor, C. (1983), ‘Hegel and the Philosophy of Action’, in Stepelevich, L. S. and Lamb, D. (eds.), Hegel's Philosophy of Action. Atlantic Highlands: Humanities Press.Google Scholar
Yeomans, C. (2012), Freedom and Reflection: Hegel and the Logic of Agency. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. (1921), Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, trans. Ogden, C. K.. London: Kegan Paul.Google Scholar