Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-dzt6s Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-28T11:54:25.342Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Hegel, Humility, and the Possibility of Intrinsic Properties1

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  22 April 2013

Jonathan L. Shaheen*
Affiliation:
University of Michigan, [email protected]
Get access

Abstract

Rae Langton (1998) offers a non-idealist interpretation of Kantian things in themselves according to which we have no knowledge of things in themselves – the intrinsic nature of things – just because our epistemic access to things is via their relational, non-intrinsic properties. Whatever the merits of her account as an interpretation of Kant's metaphysics, its plausibility presupposes the coherence of her notion of intrinsic properties. According to the account of intrinsic properties Langton uses, as we will see, there are only intrinsic properties if certain worlds are possible. Allais (2006) attacks one half of the modal intuitions on which Langton relies, but is adequately rebutted by Langton (2006). This paper discusses another, far more radical critique of the other half of the modal intuitions underlying Langton's account of intrinsic properties, intuitions which are also the basis of Langton and Lewis' (1998) account of the same. The account of intrinsicness under fire here depends on the possibility of objects existing alone in worlds in which no other objects (not counting their parts) exist. But according to Hegel's Logik, such worlds are simply not possible. To develop this critique, we cast a broad net by linking Langton (1998) with Lewis (2009) and Langton and Lewis (1998), and then consider (in a necessarily limited fashion) claims from the 1832, Lehre vom Sein in Hegel's Wissenschaft der Logik, which we consult in the edition of Hegel (2008). The primary aim of this paper is to offer a clear model of the modal error which Hegel purports to identify, and to show its application to Langton's work.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Hegel Society of Great Britain 2011

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

1

This article is a lightly revised version of a paper presented at the 2010 joint conference of the Hegel Society of Great Britain and the UK Kant Society. I am grateful to the audience at that conference for their many useful suggestions, only a fraction of which I have been able to incorporate here. Thanks are also due to Dennis Schulting, who graciously repeated much of the material on Hegel's Faith and Knowledge-era theory of judgement until I began to understand it, and Stefan Pliquett, who patiently denied that I had uncovered an adequate account of Hegel?s derivation of Other long enough for me finally to do so, whenever he wasn't busy answering questions about how to translate untranslatable bits of German. I am unsure whether they would accept the accounts as presently written, but if anyone does, it is quite a bit to their credit.

References

Allais, L. (2006), [Intrinsic Natures: A Critique of Langton on Kant], Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 73(1):143169.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Comesaña, J. (2006), [Could There Be Exactly Two Things?], forthcoming in Synthese, available at http://philosophy.wisc.edu/comesana/2things.pdf.Google Scholar
Fine, K. (1994), [Essence and modality], Philosophical Perspectives 8:116.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Guyer, P. (1993), [Thought and being: Hegel]s critique of Kant]s theoretical Philosophy] in Beiser, F. C. (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Hegel. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hanna, R. (2009), [Kant's theory of judgement] in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2009 edition). Available at http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2009/entries/kant-judgement Google Scholar
Hegel, G. W. F. (1989), Hegel's Science of Logic. Trans. Miller, A. V.. Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books.Google Scholar
Hegel, G. W. F. (2008), Wissenschaft der Logik: Die Lehre vom Sein (1832) (2nd edition). Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag.Google Scholar
Henrich, D. (1974), [Formen der Negation in Hegels Logik] in Beyer, W. R. (ed.), Hegel-Jahrbuch 1974. Köln: Pahl-Rugenstein Verlag.Google Scholar
Houlgate, S. (2006), The Opening of Hegel's Logic: From Being to Infinity, West Lafayette, IN: Purdue University Press.Google Scholar
Kant, I. (1998), Critique of Pure Reason. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kment, B. (2006), [Counterfactuals and the Analysis of Necessity], Philosophical Perspectives 20:1:237302.10.1111/j.1520-8583.2006.00108.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Langton, R. (1998), Kantian Humility. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Langton, R. (2004), [Elusive knowledge of things in themselves], Australasian Journal of Philosophy 82(1):129136.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Langton, R. (2006), [Kant's Phenomena: Extrinsic or Relational Properties? A Reply to Allais], Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 73(1):170185.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Langton, R. (2007), [Objective and Unconditioned Value], Philosophical Review 116(2):157185.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, D. (1973), Counterfactuals. Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. (1983a), [Extrinsic Properties] in Papers in Metaphysics and Epistemology: Volume 2. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. (1983b), [New Work for a Theory of Universals], in Papers in Metaphysics and Epistemology: Volume 2. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. (1986), On the Plurality of Worlds. Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. (1996), [Elusive Knowledge] in Papers in Metaphysics and Epistemology: Volume 2. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. (2009), [Ramseyan Humility] in Braddon-Mitchell, D. and Nola, R. (eds.), Conceptual Analysis and Philosophical Naturalism. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. and Langton, R. (1998), [Defining “intrinsic”] in Lewis, D., Papers in Metaphysics and Epistemology: Volume 2. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Lumsden, S. (2003), [Satisfying the Demands of Reason: Hegel]s Conceptualisation of Experience], Topoi 22:4153.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Newlands, S. (2011), [Hegel's Idealist Reading of Spinoza], Philosophy Compass 6(2):100108.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pippin, R. (1989), Hegel's Idealism: The Satisfactions of Self-Consciousness. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Putnam, H. (1987), The Many Faces of Realism. LaSalle IL: Open Court.Google Scholar
Russell, B. (1996), Our Knowledge of the External World. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Teller, P. (1986), [Relational Holism and Quantum Mechanics], British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 37:7181.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Yablo, S. (1998), [Intrinsicness], available at www.mit.edu/~yablo/intrinsicness.html.Google Scholar
Yablo, S. (2004), [Is conceivability a guide to possibility?], updated version of his 1993 paper of the same title in Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 53:142, available at http://www.mit.edu/~yablo/isconposs.pdf 10.2307/2108052CrossRefGoogle Scholar