Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-l7hp2 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-30T15:50:27.181Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Challenge of Political Right

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  22 April 2013

R. D. Winfield*
Affiliation:
University of Georgia, [email protected]

Abstract

Core share and HTML view are not available for this content. However, as you have access to this content, a full PDF is available via the ‘Save PDF’ action button.

For politics to measure up to reason, two requirements have long been acknowledged: first, that the ends of political action be universal, and second, that the pursuit of such universal ends consist in political self-determination, that is, in self-government.

Aristotle set the stage for all further political inquiry by distinguishing political association through the universality of its end or good, while identifying the end of politics with political activity itself, an activity in which citizens rule over one another while presiding over all other associations, which fall under political dominion owing to the particularity of their pursuits. Aristotle joined the universality of politics with the activity of self-rule by recognising political activity to be an end in itself that is also a master end for the sake of which all other conduct is to be pursued. As such, politics was itself the highest good, making ethics possible by overcoming the hegemony of instrumental action, whose every end is devoid of intrinsic value, leaving conduct ultimately pointless (see Aristotle 1984b: Nicomachean Ethics, 1094a18-1094b12).

Two corollary difficulties, however, undermine Aristotle's enterprise. On the one hand, he is unable to give the universal end of political association a non-arbitrary content. Politics may claim universality by being both an end in itself and a master end, but this is just a recipe for ‘might makes right’, where any prevailing rule would be identical with the highest good. Appeal to a distinctly human function or to forms of rule that pursue the common good rather than the particular interests of some ruler can provide no remedy.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Hegel Society of Great Britain 2012

References

Aristotle, (1984a), De Anima, in The Complete Works of Aristotle, Volume I, ed. Barnes, J.. Princeton NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Aristotle, (1984b), Nicomachean Ethics, in The Complete Works of Aristotle, Volume II, ed. Barnes, J.. Princeton NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Aristotle, (1984c), Physics, in The Complete Works of Aristotle, Volume I, ed. Barnes, J.. Princeton NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Hayek, F. A. (1960), The Constitution of Liberty. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Hegel, G. W. F. (1991), Elements of the Philosophy of Right, ed. Wood, Allen W., trans. Nisbet, H. B.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Plato, (1997), Republic, in Complete Works, ed. Cooper, John M.. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.Google Scholar
Winfield, R. D. (1988), The Just Economy. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Winfield, R. D. (1995), Law in Civil Society. Lawrence, KS: University Press of Kansas.Google Scholar
Winfield, R. D. (1998), The Just Family. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.Google Scholar
Winfield, R. D. (2005), The Just State: Rethinking Self-Government. Amherst, NY: Humanity Books.Google Scholar