Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-jn8rn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-29T18:50:35.849Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Hegel on the Nature of Scepticism

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  22 April 2013

Dietmar H. Heidemann*
Affiliation:
University of Luxembourg, [email protected]
Get access

Abstract

In the Encyclopaedia Logic, Hegel states that ‘philosophy … contains the sceptical as a moment within itself — specifically as the dialectical moment’ (§81, Addition 2), and that ‘scepticism’ as ‘the dialectical moment itself is an essential one in the affirmative Science’ (§78). On the one hand, the connection between scepticism and dialectic is obvious. Hegel claims that scepticism is a problem that cannot be just removed from the philosophical agenda by knock-down anti-sceptical arguments. Scepticism intrinsically belongs to philosophical thinking; that is to say, it plays a constructive role in philosophical thinking. On the other hand, scepticism has to be construed as the view according to which we cannot know whether our beliefs are true, i.e., scepticism plays a destructive role in philosophy no matter what. It is particularly this role that clashes with Hegel's claim of having established a philosophical system of true cognition of the entirety of reality. In the following I argue that for Hegel the constructive and the destructive role of scepticism are reconcilable. I specifically argue that it is dialectic that makes both consistent since scepticism is a constitutive element of dialectic.

In order to show in what sense scepticism is an intrinsic feature of dialectic I begin by sketching Hegel's early view of scepticism specifically with respect to logic and metaphysics. The young Hegel construes logic as a philosophical method of human cognition that inevitably results in ‘sceptical’ consequences in that it illustrates the finiteness of human understanding. By doing so, logic not only nullifies finite understanding but also introduces to metaphysics, i.e., the true philosophical science of the absolute.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Hegel Society of Great Britain 2011

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Breazeale, D. (2001), ‘Fichte's Conception of Philosophy as a “Pragmatic History of the Human Mind” and the Contribution of Kant, Platner, and Maimon’, Journal of the History of Ideas 62: 685703.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Claesges, U. (1981), Darstellung des erscheinenden Wissens. Systematische Einleitung in Hegels Phänomenologie des Geistes. Bonn: Bouvier (Hegel-Studien Beiheft 21).Google Scholar
Düsing, K. (ed.) (1988), Schellings und Hegels erste absolute Metaphysik (1801-1802).Zusammenfassende Vorlesungsnachschriften von I. P. V. Troxler Köln: Dinter.Google Scholar
Düsing, K. (1993), ‘Hegels Phänomenologie und die idealistische Geschichte des Selbstbewußtseins’, Hegel-Studien 28: 103126.Google Scholar
Düsing, K. (1995), Das Problem der Subjektivität in Hegels Logik. Systematische und entwicklungsgeschichtliche Untersuchungen zum Prinzip des Idealismus und zur Dialektik (Third edition). Bonn: Bouvier (Hegel-Studien Beiheft 15).Google Scholar
Forster, M. N. (1989), Hegel and Scepticism. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hegel, G. W. F. (2000), ‘On the Relation between Scepticism and Philosophy. Exposition of his Different Modifications and Comparison of the Latest Form with the Ancient One’. Trans. Harris, H. S., in di Giovanni, G. and Harris, H. S. (eds.), Between Kant and Hegel. Texts in the Development Of Post-Kantian Idealism. Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
Hegel, G. W. F. (‘18301991), The Encyclopaedia Logic. Part I of the Encyclopaedia of Philosophical Sciences with Zusätze. Trans. Gerates, T. F., Suchting, W. A., and Harris, H. S.. Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
Hegel, G. W. F. (1977), Phenomenology of Spirit. Trans Miller, A. V.. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hegel, G. W. F. (1971), ‘Fragment of a System’. Trans. Knox, T. M. and Kroner, R. in Early Theological Writings. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.Google Scholar
Hegel, G. W. F. (1970ff.), Theorie-Werk-Ausgabe, ed. Moldenhauer, E. and Michel, K. M., vols. 1–20. Frankfurt/M.: Suhrkamp.Google Scholar
Heidemann, D. H. (2008), ‘Substance, Subject, System. The justification of science and the history of self-consciousness in Hegel's Phenomenology of Spirit’, in Moyar, D. and Quante, M. (eds.), Hegel's Phenomenology of Spirit. A Critical Guide. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 120.Google Scholar
Heidemann, D. H. (2007), Der Begriff des Skeptisismus. Seine systematischen Formen, die pyrrhonische Skepsis und Hegels Herausforderung. Berlin and New York: De Gruyter.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hyppolite, J. (1956), Genèse et structure de la Phénoménologie de l'Esprit. Paris: Aubier.Google Scholar
Kondylis, P. (1979), Die Entstehung der Dialektik. Eine Analyse der geistigen Entwicklung von Hölderlin, Schelling und Hegel bis 1802. Stuttgart: Klett-Cotta.Google Scholar
Lukács, G. (‘19481973), Der junge Hegel (vol. II). Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.Google Scholar
Marx, W. (1981), Hegels Phänomenologie des Geistes. Die Bestimmung ihrer Idee in ’Vorrede' und ’Einleitung'. Zweite Auflage. Frankfurt: Klostermann.Google Scholar
Röttges, H. (1987), Dialektik und Skeptisismus. Die Rolle des Skeptisismus für Genese, Selbstverständnis und Kritik der Dialektik. Frankfurt: Athenäum.Google Scholar
Sextus Empiricus (1933), Outlines of Pyrrhonism. Trans. Bury, R. G.. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar